20.07.2013 Views

Phonological Conditions on Affixation

Phonological Conditions on Affixation

Phonological Conditions on Affixation

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>C<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> Affixati<strong>on</strong><br />

by<br />

Mary Elizabeth Paster<br />

B.A. (Ohio State University) 2000<br />

M.A. (University of California, Berkeley) 2002<br />

A dissertati<strong>on</strong> submitted in partial satisfacti<strong>on</strong> of the<br />

requirements for the degree of<br />

Doctor of Philosophy<br />

in<br />

Linguistics<br />

in the<br />

GRADUATE DIVISION<br />

of the<br />

UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, BERKELEY<br />

Committee in charge:<br />

Professor Shar<strong>on</strong> Inkelas, Co-Chair<br />

Professor Andrew Garrett, Co-Chair<br />

Professor Kristin Hans<strong>on</strong><br />

Spring 2006


<str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>C<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> Affixati<strong>on</strong><br />

© 2006<br />

by<br />

Mary Elizabeth Paster


Abstract<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>C<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> Affixati<strong>on</strong><br />

by<br />

Mary Elizabeth Paster<br />

Doctor of Philosophy in Linguistics<br />

University of California, Berkeley<br />

Professor Shar<strong>on</strong> Inkelas and Professor Andrew Garrett, Co-Chairs<br />

This dissertati<strong>on</strong> presents results of a cross-linguistic survey of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy (PCSA). One hundred thirty-seven examples are<br />

discussed, representing 67 languages. Three major generalizati<strong>on</strong>s emerge from the<br />

survey. First, PCSA occurs at the same edge of the stem as the trigger: PCSA in prefixes<br />

is triggered at the left edge of the stem, while PCSA in suffixes is triggered at the right<br />

edge. Sec<strong>on</strong>d, PCSA is sensitive to underlying rather than surface forms. This is<br />

dem<strong>on</strong>strated in several examples where ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes render opaque the<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s determining allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong>. Finally, despite its characterizati<strong>on</strong> in<br />

recent literature, PCSA is not always optimizing. In numerous examples, words are no<br />

more ph<strong>on</strong>ologically well-formed than they would be if there were no allomorphy, or if<br />

the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs were reversed.<br />

The generalizati<strong>on</strong>s arising in this survey distinguish between competing<br />

frameworks for modeling ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong>. The first is the ‘P >> M’<br />

approach, where PCSA is modeled by ranking <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>straints over<br />

Morphological c<strong>on</strong>straints in Optimality Theory. This model predicts that PCSA should<br />

1


e ph<strong>on</strong>ologically optimizing and that allomorphy may be sensitive to ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s anywhere in the word.<br />

In the alternative approach, advocated here, PCSA is modeled by incorporating<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological elements of stems into the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> frames of affixes.<br />

Subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> frames specify the type of stem to which affixes will attach, including<br />

syntactic, morphological, and (crucially) ph<strong>on</strong>ological features of stems. The distributi<strong>on</strong><br />

of suppletive allomorphs results from different requirements imposed by each allomorph<br />

<strong>on</strong> stems. This approach predicts that allomorphy should be sensitive to input rather than<br />

surface ph<strong>on</strong>ological elements and that PCSA should be sensitive <strong>on</strong>ly to elements at the<br />

edge of the stem where the affix attaches. These predicti<strong>on</strong>s are upheld in the survey.<br />

In the introducti<strong>on</strong> and c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>, I situate these findings in the broader c<strong>on</strong>text<br />

of the literature <strong>on</strong> the ph<strong>on</strong>ology-morphology interface. I also c<strong>on</strong>sider predicti<strong>on</strong>s of the<br />

models discussed above for other types of ph<strong>on</strong>ological effects in morphology, showing<br />

that research in those areas c<strong>on</strong>verges with the results presented here.<br />

2


Table of c<strong>on</strong>tents<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>C<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> Affixati<strong>on</strong><br />

Chapter 1. Introducti<strong>on</strong> ........................................................................................... 1<br />

1.1 <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong> ............................................................... 3<br />

1.1.1 The P >> M model ....................................................................................... 6<br />

1.1.1.1 Descripti<strong>on</strong> of the model ....................................................................... 7<br />

1.1.1.2 Predicti<strong>on</strong>s for ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy ...... 8<br />

1.1.2 The subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> model ....................................................................... 11<br />

1.1.2.1 Descripti<strong>on</strong> of the model ....................................................................... 11<br />

1.1.2.2 Predicti<strong>on</strong>s for ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy ...... 12<br />

1.2 <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g>ly c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy .......................................... 16<br />

1.2.1 Previous discussi<strong>on</strong>s .................................................................................... 17<br />

1.2.2 Survey methodology .................................................................................... 22<br />

Chapter 2. Segmentally c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy ................................ 25<br />

2.1 Survey results ..................................................................................................... 25<br />

2.1.1 Allomorphy vs. morphoph<strong>on</strong>ology .............................................................. 27<br />

2.1.2 Examples ...................................................................................................... 31<br />

2.1.2.1 Assimilati<strong>on</strong>/harm<strong>on</strong>y ............................................................................ 31<br />

2.1.2.2 Dissimilati<strong>on</strong>/disharm<strong>on</strong>y ...................................................................... 39<br />

2.1.2.3 Syllable structure optimizati<strong>on</strong> .............................................................. 53<br />

2.1.2.4 Syllable c<strong>on</strong>tact c<strong>on</strong>straint satisfacti<strong>on</strong> .................................................. 72<br />

2.1.2.5 N<strong>on</strong>-optimizati<strong>on</strong> ................................................................................... 76<br />

2.1.2.6 Opaque c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing .............................................................................. 98<br />

2.1.3 Summary ...................................................................................................... 103<br />

2.2 Analysis ............................................................................................................. 104<br />

2.3 C<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> ......................................................................................................... 109<br />

Chapter 3. T<strong>on</strong>e/stress c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy .................................. 111<br />

3.1 Survey results ..................................................................................................... 111<br />

3.1.1 Examples ...................................................................................................... 113<br />

3.1.1.1 Stress effects .......................................................................................... 113<br />

3.1.1.2 Stem allomorphy .................................................................................... 119<br />

3.1.1.3 T<strong>on</strong>e effects ........................................................................................... 126<br />

3.1.1.4 N<strong>on</strong>-optimizati<strong>on</strong> ................................................................................... 131<br />

3.1.2 Summary ...................................................................................................... 135<br />

3.2 Analysis ............................................................................................................. 136<br />

3.3 C<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> ......................................................................................................... 139<br />

Chapter 4. Prosodically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy ................................ 140<br />

4.1 Survey results ..................................................................................................... 140<br />

4.1.1 Examples ...................................................................................................... 142<br />

4.1.1.1 Foot parsing ........................................................................................... 144<br />

4.1.1.2 Minimality ............................................................................................. 159<br />

i


4.1.1.3 N<strong>on</strong>-optimizati<strong>on</strong> ................................................................................... 165<br />

4.1.2 Summary ...................................................................................................... 172<br />

4.2 Historical development of prosodically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy:<br />

The case of Pama-Nyungan ergative suffix allomorphy ................................... 174<br />

4.2.1 Examples ...................................................................................................... 176<br />

4.2.2 Previous discussi<strong>on</strong>s .................................................................................... 196<br />

4.2.3 A history of PN ergative allomorphy ........................................................... 201<br />

4.3 Analysis of prosodically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy ........................... 205<br />

4.3.1 The Output Optimizati<strong>on</strong> approach ............................................................. 205<br />

4.3.2 Survey results revisited ................................................................................ 207<br />

4.3.3 Examples of n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing syllable-counting allomorphy (SCA) ............ 208<br />

4.3.4 Examples of SCA possibly resulting from TETU ....................................... 211<br />

4.3.5 The Subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach .................................................................. 212<br />

4.3.6 Using Subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> to model SCA....................................................... 214<br />

4.3.7 Est<strong>on</strong>ian revisited ......................................................................................... 214<br />

4.3.8 Summary of analysis .................................................................................... 216<br />

4.4 C<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> ......................................................................................................... 217<br />

Chapter 5. Predicti<strong>on</strong>s of the P >> M model .......................................................... 219<br />

5.1 Empty morphs .................................................................................................... 221<br />

5.2 <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g>ly induced morphological gaps ..................................................... 223<br />

5.3 Reduplicati<strong>on</strong> ..................................................................................................... 225<br />

5.4 <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g>ly c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed affix order ............................................................. 227<br />

5.4.1 Predicti<strong>on</strong>s for affix order ............................................................................ 227<br />

5.4.2 Cross-linguistic findings .............................................................................. 229<br />

5.4.3 Pulaar ........................................................................................................... 232<br />

5.4.3.1 S<strong>on</strong>ority-based affix order? .................................................................... 232<br />

5.4.3.1.1 Gombe Fula affix order .................................................................... 233<br />

5.4.3.1.2 A P >> M account of Gombe Fula affix order ................................. 237<br />

5.4.3.1.3 Fuuta Tooro Pulaar (Northeastern Senegal) ..................................... 239<br />

5.4.3.1.4 A scope-template account of Fuuta Tooro affix order ..................... 245<br />

5.4.3.1.5 A scope-based reanalysis of Gombe Fula ........................................ 248<br />

5.5 Infixati<strong>on</strong> ............................................................................................................ 251<br />

5.6 C<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> ......................................................................................................... 254<br />

Chapter 6. C<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> .............................................................................................. 255<br />

6.1 Summary of predicti<strong>on</strong>s ..................................................................................... 256<br />

6.2 Summary of survey results ................................................................................ 258<br />

6.3 Summary of theoretical implicati<strong>on</strong>s ................................................................. 260<br />

6.4 Two types of PCSA? ............ ............................................................................. 264<br />

6.5 M >> P vs. separate comp<strong>on</strong>ents ........................................................................ 269<br />

6.6 Future directi<strong>on</strong>s ................................................................................................ 271<br />

References .................................................................................................................. 274<br />

Appendix: Surveyed languages ............................................................................... 290<br />

ii


List of tables and figures<br />

Figure 1: Map showing locati<strong>on</strong> of examples of ergative allomorphy ....................... 177<br />

Figure 2: Map showing distributi<strong>on</strong> of c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> ergative allomorphy ............... 195<br />

Table 1: Examples of ergative allomorphy ................................................................. 193<br />

Table 2: Examples of locative allomorphy ................................................................. 194<br />

Table 3: Hale’s (1976b) proposed history of PN ergative/locative allomorphy ......... 199<br />

iii


Acknowledgements<br />

I have many people to thank for their various c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong>s to my work. My<br />

studies in linguistics began almost by accident when I was an undergraduate at Ohio<br />

State. I had changed my major several times, but was hooked by an excellent intro<br />

linguistics course with Beth Hume, whose enthusiasm for the subject rubbed off <strong>on</strong> me<br />

from the start. Dave Odden’s ph<strong>on</strong>ology course sealed the deal. Dave taught me how to<br />

do fieldwork and how to do ph<strong>on</strong>ology. He is <strong>on</strong>e of the people I admire and respect<br />

most, and I am deeply appreciative to him for being a great role model.<br />

I would also like to thank my advisors, Shar<strong>on</strong> Inkelas and Andrew Garrett, for<br />

their guidance and support. I cannot thank them enough. Shar<strong>on</strong> has been a w<strong>on</strong>derful<br />

mentor and friend. Invariably, when I have felt at all c<strong>on</strong>fused or discouraged about<br />

something I was working <strong>on</strong>, I have always emerged from meetings with Shar<strong>on</strong> feeling<br />

infinitely better, with clearer thinking and better focus than before. Andrew has also been<br />

an excellent advisor, and in particular I am extremely grateful to him for helping me<br />

through a period of uncertainty early in my graduate career with encouragement and<br />

understanding. Andrew is some<strong>on</strong>e whose standards of intellectual excellence are<br />

sometimes intimidating but always inspiring.<br />

I am also very grateful to Larry Hyman, who is always interesting to talk to and<br />

has influenced my work in many ways. Larry’s obvious passi<strong>on</strong> for his work has been an<br />

inspirati<strong>on</strong> at times when I have felt bogged down in my studies, and I have appreciated<br />

this very much. There are several other faculty members who have been especially<br />

helpful and influential during my time at Berkeley, including Juliette Blevins, John<br />

Ohala, and Ian Maddies<strong>on</strong>; in general, all of the linguistics faculty at Berkeley have been<br />

iv


very supportive. In additi<strong>on</strong>, the linguistics staff members have been tremendously<br />

helpful, especially Belen Flores, to whom I am very grateful, especially for dealing with<br />

the hassles that have g<strong>on</strong>e al<strong>on</strong>g with my finishing from out of town. I have really<br />

appreciated being part of such a friendly and intellectually engaging department.<br />

While at Berkeley, I have had great friends and colleagues to whom I am thankful<br />

for their support and for all the good times. Julie Lars<strong>on</strong> and Suzanne Wilhite have<br />

always been fun and w<strong>on</strong>derfully supportive for me in work and life. They and the other<br />

members of our cohort made all of my classes pleasant and/or interesting. In particular,<br />

Abby Wright has been a loyal and thoughtful friend, and has c<strong>on</strong>tinued to take an interest<br />

in my work even after she left the field. I am also grateful to the many other Berkeley<br />

students who have been my close friends and colleagues, including (but not limited to,<br />

and in no particular order) Alan Yu, Lisa C<strong>on</strong>athan, Jeff Good, Rosemary Beam de<br />

Azc<strong>on</strong>a, Yuni Kim, Teresa McFarland, Lisa Bennett, and Anne Pycha. Thank you for<br />

inspiring and entertaining me. I am also grateful to my partner, Sean Spellman, who has<br />

been patient and supportive throughout the latter stages of my graduate career.<br />

The last porti<strong>on</strong> of my dissertati<strong>on</strong> writing has been c<strong>on</strong>ducted while I have been<br />

teaching at the University of Pittsburgh. I would like to thank the linguistics faculty, staff,<br />

and students at Pitt for making this time enjoyable and interesting for me.<br />

Finally, I would like to thank my parents for their support of my career choice and<br />

my decisi<strong>on</strong> to go away for graduate school. They have always given me whatever I<br />

needed to be successful, in the form of emoti<strong>on</strong>al support, encouragement, and (of<br />

course) m<strong>on</strong>ey. I am truly lucky to have the benefit of their love and support, and I<br />

dedicate my dissertati<strong>on</strong> to them.<br />

v


Chapter 1: Introducti<strong>on</strong><br />

This dissertati<strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>cerns ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> the morphological process<br />

of affixati<strong>on</strong>, focusing <strong>on</strong> cases of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy<br />

(PCSA). An example of PCSA is found in Dja:bugay (Patz 1991), a Pama-Nyungan<br />

language of Australia. As seen in the examples in (1), the genitive suffix in Dja:bugay<br />

has two different forms, -n and -ŋun (Patz 1991: 269).<br />

(1) a. guludu-n ‘dove-GEN’ b. girrgirr-ŋun ‘bush canary-GEN’<br />

gurra:-n ‘dog-GEN’ gaɲal-ŋun ‘goanna-GEN’<br />

djama-n ‘snake-GEN’ bibuy-ŋun ‘child-GEN’<br />

When the stem ends in a vowel, as in (1)a, the -n suffix is used. When the stem ends in a<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant, as in (1)b, the -ŋun suffix is used. What distinguishes this as suppletive<br />

allomorphy is that it is not obvious how any plausible ph<strong>on</strong>ological process could relate<br />

the two allomorphs to a single underlying form, since this would involve the<br />

simultaneous deleti<strong>on</strong> or inserti<strong>on</strong> (depending <strong>on</strong> the analysis) of two segments, [ŋ] and<br />

[u]. We therefore c<strong>on</strong>clude that there are two separate underlying forms that can be used<br />

to mark genitive. However, even though we are not able to write rules or c<strong>on</strong>straints to<br />

derive the allomorphs from a single underlying form, we can n<strong>on</strong>etheless state the<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs in ph<strong>on</strong>ological terms, since the relevant property of the stem<br />

(c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant- vs. vowel-final) is ph<strong>on</strong>ological in nature.<br />

C<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants vs. vowels at stem edges are found to c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> PCSA in many of the<br />

world’s languages (as will be seen in chapter 2), but this is by no means the <strong>on</strong>ly type of<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> that is found. In this dissertati<strong>on</strong>, I describe results of a cross-linguistic survey<br />

that attempts to discover the precise range of possible ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> PCSA,<br />

and I show how these results bear <strong>on</strong> the general questi<strong>on</strong> of how to model ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

1


c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong>. The aims and c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong>s of this dissertati<strong>on</strong> are twofold: to<br />

present a typological overview of PCSA, and to show how these typological results point<br />

us towards a subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>-based model of ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

The dissertati<strong>on</strong> is structured as follows. In the remainder of chapter 1, I provide<br />

some background <strong>on</strong> the study of ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong> and of PCSA. I<br />

describe two competing models that have been advanced to account for PCSA, namely,<br />

the ‘P >> M’ model and a subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>-based model (both to be explained later in<br />

this chapter). In this chapter I give an overview of their respective predicti<strong>on</strong>s for<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong>; these predicti<strong>on</strong>s are discussed in more detail in<br />

later chapters.<br />

Chapters 2-4 present the results of the cross-linguistic survey of PCSA,<br />

generalizati<strong>on</strong>s about the examples and their bearing <strong>on</strong> the choice between theoretical<br />

models, and sample analyses of some representative examples of each type. In each<br />

chapter, it is argued that subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> provides a superior analysis that avoids some<br />

problems of under- and overpredicti<strong>on</strong> that are encountered by P >> M. The examples in<br />

chapter 2 involve c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing by individual segments or their features. Those in chapter<br />

3 are c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by t<strong>on</strong>e or stress. Finally, the examples in chapter 4 are c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by<br />

prosodic factors such as syllable count, mora count, or foot structure. Chapter 4 also<br />

features a detailed discussi<strong>on</strong> of the nature and development of a set of examples found in<br />

the Pama-Nyungan languages of Australia; it is dem<strong>on</strong>strated that a diachr<strong>on</strong>ic<br />

perspective <strong>on</strong> PCSA is instructive in assessing the relative merits of the theoretical<br />

models that are c<strong>on</strong>trasted in this dissertati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

2


In chapter 5, I situate the findings of the present study within the larger c<strong>on</strong>text of<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong>. In that chapter, I lay out the range of predicti<strong>on</strong>s<br />

that are made by the P >> M approach for all aspects of affixati<strong>on</strong>, and where possible, I<br />

compare these predicti<strong>on</strong>s with cross-linguistic survey data. As will be seen, the<br />

predicti<strong>on</strong>s generally do not match up well with the survey data. This provides another<br />

argument against the use of P >> M, and by extensi<strong>on</strong>, an argument in favor of the<br />

alternative, subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>-based approach that I advocate.<br />

Finally, in chapter 6, I c<strong>on</strong>clude by summarizing the typological generalizati<strong>on</strong>s<br />

about PCSA and the implicati<strong>on</strong>s of the survey results for the two competing models. I<br />

c<strong>on</strong>sider (and ultimately reject) a ‘hybrid’ approach that distinguishes two types of PCSA<br />

and uses both the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> and P >> M models, and I c<strong>on</strong>clude with some<br />

further remarks <strong>on</strong> strategies for modeling ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

1.1 <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong><br />

The study of the ph<strong>on</strong>ology-morphology interface has relatively old roots in the<br />

theoretical literature, particularly in the formal analysis of morphologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ology (see especially Kiparsky 1982a, b and Mohanan 1986 <strong>on</strong> Lexical Ph<strong>on</strong>ology).<br />

However, <strong>on</strong>ly within the last decade has there been a push towards the study of<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological effects in morphology, and more specifically, ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong><br />

affixati<strong>on</strong>. This dissertati<strong>on</strong> is intended to c<strong>on</strong>tribute to this previously neglected area of<br />

the literature.<br />

Subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>-based models of affixati<strong>on</strong> have been proposed in various<br />

forms over the course of many years; see, for example, Lieber 1980, Kiparsky 1982b,<br />

Selkirk 1982, Orgun 1996, and Yu 2003. Orgun 1996 makes explicit the idea of<br />

3


incorporating ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s directly into subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> frames, though this<br />

is implicit in earlier versi<strong>on</strong>s of the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach. Thus, there has l<strong>on</strong>g been<br />

a framework available for the analysis of ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong>; I will<br />

refer to this general framework as the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach. The basic idea behind<br />

this approach is that the underlying form of affixes includes specificati<strong>on</strong>s as to the type<br />

of stems to which they will attach. This can include morphological, syntactic, and<br />

semantic informati<strong>on</strong>; crucially, it can also include ph<strong>on</strong>ological properties of the stem. I<br />

will discuss the details of this approach in §1.1.2.<br />

Beginning with the advent of Optimality Theory (OT; McCarthy and Prince<br />

1993a, b; Prince and Smolensky 1993), some researchers have pursued a different<br />

approach to ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong>. From the beginning, McCarthy and<br />

Prince (1993a, b) incorporated into OT the possible ranking schema ‘P >> M’, where P is<br />

a ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint 1 that outranks M, a morphological c<strong>on</strong>straint. McCarthy and<br />

Prince claimed that ‘[i]n all cases of prosodic morphological phenomena, prosodic<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straints dominate morphological <strong>on</strong>es’ (1993b: 154). The details of this approach,<br />

which I will refer to as the ‘P >> M’ approach, will be discussed further in §1.1.1. It is<br />

important to note that despite the fact that McCarthy and Prince proposed ‘P >> M’ from<br />

1<br />

McCarthy and Prince (1993a) use ‘P’ in ‘P >> M’ to refer to prosodic, not<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological, c<strong>on</strong>straints. This implies that the P c<strong>on</strong>straints being referred to might be<br />

restricted to those c<strong>on</strong>cerning elements of the prosodic hierarchy and not to other<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological elements such as features. However, <strong>on</strong>e of McCarthy and Prince’s<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straints in a P >> M analysis does refer to a feature: the CODA-COND c<strong>on</strong>straint in<br />

Axininca Campa (1993a: 122) mandates that coda c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants can <strong>on</strong>ly be nasals<br />

homorganic to a following stop or affricate. Furthermore, even if <strong>on</strong>e wanted to limit P<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straints in the P >> M schema to c<strong>on</strong>straints referring to elements in the prosodic<br />

hierarchy, there would be no principled way of making this restricti<strong>on</strong>. Therefore, when<br />

McCarthy and Prince allow for P >> M in OT, then in principle they allow any<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint to outrank any morphological c<strong>on</strong>straint. Thus, throughout the<br />

dissertati<strong>on</strong> when I refer to ‘P >> M’, ‘P’ is meant to refer to ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints.<br />

4


the very beginning of the OT literature, this ranking schema is not a central tenet of the<br />

theory. It assumes that ph<strong>on</strong>ological and morphological well-formedness are assessed<br />

simultaneously, which is separate from the more basic principle of OT ph<strong>on</strong>ology that<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological well-formedness in all dimensi<strong>on</strong>s is evaluated in parallel by ranked,<br />

violable c<strong>on</strong>straints. Therefore, the arguments that I will make against the P >> M<br />

approach do not c<strong>on</strong>stitute arguments against the independent use of OT in ph<strong>on</strong>ology or<br />

morphology.<br />

Over the last decade, the P >> M approach has become the dominant model for<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong>, but there does not appear to have been any explicit<br />

comparis<strong>on</strong> of P >> M with subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> until relatively recently. Thus, the<br />

widespread acceptance of P >> M has proceeded without much c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong> for the<br />

c<strong>on</strong>sequences of the decisi<strong>on</strong> to use this model as opposed to subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>. One<br />

excepti<strong>on</strong> is Booij 1998. Booij argues in favor of the use of ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints to<br />

account for some types of gaps and allomorph selecti<strong>on</strong>, while pointing out that<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological output c<strong>on</strong>straints are not sufficient to account for allomorphy. Thus, in<br />

Booij’s approach, either P >> M or subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> can be used depending <strong>on</strong> the<br />

properties of the example to be analyzed. Booij's primary argument in favor of using<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints to select allomorphs is that the use of subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> frames<br />

makes the selecti<strong>on</strong> arbitrary and cannot relate the shape of the allomorph to the<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> under which it occurs. For example, Booij argues that a simple statement of the<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong> of Dutch suffixes (‘-s after an unstressed syllable, -en after a stressed<br />

syllable’) ‘...does not explain why this particular selecti<strong>on</strong> principle holds. In terms of<br />

complexity of the grammar, it would make no difference if Dutch were just the other way<br />

5


around, i.e. if -s occurred after stressed syllables, and -en after unstressed <strong>on</strong>es’ (1998:<br />

145). In Booij’s view, P >> M should be used for cases that share this optimizing<br />

character with the Dutch example, while subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> should be used when the<br />

allomorphy is not optimizing. Cases of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy<br />

are thereby split into two types depending <strong>on</strong> where in the grammar the ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> is specified (in subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> frames vs. in ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints).<br />

A more recent and more explicit comparis<strong>on</strong> between the P >> M approach and<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> is made by Yu 2003, a study that focuses <strong>on</strong> patterns of infixati<strong>on</strong> (see<br />

chapter 5, §5.5). Yu (2003) surveys a broad range of languages exhibiting infixati<strong>on</strong>, and<br />

his findings lend support to his model of Generalized Prosodic Subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>, which<br />

is c<strong>on</strong>trasted with the Displacement Theory approach in OT that makes use of the P >> M<br />

schema. In fact, Yu (2003: 108) proposes a universal ranking M >> P in direct<br />

c<strong>on</strong>tradicti<strong>on</strong> to P >> M. My own proposal is somewhat different, in that I claim there is<br />

no ranking relati<strong>on</strong> between P and M c<strong>on</strong>straints; see chapter 6 for discussi<strong>on</strong>.<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong>, I have given some historical background <strong>on</strong> the two approaches to<br />

be c<strong>on</strong>trasted here. In §1.1.1 and §1.1.2, I give more detail regarding the implementati<strong>on</strong><br />

of the P >> M and subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approaches, respectively.<br />

1.1.1 The P >> M model<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong>, I introduce the P >> M model. This is the approach menti<strong>on</strong>ed<br />

above in which ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong> are modeled by ranking<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological (P) c<strong>on</strong>straints over morphological (M) c<strong>on</strong>straints in OT. In §1.1.1.1, I<br />

6


present the details of this model, and in §1.1.1.2, I discuss the predicti<strong>on</strong>s that this model<br />

makes for PCSA.<br />

1.1.1.1 Descripti<strong>on</strong> of the model<br />

As menti<strong>on</strong>ed above, the term ‘P >> M’ refers to the fact that this approach<br />

involves ranking some P c<strong>on</strong>straint over some M c<strong>on</strong>straint, with the result that the<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ology has an effect <strong>on</strong> a morphological process. This c<strong>on</strong>straint ranking schema was<br />

first proposed by McCarthy and Prince (1993a, b). 2 Perhaps the most important evidence<br />

for the P >> M proposal was in the domain of infix placement (to be discussed further in<br />

chapter 5). A classic example of a P >> M analysis of infix placement is the Ulwa<br />

example from McCarthy and Prince (1993a). In Ulwa (Misumalpan, Nicaragua; Hale and<br />

Lacayo Blanco 1989), possessive markers occur immediately after the head foot (main<br />

stress) of the word, as shown below (head feet are in parentheses; examples are from<br />

McCarthy and Prince 1993a: 79, 109-110).<br />

(2) (bas)-ka ‘his/her hair’ (siwa)-ka-nak ‘his/her root’<br />

(su:)-ka-lu ‘his/her dog’ (ki:)-ka ‘his/her st<strong>on</strong>e’<br />

(as)-ka-na ‘his/her clothes’ (sana)-ka ‘his/her deer’<br />

(sapa:)-ka ‘his/her forehead’ (ana:)-ka-la:ka ‘his/her chin’<br />

McCarthy and Prince (1993a: 110) propose a P c<strong>on</strong>straint to account for this<br />

(where Ft' is the head foot), shown below. 3<br />

(3) ALIGN-TO-FOOT (Ulwa): Align([POSS]Af, L, Ft', R)<br />

2 In fact, it was originally claimed that prosodically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed morphology is always<br />

driven by P >> M. McCarthy and Prince assert (1993a: 24) that ‘[f]or morphology to be<br />

prosodic at all within OT, the ranking schema P >> M must be obeyed, in that at least<br />

some ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint must dominate some c<strong>on</strong>straint of the morphology’. A<br />

similar statement is made in McCarthy and Prince 1993b.<br />

3 I assume that a given c<strong>on</strong>straint is a P c<strong>on</strong>straint if it makes reference to a ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

element. This is following McCarthy and Prince: ‘…AFX-TO-FT is a P-c<strong>on</strong>straint, because<br />

it crucially refers to a prosodic noti<strong>on</strong>, the foot…’ (1993b: 114).<br />

7


This c<strong>on</strong>straint requires possessive affixes to occur to the right of the main stress in the<br />

word.<br />

The M c<strong>on</strong>straint given below (McCarthy and Prince 1993a: 111) designates the<br />

possessive affixes as suffixes by aligning them to the right edge of the stem.<br />

(4) ALIGN-IN-STEM: Align ([POSS]Af, R, Stem, R)<br />

This reflects the assumpti<strong>on</strong> that every affix is either a prefix or a suffix, according to the<br />

morpheme-specific Alignment c<strong>on</strong>straint that determines its placement. 4<br />

Finally, the ranking of ALIGN-TO-FOOT (the P c<strong>on</strong>straint) over ALIGN-IN-STEM<br />

(the M c<strong>on</strong>straint) yields the infixati<strong>on</strong> pattern observed in Ulwa, as seen in (5)a<br />

(McCarthy and Prince 1993a: 112) and (5)b.<br />

(5) a. /siwanak, ka/ ALIGN-TO-FOOT ALIGN-IN-STEM siwa,ka,nak<br />

a. (siwa)nak-ka *! ‘his/her root’<br />

b. (siwa)-ka-nak *<br />

/sapa:, ka/ ALIGN-TO-FOOT ALIGN-IN-STEM sapa:-ka<br />

a. (sapa:)-ka ‘his/her forehead’<br />

b. sa-ka-pa: *! *<br />

This has been a brief introducti<strong>on</strong> to <strong>on</strong>e use of the P >> M model. In the following<br />

secti<strong>on</strong>, I discuss predicti<strong>on</strong>s that are made by the P >> M model that refer specifically to<br />

PCSA.<br />

1.1.1.2 Predicti<strong>on</strong>s for ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy<br />

The P >> M approach makes four major predicti<strong>on</strong>s for PCSA, to be discussed<br />

here. The overall results of the survey with respect to these predicti<strong>on</strong>s are summarized in<br />

4 See Yu (2003) for an argument against this assumpti<strong>on</strong>, based <strong>on</strong> the existence of ‘true<br />

infixes’, which always surface as infixes, and never as prefixes or suffixes.<br />

8


chapter 6, §6.3. Bey<strong>on</strong>d these, more detailed predicti<strong>on</strong>s are made for specific types of<br />

PCSA; these are discussed in chapters 2-4, each of which deals with PCSA c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed<br />

by a different type of ph<strong>on</strong>ological element.<br />

The first major predicti<strong>on</strong> of P >> M for PCSA is that this phenomen<strong>on</strong> results<br />

from preexisting well-formedness c<strong>on</strong>straints. This means that usually, the c<strong>on</strong>straints<br />

used for allomorph selecti<strong>on</strong> in an analysis of PCSA should be motivated elsewhere. This<br />

may mean that the relevant P c<strong>on</strong>straint is an active c<strong>on</strong>straint in the language with<br />

effects manifested in areas of the grammar other than the allomorphy being analyzed.<br />

Alternatively, PCSA could result from the Emergence of the Unmarked (TETU;<br />

McCarthy and Prince 1994). This means that the relevant P c<strong>on</strong>straint would not have to<br />

be motivated in the particular language being analyzed, but it should be a c<strong>on</strong>straint that<br />

is well-motivated in other languages, so that it may be c<strong>on</strong>sidered a universal c<strong>on</strong>straint.<br />

A sec<strong>on</strong>d predicti<strong>on</strong> of P >> M is that PCSA should be sensitive to ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

elements in surface forms, not in underlying forms. This predicti<strong>on</strong> follows from the fact<br />

that c<strong>on</strong>straints in OT generally refer to surface well-formedness. It would be<br />

c<strong>on</strong>tradicted by examples where allomorphy is clearly sensitive to underlying<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological elements, and where the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> PCSA are rendered opaque by a<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological process. 5<br />

A third predicti<strong>on</strong> is that, in P >> M, ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> PCSA are<br />

expected to come from either the ‘inside’ or the ‘outside’ (referring to elements closer to<br />

or farther from the root, respectively). This means, for example, that ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

properties of <strong>on</strong>e affix can affect the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs of an affix closer to the<br />

5 In fact, as will be seen in chapters 2-4, there do exist examples of precisely this type,<br />

c<strong>on</strong>tradicting this predicti<strong>on</strong> of P >> M.<br />

9


oot; it also means that affixes can c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> stem allomorphy. This predicti<strong>on</strong> is due to<br />

the fact that standard P >> M analyses do not take morphological c<strong>on</strong>stituency into<br />

account; inputs c<strong>on</strong>sist of unordered morphemes including the root and affixes, and the P<br />

and M c<strong>on</strong>straints establish both the order of affixes and the choice of allomorphs. 6<br />

A final predicti<strong>on</strong> of P >> M for PCSA is that c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> allomorph selecti<strong>on</strong><br />

can be located anywhere in the word. In principle, there is nothing in the P >> M model<br />

that would prevent, e.g., an OCP c<strong>on</strong>straint from driving allomorphy in a prefix that is<br />

sensitive to the stem-final segment, or allomorphy in a suffix that is sensitive to the stem-<br />

initial segment. No feature of the model itself predicts that allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong> must be<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed at the edge of affixati<strong>on</strong>; any such effect must be explained by adjacency<br />

requirements specified in the definiti<strong>on</strong> of each of the relevant P c<strong>on</strong>straints.<br />

The predicti<strong>on</strong>s of P >> M for PCSA, discussed above, are summarized below.<br />

(6) a. PCSA is ‘optimizing’ and analyzable using preexisting P c<strong>on</strong>straints<br />

b. PCSA is sensitive to ph<strong>on</strong>ological elements in surface forms, not underlying<br />

forms<br />

c. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing between stem and affix can be bidirecti<strong>on</strong>al<br />

d. <str<strong>on</strong>g>C<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> allomorph selecti<strong>on</strong> can be located anywhere in the word<br />

These predicti<strong>on</strong>s should be borne in mind when <strong>on</strong>e c<strong>on</strong>siders the examples in chapters<br />

2-4; these predicti<strong>on</strong>s (as well as more specific predicti<strong>on</strong>s made for each type of PCSA)<br />

are stated in each of those chapters for ease of comparis<strong>on</strong> between the attested affects<br />

and those predicted by P >> M. In the following secti<strong>on</strong>, I discuss a competing model, the<br />

6<br />

It should be noted that this predicti<strong>on</strong> would not be made if P >> M were couched in a<br />

versi<strong>on</strong> of OT, such as Stratal OT (SOT; Kiparsky 2000), that respects morphological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>stituency. This is because if words are built from the inside-out in ‘layers’ as in SOT<br />

(and in the pre-OT predecessor to SOT, Lexical Ph<strong>on</strong>ology), then an outer affix will<br />

never be able to c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> allomorphy in an inner affix, since the inner affix will already<br />

have been selected and attached to the stem prior to the attachment of the outer affix.<br />

10


subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> model; as in this secti<strong>on</strong>, I begin by laying out the model, then discuss<br />

the predicti<strong>on</strong>s that it makes for PCSA.<br />

1.1.2 The subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> model<br />

This secti<strong>on</strong> introduces the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach, in which ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong> are modeled by incorporating ph<strong>on</strong>ological aspects of stems<br />

directly into the selecti<strong>on</strong>al requirements of affixes. In §1.1.2.1, I present the details of<br />

this model, and in §1.1.2.2, I discuss the predicti<strong>on</strong>s of subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> for PCSA.<br />

1.1.2.1 Descripti<strong>on</strong> of the model<br />

In the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach, as menti<strong>on</strong>ed above, suppletive allomorphy<br />

results when two or more different affixes with the same meaning have different<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>al requirements, which are selecti<strong>on</strong>al requirements imposed by affixes<br />

<strong>on</strong> stems. In a morphological subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach (Lieber 1980, Kiparsky 1982b,<br />

Selkirk 1982, Orgun 1996, Yu 2003, in press), affixati<strong>on</strong> satisfies missing elements that<br />

are required as specified in the lexical entry for each morpheme. An example of a<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> account will be given below for an example from Tahitian (Polynesian,<br />

French Polynesia; Lazard and Peltzer 2000), which will be discussed again in chapter 2.<br />

In Tahitian, the causative/factitive is marked by ha’a when the root begins with a<br />

labial ((7)a), and fa’a elsewhere ((7)b) (Lazard and Peltzer 2000: 224-225).<br />

(7) a. fiu ‘se lasser’ ha’a-fiu ‘ennuyer, s’ennuyer’<br />

mana’o ‘penser’ ha’a-mana’o ‘se rappeler’<br />

veve ‘pauvre’ ha’a-veve ‘appauvrir’<br />

b. ’amu ‘manger’ fa’a-’amu ‘faire manger, nourrir’<br />

rave ‘faire’ fa’a-rave ‘faire faire’<br />

tai’o ‘lire’ fa’a-tai’o ‘faire lire’<br />

11


In a subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> account, the distributi<strong>on</strong> of ha’a- and fa’a- would result not from<br />

the ranking of a P c<strong>on</strong>straint over an M c<strong>on</strong>straint, but from the different<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>al requirements of the two forms, as shown in c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>s 1 and 2<br />

below.<br />

(8) Tahitian causative c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> #1 Tahitian causative c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> #2<br />

causative verb causative verb<br />

SYNSEM causative SYNSEM causative<br />

PHON ϕ(ha’a, ) PHON ϕ(fa’a, )<br />

causative prefix verb stem causative prefix verb stem<br />

PHON ha’a PHON PHON fa’a PHON <br />

The same c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>s can be schematized alternatively using bracket notati<strong>on</strong>, shown<br />

below.<br />

(9) Tahitian causative c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> #1 Tahitian causative c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> #2<br />

[ha’a- [#C[labial]...]verb stem]causative verb [fa’a- [ ]verb stem]causative verb<br />

Because the ph<strong>on</strong>ological requirements of the ha’a form are more specific than those of<br />

the fa’a form, ha’a is selected when the stem is labial-initial; fa’a is selected in the<br />

‘elsewhere case’.<br />

Thus, the distributi<strong>on</strong> of affixes in the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach is determined<br />

by subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>al requirements. These are properties of each affix, and they<br />

determine the types of stems to which each affix will be allowed to attach.<br />

1.1.2.2 Predicti<strong>on</strong>s for ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy<br />

The subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach makes a number of predicti<strong>on</strong>s for PCSA, several<br />

of which are different from those of the P >> M approach, allowing us to distinguish the<br />

12


two models in terms of how well they match up with the survey results to be presented in<br />

chapters 2-4. In chapter 6 (§6.3), I c<strong>on</strong>trast the two models in terms of the accuracy of<br />

their respective predicti<strong>on</strong>s. As in the discussi<strong>on</strong> of the predicti<strong>on</strong>s of P >> M in §1.1.1.2,<br />

the predicti<strong>on</strong>s to be discussed here are general. In each of chapters 2-4, more specific<br />

predicti<strong>on</strong>s for particular types of PCSA will be discussed where relevant.<br />

One predicti<strong>on</strong> made by the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach is that PCSA is not<br />

necessarily ph<strong>on</strong>ologically optimizing, and that there should exist cases in which no<br />

plausible ph<strong>on</strong>ological well-formedness c<strong>on</strong>straint can be written to account for the<br />

pattern of allomorphy. This is because in the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach, ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straints play no role in determining the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs. The ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong> are simply stated in the lexical entry for each affix, so the<br />

relati<strong>on</strong>ship between the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> allomorphy and the shape of the affix is arbitrary.<br />

It should be stressed that this does not mean that PCSA never has an optimizing<br />

character. To the c<strong>on</strong>trary, it has already been established (prior to the present survey)<br />

that many examples of PCSA look as if they maximize the well-formedness of words.<br />

This is not necessarily problematic for the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach; since PCSA<br />

probably originates in many cases from the loss of a regular rule, it should not be<br />

surprising that many cases appear to be ph<strong>on</strong>ologically optimizing. In this approach it<br />

would be surprising, and problematic, if there were no examples of arbitrary, n<strong>on</strong>-<br />

optimizing examples of PCSA. This is the type of example that would be problematic for<br />

P >> M, since PCSA is driven in that approach by ph<strong>on</strong>ological well-formedness.<br />

13


Therefore, the existence or n<strong>on</strong>-existence of n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing allomorphy is an empirical<br />

questi<strong>on</strong> that bears directly <strong>on</strong> the choice between these competing models. 7<br />

A sec<strong>on</strong>d predicti<strong>on</strong> is that PCSA should be sensitive to ph<strong>on</strong>ological elements in<br />

input forms, rather than surface forms. This is because morphology is assumed to apply<br />

before ph<strong>on</strong>ology, at least at each layer of morphology. Unlike the P >> M approach, the<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach is not based <strong>on</strong> surface well-formedness c<strong>on</strong>straints.<br />

Therefore, the ph<strong>on</strong>ological requirements imposed by affixes <strong>on</strong> stems should involve<br />

input ph<strong>on</strong>ological properties, not properties that are derived by the applicati<strong>on</strong> of later<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes. We therefore predict that there should be some languages in<br />

which the ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong> are rendered opaque by the<br />

operati<strong>on</strong> of a regular ph<strong>on</strong>ological process. This is another predicti<strong>on</strong> that distinguishes<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> from the P >> M approach, since as discussed above, P >> M predicts<br />

that PCSA should be sensitive to surface ph<strong>on</strong>ological properties.<br />

A third predicti<strong>on</strong> of subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> for PCSA is that ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing can come <strong>on</strong>ly from the ‘inside’. This means that the distributi<strong>on</strong> of<br />

allomorphs of a particular affix can <strong>on</strong>ly be c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by ph<strong>on</strong>ological properties of the<br />

‘stem of affixati<strong>on</strong>,’ i.e. those parts of the stem that are already present at the stage of the<br />

derivati<strong>on</strong> in which the affix in questi<strong>on</strong> will be attached. Linear order am<strong>on</strong>g affixes <strong>on</strong><br />

the same side of the stem is usually assumed to corresp<strong>on</strong>d to the order in which affixes<br />

7<br />

In chapters 2-4, I will present several cases of apparently n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing PCSA, which<br />

provide an argument in favor of subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> and against P >> M. The problem in<br />

dealing with such examples is to determine whether a particular pattern of allomorphy is<br />

optimizing or not, since it is impossible to anticipate every ph<strong>on</strong>ological well-formedness<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straint that could possibly be proposed for any language. Therefore, the existence of a<br />

single instance of apparently n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing PCSA would not c<strong>on</strong>stitute a knockout<br />

argument against P >> M in favor of subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>. Instead, <strong>on</strong>e should c<strong>on</strong>sider the<br />

cumulative weight of all of the apparently n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing examples to be discussed.<br />

14


are attached; for example, in a word with multiple suffixes, it is assumed that the leftmost<br />

suffix was attached first, and the rightmost suffix was attached last. Of course, the<br />

possibility of infixes intervening between other affixes prevents this generalizati<strong>on</strong> from<br />

being true <strong>on</strong>e hundred percent of the time. In the usual case, however, there is a<br />

corresp<strong>on</strong>dence between surface linear order and the order of affixati<strong>on</strong>. Therefore, we<br />

predict that the ph<strong>on</strong>ological properties of a particular affix cannot c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> allomorphy<br />

in an affix that occurs closer to the root. This is yet another predicti<strong>on</strong> that is different<br />

from the P >> M model, since the P >> M model allows for both ‘inside-out’ and<br />

‘outside-in’ c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing. The existence of ‘outside-in’ c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing would therefore<br />

provide evidence in favor of the P >> M model and against subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> (or, at least,<br />

against the particular implementati<strong>on</strong> of it assumed here, in which words are built from<br />

the inside-out).<br />

A fourth and final predicti<strong>on</strong> of subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> for PCSA is made when we<br />

incorporate a general principle of grammar that has been proposed to account for other<br />

phenomena but, as will be seen, is quite useful in an analysis of PCSA as well. This is the<br />

Generalized Determinant Focus Adjacency C<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> (GDFAC; Inkelas 1990: 201,<br />

building <strong>on</strong> Poser’s (1985) Determinant Focus Adjacency C<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>). The GDFAC is<br />

given below.<br />

(10) Generalized Determinant Focus Adjacency C<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>: Each ph<strong>on</strong>ologically<br />

c<strong>on</strong>strained element must be adjacent to each c<strong>on</strong>straining element.<br />

If the GDFAC is incorporated into the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach, we predict that affix<br />

allomorphs should occur immediately next to the ph<strong>on</strong>ological elements of stems that<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> their distributi<strong>on</strong>. For instance, prefix allomorphs should be c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by<br />

elements at the left edge of the stem, while suffix allomorphs should be c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by<br />

15


elements at the right edge. This predicti<strong>on</strong>, as with the previous three predicti<strong>on</strong>s,<br />

c<strong>on</strong>stitutes a difference between the P >> M and subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approaches. 8<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong>, we have discussed four predicti<strong>on</strong>s of the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

approach for PCSA, summarized below.<br />

(11) a. PCSA is not always ph<strong>on</strong>ologically optimizing<br />

b. PCSA is sensitive to ph<strong>on</strong>ological elements in underlying/input forms, not surface<br />

forms<br />

c. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> PCSA can come <strong>on</strong>ly from the ‘inside’<br />

d. Affix allomorphs occur adjacent to the ph<strong>on</strong>ological elements of stems that<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> their distributi<strong>on</strong><br />

Each of the predicti<strong>on</strong>s has been c<strong>on</strong>trasted with predicti<strong>on</strong>s of the P >> M approach. We<br />

are now equipped to c<strong>on</strong>sider the results of the cross-linguistic survey of PCSA, since we<br />

have set up some expectati<strong>on</strong>s for the types of examples that should be found under each<br />

of the two competing models. In the following secti<strong>on</strong>, I present some background for the<br />

survey of PCSA, beginning with a discussi<strong>on</strong> of previous discussi<strong>on</strong>s and surveys of<br />

PCSA (§1.2.1), and c<strong>on</strong>cluding the chapter in §1.2.2 with a discussi<strong>on</strong> of the<br />

methodology for the new survey whose results will be reported in this dissertati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

1.2 <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g>ly c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong>, I focus <strong>on</strong> PCSA, first discussing at length some previous<br />

treatments of the phenomen<strong>on</strong> (§1.2.1). I then explain (§1.2.2) the setup and<br />

methodology for the survey of PCSA, whose results will be presented in chapters 2-4.<br />

8<br />

It should be acknowledged that the GDFAC is not a property of the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

model in itself but is rather an assumpti<strong>on</strong> that is made about the nature of<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>. However, it should also be pointed out that while the GDFAC is easily<br />

incorporated into the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach, it cannot be readily implemented in P<br />

>> M since that model does not really involve any ‘ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>strained elements’.<br />

16


1.2.1 Previous discussi<strong>on</strong>s<br />

The first major and explicit discussi<strong>on</strong> of PCSA is in Carstairs 1988. The primary<br />

c<strong>on</strong>cern of Carstairs 1988 is to use examples of PCSA to gain insight into how (if at all)<br />

to distinguish between inflecti<strong>on</strong> and derivati<strong>on</strong>. Thus, the point of the article is not to<br />

document PCSA for its own sake, though Carstairs presents several examples 9 of PCSA<br />

(1988: 70-72) in order to document the existence of the phenomen<strong>on</strong>, which was not well<br />

known at the time. Carstairs discusses the noti<strong>on</strong> that derivati<strong>on</strong>al morphology never<br />

exhibits suppleti<strong>on</strong> because the c<strong>on</strong>cept of suppleti<strong>on</strong> relies <strong>on</strong> the existence of a<br />

paradigm, and derivati<strong>on</strong>al morphology does not involve paradigms (1988: 74). Carstairs<br />

argues against this idea because derivati<strong>on</strong>al morphology does have a paradigmatic<br />

aspect (van Marle 1985, 1986) and because some of the examples that Carstairs cites do<br />

involve suppleti<strong>on</strong> in derivati<strong>on</strong>al morphology. Furthermore, derivati<strong>on</strong>al morphs can<br />

have ph<strong>on</strong>ological restricti<strong>on</strong>s (e.g., English -en can <strong>on</strong>ly attach to adjectives ending in a<br />

certain restricted set of obstruents), so it is unclear why two derivati<strong>on</strong>al morphs with the<br />

same meaning cannot to enter into suppletive relati<strong>on</strong>ships c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by ph<strong>on</strong>ology.<br />

Carstairs makes the generalizati<strong>on</strong> (1988: 75) that most of the examples in his set<br />

involve inflecti<strong>on</strong> rather than derivati<strong>on</strong> 10 . The explanati<strong>on</strong> provided for this fact invokes<br />

the principle of ‘inflecti<strong>on</strong>al parsim<strong>on</strong>y’, which states that for any combinati<strong>on</strong> of<br />

morphosyntactic features that can mark members of a particular word class, each word<br />

9<br />

Fifteen examples are discussed, from ten languages.<br />

10<br />

Of course, the c<strong>on</strong>cept of ‘most’ used here is not very meaningful given the small<br />

sample size (fifteen examples). However, this finding does appear to hold up in the larger<br />

survey to be described in this dissertati<strong>on</strong>. It is difficult to obtain a count of cases of<br />

inflecti<strong>on</strong> vs. derivati<strong>on</strong> since many affixes do not clearly fall into <strong>on</strong>e category or<br />

another, but am<strong>on</strong>g those that do, there are more cases of inflecti<strong>on</strong> than derivati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

17


will have exactly <strong>on</strong>e inflecti<strong>on</strong>al realizati<strong>on</strong>. According to Carstairs (1988: 76), there are<br />

three ways in which a language can resolve a potential violati<strong>on</strong> of parsim<strong>on</strong>y: first, all<br />

but <strong>on</strong>e of the possible realizati<strong>on</strong>s could drop out of use; sec<strong>on</strong>d, all of the realizati<strong>on</strong>s<br />

could be distributed arbitrarily into c<strong>on</strong>jugati<strong>on</strong>s or declensi<strong>on</strong>s; third, all of the<br />

realizati<strong>on</strong>s could be distributed according to some independent principle (whether<br />

semantic, syntactic, morphological, or ph<strong>on</strong>ological). Thus, the development of<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppleti<strong>on</strong> is just <strong>on</strong>e of many ways in which a language can<br />

adhere to the parsim<strong>on</strong>y principle.<br />

Carstairs goes <strong>on</strong> to argue that ‘...a principle of parsim<strong>on</strong>ious coverage does<br />

appear to exercise an influence over not <strong>on</strong>ly inflecti<strong>on</strong>al morphology and syntactic<br />

structure but also certain areas of lexical organisati<strong>on</strong> involving even m<strong>on</strong>omorphemic<br />

items. If this is so, it would be surprising if the principle could not also affect<br />

morphologically complex lexical items, including derived words’ (1988: 79). An example<br />

of the former type of effect in English is pointed out, where animal species have <strong>on</strong>e item<br />

in each of the categories adult male, adult female, and young. According to Carstairs, it is<br />

this type of derivati<strong>on</strong>, which he describes as ‘meaning-driven’ 11 , in which parsim<strong>on</strong>ious<br />

coverage is apparent. Another example is male vs. female titles of ranks of the British<br />

peerage (duke and duchess, etc.). An example of English derivati<strong>on</strong> that is not meaning-<br />

driven is deverbalizati<strong>on</strong> using -i<strong>on</strong>, -al, -ment, -ance, or stress shift. In this type of<br />

derivati<strong>on</strong>, the exact meaning of the noun derived from the verb is not predictable (e.g.,<br />

remit vs. remissi<strong>on</strong>), and we do not find parsim<strong>on</strong>ious coverage: some verbs have<br />

11 Carstairs defines ‘meaning-driven’ morphology as having ‘semantic coherence,<br />

describable in terms of semantic features or comp<strong>on</strong>ents,’ whereas ‘expressi<strong>on</strong>-driven’<br />

morphology exhibits ‘semantic vagueness or unpredictability’ (1988: 88).<br />

18


multiple possible nominal forms (e.g., commissi<strong>on</strong>, commital, commitment). In Carstairs’<br />

view, the fact that <strong>on</strong>ly meaning-driven derivati<strong>on</strong> obeys the principle of parsim<strong>on</strong>ious<br />

coverage accounts for the fact that cases of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppleti<strong>on</strong> are<br />

more often inflecti<strong>on</strong>al than derivati<strong>on</strong>al. The questi<strong>on</strong> is then posed whether we might<br />

find some example of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppleti<strong>on</strong> in a type of meaning-driven<br />

derivati<strong>on</strong>, and Carstairs does present <strong>on</strong>e such case from Dutch, where the distributi<strong>on</strong><br />

of suffixes that create ‘neutral deverbal pers<strong>on</strong>al names’ (e.g., terms meaning ‘drummer,’<br />

‘camper,’ etc.) is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by the stem-final segment(s) (1988: 84). Carstairs<br />

c<strong>on</strong>cludes by suggesting that the c<strong>on</strong>cepts of ‘meaning-driven’ vs. ‘expressi<strong>on</strong>-driven’<br />

morphology may turn out to be more useful than inflecti<strong>on</strong> vs. derivati<strong>on</strong>. Thus, PCSA is<br />

used to make an argument against the distincti<strong>on</strong> between inflecti<strong>on</strong> and derivati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

A sec<strong>on</strong>d important paper dealing with PCSA is Carstairs 1990. This brief article<br />

outlines some implicati<strong>on</strong>s of PCSA for ph<strong>on</strong>ological and morphological theory. One<br />

primary c<strong>on</strong>sequence for ph<strong>on</strong>ology, of course, is that ‘the existence of a ph<strong>on</strong>ologically<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed alternati<strong>on</strong> does not by itself prove the existence of some synchr<strong>on</strong>ic<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological process giving rise to it’ (Carstairs 1990: 19).<br />

Carstairs makes some generalizati<strong>on</strong>s about what types of ph<strong>on</strong>ological factors<br />

can c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> allomorphy. These seem to be based <strong>on</strong> the set of eleven examples that<br />

Carstairs provides (1990: 18). One generalizati<strong>on</strong> is that there are no cases where a<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological characteristic of a word or morph c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s allomorph selecti<strong>on</strong> for a<br />

separate ph<strong>on</strong>ological word. A sec<strong>on</strong>d generalizati<strong>on</strong> is that, as predicted by Lexical<br />

Ph<strong>on</strong>ology, c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing is generally ‘outward’, i.e., involving a root or inner affix<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs of an outer affix. There are some apparent<br />

19


excepti<strong>on</strong>s to this, but Carstairs points out that in each case of apparent 'inward'<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing, the alternants are either ph<strong>on</strong>etically uninterpretable in isolati<strong>on</strong>, or else<br />

they can be analyzed as ‘empty morphs’. 12 Thus, the directi<strong>on</strong> of c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing in PCSA<br />

follows from a layered model of word-building such as Lexical Ph<strong>on</strong>ology.<br />

The first major paper dedicated to PCSA in the OT era was Mester 1994. 13 Mester<br />

provides an analysis of Latin stress, arguing in favor of bimoraic minimality and<br />

maximality in foot structure. Mester’s analysis likely c<strong>on</strong>stitutes the first use of<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints to determine the distributi<strong>on</strong> of suppletive allomorphs, aside<br />

from McCarthy and Prince 1993a, b. Mester uses this approach to account for three<br />

instances of allomorphy in Latin, all of which appear to be c<strong>on</strong>figured in such a way as to<br />

avoid 'trapping' c<strong>on</strong>figurati<strong>on</strong>s in which a syllable is left unfooted due to strict bimoraic<br />

foot minimality and maximality. Further details of Mester’s Latin examples will be<br />

discussed in chapter 4.<br />

Another important c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong> to the literature <strong>on</strong> PCSA was made by Kager<br />

1996. Kager describes a phenomen<strong>on</strong> of ‘syllable-counting allomorphy’ in Est<strong>on</strong>ian,<br />

arguing that this type of allomorphy is a form of output optimizati<strong>on</strong>. Kager argues that<br />

syllable-counting allomorphy reduces to foot-based allomorphy, and that the result is to<br />

maximize foot parsing. As will be discussed in chapter 4, the problem with this view is<br />

12<br />

As will be seen in chapters 2-4, both of the observati<strong>on</strong>s made by Carstairs (1990) are<br />

upheld in a larger survey of PCSA. First, PCSA always occurs within the (ph<strong>on</strong>ological)<br />

word (always between an affix and the stem of attachment, or else between a clitic and its<br />

host); no cases of between-word c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing are found. Sec<strong>on</strong>d, c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing does<br />

appear to be ‘inside-out’, not ‘outside-in’, and the very few cases of apparent ‘outside-in’<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing yield to alternative analyses.<br />

13<br />

In fact, Mester’s analysis is couched in the earlier, similar theory of ‘Harm<strong>on</strong>y-<br />

Theoretic Ph<strong>on</strong>ology’ rather than OT, which was <strong>on</strong>ly beginning to be developed at the<br />

time of publicati<strong>on</strong>. However, the Harm<strong>on</strong>ic approach was also c<strong>on</strong>straint-based, so the<br />

basic insights of Mester’s analysis could easily translate into OT.<br />

20


the assumpti<strong>on</strong> that all syllable-counting allomorphy is optimizing and based <strong>on</strong> foot<br />

structure. This ignores the many cases (to be discussed in §4.1.1.3) where syllable-<br />

counting allomorphy is not optimizing and may not reduce to c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s of footing.<br />

A final important study of PCSA is Carstairs-McCarthy 1998. This article<br />

provides a useful way of looking at PCSA which unifies it with the phenomen<strong>on</strong> of<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed morphological gaps. In Carstairs-McCarthy’s view, both<br />

phenomena result from ph<strong>on</strong>ological restricti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> the distributi<strong>on</strong> of particular affixes.<br />

Different languages react to these gaps in <strong>on</strong>e or more of three ways: (a) unsystematic<br />

filling of the gaps, (b) systematic morphological filling of the gaps, and (c) systematic<br />

syntactic filling of the gaps via periphrasis. Carstairs-McCarthy points out an interesting<br />

asymmetry: in the domain of inflecti<strong>on</strong>, strategies (b) and (c) are used, while in the<br />

domain of derivati<strong>on</strong>, strategy (a) is used. 14 Carstairs-McCarthy relates this (1998: 148)<br />

to ‘the importance of the paradigmatic dimensi<strong>on</strong> in inflecti<strong>on</strong>’, though as discussed<br />

above, Carstairs (1988) points out that paradigms may play a role in certain types of<br />

derivati<strong>on</strong> as well.<br />

As can be seen, the theoretical treatment of PCSA has been relatively sparse,<br />

since the five papers discussed above c<strong>on</strong>stitute the important recent literature <strong>on</strong> the<br />

topic to deal with PCSA cross-linguistically. 15 This is despite the fact that, as pointed out<br />

repeatedly in this literature, PCSA has enormous potential to shed light <strong>on</strong> the nature of<br />

14<br />

Only seven examples are c<strong>on</strong>sidered; in the larger survey of PCSA to be discussed in<br />

chapters 2-4, this generalizati<strong>on</strong> is c<strong>on</strong>tradicted by the existence of many examples of<br />

PCSA in derivati<strong>on</strong>al affixes (though, as pointed out earlier in this secti<strong>on</strong> in the<br />

discussi<strong>on</strong> of Carstairs 1988, the generalizati<strong>on</strong> does seem to hold as a tendency in the<br />

data).<br />

15<br />

There are several other papers that discuss PCSA to varying degrees of depth; see, e.g.,<br />

Mascaró 1996, Tranel 1996a,b, Vaux 2003, B<strong>on</strong>et 2004, B<strong>on</strong>et et al in press, and Bye to<br />

appear.<br />

21


ph<strong>on</strong>ology, morphology, and especially the ph<strong>on</strong>ology-morphology interface. The focus<br />

of most of these earlier works has been <strong>on</strong> using PCSA to answer broader questi<strong>on</strong>s about<br />

morphology (Carstairs 1988), providing c<strong>on</strong>straint-based analyses for it (Mester 1994,<br />

Kager 1996), or explaining why PCSA occurs (Carstairs-McCarthy 1998). Only <strong>on</strong>e<br />

paper, Carstairs 1990, attempts to make serious typological generalizati<strong>on</strong>s about the<br />

phenomen<strong>on</strong>, and that paper relies <strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong>ly eleven examples of PCSA. It should therefore<br />

be clear why a larger cross-linguistic survey of PCSA is desirable. I introduce such a<br />

survey in the following secti<strong>on</strong>, discussing the methodology before presenting the results<br />

of the survey in chapters 2-4.<br />

1.2.2 Survey methodology<br />

In order to determine the precise range of ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s that can<br />

determine suppletive allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong>, and the specific ways in which this<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing can be manifested, a cross-linguistic survey of PCSA was undertaken. The<br />

results of the survey will be reported in chapters 2-4, but it is important here to discuss<br />

the methodology used in the c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of the survey.<br />

The primary problem in c<strong>on</strong>structing a large cross-linguistic survey is that <strong>on</strong>e can<br />

never survey enough languages. Comprehensive grammars have been written for <strong>on</strong>ly a<br />

small fracti<strong>on</strong> of the world’s living languages, and this completely ignores extinct<br />

languages. It is impossible to know what type and amount of bias this introduces into<br />

cross-linguistic surveys. This is especially problematic when making negative<br />

generalizati<strong>on</strong>s of the type ‘No language has property X’.<br />

22


Fortunately, most of the important generalizati<strong>on</strong>s that I draw based <strong>on</strong> the<br />

present survey are positive generalizati<strong>on</strong>s. For example, as will be discussed, I have<br />

found that PCSA can be c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by feet, syllables, moras, stress, t<strong>on</strong>e, segments, or<br />

features. This type of generalizati<strong>on</strong> is much easier to make than a negative<br />

generalizati<strong>on</strong>, since any phenomen<strong>on</strong> for which there are multiple examples from<br />

different language families (as is the case for the generalizati<strong>on</strong> stated above) is clearly an<br />

‘attested’ phenomen<strong>on</strong>, regardless of the sample size.<br />

In some cases, I do make negative generalizati<strong>on</strong>s. One such generalizati<strong>on</strong> is that<br />

based <strong>on</strong> the survey data, it appears that there is no language in which PCSA in an affix is<br />

triggered at the opposite edge of the stem; for example, there is no language where prefix<br />

allomorphy is triggered by the stem-final segment. Of course, this generalizati<strong>on</strong> can be<br />

falsified if another researcher uncovers such an example in future research. In that case, a<br />

good scientific way to proceed would be to discern whether the apparent counterexample<br />

can be interpreted so that it does not directly c<strong>on</strong>tradict the theory that was devised in<br />

order to explain the generalizati<strong>on</strong>; if this proves impossible, then the theory should be<br />

aband<strong>on</strong>ed. In the mean time, my c<strong>on</strong>fidence that the generalizati<strong>on</strong> does reflect some<br />

true fact about human languages (rather than a sampling error) can be increased by my<br />

own deliberate efforts in c<strong>on</strong>structing the survey, which I discuss below.<br />

The best way to avoid making spurious negative generalizati<strong>on</strong>s is to make the<br />

survey as large and broad as possible. I have attempted to do this in a variety of ways.<br />

First, I have scoured several types of sources in my search for examples. About 600<br />

sources were c<strong>on</strong>sulted in total, though of course not all of these yielded examples of<br />

PCSA. Most of the examples to be presented were found by searching through<br />

23


descriptive and teaching grammars <strong>on</strong> the shelves at the UC Berkeley library. I also<br />

became aware of some examples by querying several specialists in ph<strong>on</strong>ology and<br />

morphology. This was complemented by the additi<strong>on</strong> of many examples already<br />

discussed in theoretical literature (mainly in journal articles) and in linguistics textbooks.<br />

Whenever an example was found in <strong>on</strong>e of these sec<strong>on</strong>dary sources, I have attempted to<br />

locate the primary source to c<strong>on</strong>firm the examples and the characterizati<strong>on</strong> of patterns.<br />

The minimal standard for inclusi<strong>on</strong> of a particular example in the survey was that the<br />

shape and distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs must be clear, and examples must be given. In<br />

general, I have used the transcripti<strong>on</strong>al or orthographic c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>s employed in each<br />

source, except where noted. In some instances where examples are neither provided in<br />

the primary descripti<strong>on</strong> nor accessible elsewhere, I have described these cases in<br />

footnotes. In general, I have tried to make the survey as large as possible.<br />

Though I did not deliberately seek out examples from every language family in<br />

creating the database, I did attempt to balance the survey. Throughout the course of the<br />

survey research, I c<strong>on</strong>tinued to take stock of the examples, and whenever it appeared that<br />

a major language family was not well-represented in the survey, I made a particular effort<br />

to obtain grammars of languages in that family. 16 Thus, the survey was not intenti<strong>on</strong>ally<br />

balanced in a systematic way, but the result of the methodology described here seems to<br />

have resulted in a relatively balanced set of examples. The reader may assess this for<br />

him- or herself by c<strong>on</strong>sulting the Appendix, which lists the languages and families from<br />

which I obtained the data to be discussed in the following three chapters.<br />

16<br />

Except where noted, all language family classificati<strong>on</strong>s are from the Ethnologue<br />

(Gord<strong>on</strong> 2005).<br />

24


Chapter 2: Segmentally c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy<br />

In this chapter I present examples and an analysis of suppletive allomorphy<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants and vowels and their features. The ‘P >> M’ ranking schema<br />

discussed in chapter 1, where ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints are ranked ahead of morphological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straints, predicts that any segment or feature anywhere in the word should in principle<br />

be able to c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> the distributi<strong>on</strong> of suppletive allomorphs of affixes or stems for<br />

reas<strong>on</strong>s of output optimizati<strong>on</strong>. The extent to which this predicti<strong>on</strong> is or is not borne out<br />

is discussed in §2.1, where I present examples of segmentally c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy<br />

revealed by a cross-linguistic survey. In §2.2, I give an analysis of representative<br />

examples of this type in terms of subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>, dem<strong>on</strong>strating that such an analysis<br />

is feasible and superior to a P >> M analysis. The chapter is c<strong>on</strong>cluded in §2.3 with a<br />

summary of the findings and the analysis.<br />

2.1 Survey results<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong>, I give examples of suppletive allomorphy c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by segments<br />

and their features. These examples were collected as part of a cross-linguistic survey of<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy (PCSA), described in chapter 1.<br />

Grammars of over 600 languages were surveyed, yielding 137 examples of PCSA in 67<br />

languages. Seventy-two of these cases (from 32 different languages) involve c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing<br />

by c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants or vowels or their features and are discussed in this chapter. The examples<br />

in this chapter are organized according to the effect that the pattern of allomorph<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong> has <strong>on</strong> the word, as follows.<br />

25


§2.1.2.1 discusses cases where allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong> has an assimilatory or<br />

harm<strong>on</strong>izing effect; that is, where the degree of featural agreement between the stem and<br />

affix is higher than if there were no allomorphy or if the allomorphs had a different<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong>. The examples in §2.1.2.2 involve patterns that result in dissimilati<strong>on</strong> or<br />

antiharm<strong>on</strong>y, where the degree of featural agreement between the stem and affix is lower<br />

than if there were no allomorphy or if the allomorphs had a different distributi<strong>on</strong>. In<br />

§2.1.2.3, I discuss examples where the distributi<strong>on</strong> of suppletive allomorphs appears to<br />

improve the overall syllable structure of the word. A related set of examples is discussed<br />

in §2.1.2.4, which describes examples where allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong> appears to relate to<br />

syllable c<strong>on</strong>tact (rather than the shape of individual syllables). In §2.1.2.5, I discuss cases<br />

where the allomorphy has an effect that is n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing. Finally, in §2.1.2.6, I present<br />

examples where ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes render opaque the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> PCSA. As I<br />

discuss, these are especially problematic for the P >> M model.<br />

The organizati<strong>on</strong> of this secti<strong>on</strong> according to the ‘outcome’ of allomorph<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong> may seem to presuppose the truth of the claim inherent in the P >> M<br />

approach, that ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy is ph<strong>on</strong>ologically<br />

optimizing. However, as will be discussed in the summary in §2.1.3, this is far from a<br />

foreg<strong>on</strong>e c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>. As will be discussed, the examples in §2.1.2.5 where the allomorph<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong> is ph<strong>on</strong>ologically n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing are problematic for the claim that PCSA<br />

results in output ph<strong>on</strong>ological optimizati<strong>on</strong>, as are the examples in §2.1.2.6 where PCSA<br />

is shown to be sensitive to ph<strong>on</strong>ological features in the input rather than the output. The<br />

theoretical c<strong>on</strong>sequences of these examples are discussed in §§2.2 and 2.3.<br />

26


Some generalizati<strong>on</strong>s that will emerge in the presentati<strong>on</strong> of examples is as<br />

follows. First, the ph<strong>on</strong>ological element that c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s PCSA is always adjacent to the<br />

locati<strong>on</strong> of attachment of the affix in questi<strong>on</strong>. Prefix distributi<strong>on</strong> is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by<br />

segments and features at the left edge of the stem, while suffix distributi<strong>on</strong> is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed<br />

by segments and features at the right edge. Sec<strong>on</strong>d, a wide range of c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant and vowel<br />

features, as well as the C/V distincti<strong>on</strong> itself, can c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> the distributi<strong>on</strong> of suppletive<br />

allomorphs. Third, a substantial number of examples of PCSA appear to be n<strong>on</strong>-<br />

optimizing, a finding that is not predicted by P >> M and that is, in fact, problematic for<br />

that model. Finally, a related finding is that PCSA seems to be sensitive to ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

elements in input forms, rather than outputs.<br />

2.1.1 Allomorphy vs. morphoph<strong>on</strong>ology<br />

An issue that arises in the presentati<strong>on</strong> of examples to follow in this chapter (and<br />

also in chapters 3 and 4 where I discuss examples with other types of ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing) is the difficulty of determining whether a particular example of<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy involves suppleti<strong>on</strong>. Kiparsky (1996) discusses<br />

this problem and proposes the following criteria to distinguish between instances of<br />

morphoph<strong>on</strong>ology (ph<strong>on</strong>ological rule/c<strong>on</strong>straint-driven allomorphy) and (suppletive)<br />

allomorphy (1996: 17):<br />

(1) Morphoph<strong>on</strong>ology Allomorphy<br />

a. general (not item-specific) item-specific<br />

b. involve a single segment may involve more than <strong>on</strong>e segment<br />

c. observe ph<strong>on</strong>ological locality c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s obey morphological locality c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s<br />

d. follow all morpholexical processes ordered prior to morphoph<strong>on</strong>emic rules<br />

Some of these criteria are more useful than others, and as will become evident in the<br />

presentati<strong>on</strong> of examples, there is a significant gray area left by these criteria, such that<br />

27


some examples are difficult to classify. Criteri<strong>on</strong> (a), involving the generality of the<br />

pattern, is <strong>on</strong>e of the more useful criteria. If a ph<strong>on</strong>ological rule/c<strong>on</strong>straint proposed to<br />

account for a pattern of allomorphy in a particular morpheme can also account for <strong>on</strong>e or<br />

more other patterns of allomorphy in the same language, this suggests that the<br />

allomorphy is best analyzed as resulting from the applicati<strong>on</strong> of ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

rules/c<strong>on</strong>straints to a single underlying form (i.e., that the allomorphy is not suppletive).<br />

If, <strong>on</strong> the other hand, the rule/c<strong>on</strong>straint that would need to be posited to account for a<br />

pattern of allomorphy would <strong>on</strong>ly be manifested in that particular morpheme, then the<br />

allomorphy is more likely to be suppletive. However, in some cases it can be argued that<br />

a particular affix or group of affixes is associated with a ‘co-ph<strong>on</strong>ology’ (Inkelas, Orgun,<br />

and Zoll 1997, Inkelas 1998) that might result in particular rules or c<strong>on</strong>straint rankings<br />

that do not apply throughout the entire language. This is especially useful if a<br />

c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> that includes a particular affix (or <strong>on</strong>e of a group of affixes) seems always to<br />

have a particular ph<strong>on</strong>ological property (as with, for example, stress-shifting affixes).<br />

A related factor that bears <strong>on</strong> whether to analyze a particular pattern as suppleti<strong>on</strong><br />

or item-specific rule applicati<strong>on</strong> is the ph<strong>on</strong>etic naturalness of the proposed rule. Suppose<br />

that a particular morpheme presents the <strong>on</strong>ly instance in the language of the ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>figurati<strong>on</strong> that would trigger the rule. In this case, the rule would be both ‘general’ (in<br />

the sense that it applies everywhere in which the ph<strong>on</strong>ological envir<strong>on</strong>ment for its<br />

applicati<strong>on</strong> is met) and ‘item-specific’ (since it would <strong>on</strong>ly apply to <strong>on</strong>e morpheme).<br />

Therefore, in this hypothetical situati<strong>on</strong>, criteri<strong>on</strong> (a) is of no help in determining whether<br />

this is a case of rule-driven allomorphy or suppleti<strong>on</strong>. 1 A sec<strong>on</strong>dary c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong> in such<br />

1<br />

This situati<strong>on</strong> is exemplified by an example from Spanish to be discussed in §2.1.2.5.<br />

28


a situati<strong>on</strong> is the plausibility of the proposed ph<strong>on</strong>ological rule. If the rule is item-specific<br />

but is also ph<strong>on</strong>etically natural and attested in a number of languages, this is an argument<br />

in favor of rule-derived rather than suppletive allomorphy. On the other hand, if the<br />

proposed rule would be ph<strong>on</strong>etically unnatural and not attested in other languages, this<br />

suggests that the pattern involves suppleti<strong>on</strong>. This criteri<strong>on</strong> does, of course, involve some<br />

subjective judgment as to what c<strong>on</strong>stitutes ‘ph<strong>on</strong>etic naturalness,’ but this noti<strong>on</strong> in<br />

combinati<strong>on</strong> with the frequency of such rules in other languages of the world should<br />

provide some idea of the overall plausibility of the rule.<br />

Criteri<strong>on</strong> (b), which refers to the number of segments involved in the alternati<strong>on</strong>,<br />

is also relatively useful but not unproblematic. It is quite clear-cut when each of the<br />

allomorphs has several segments and n<strong>on</strong>e of them are the same (or even similar) from<br />

<strong>on</strong>e allomorph to the other; in such a case, we would almost certainly analyze the pattern<br />

as suppletive. This is not a comm<strong>on</strong> situati<strong>on</strong>, however. More comm<strong>on</strong> is a situati<strong>on</strong><br />

where <strong>on</strong>e or two segments are different in the different allomorphs. If <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>on</strong>e segment<br />

differs, the pattern may be rule-derived, though in this case we would have to evaluate<br />

the proposed rule based <strong>on</strong> the discussi<strong>on</strong> above to decide whether its generality and<br />

plausibility merit positing a ph<strong>on</strong>ological rule for the language. If two or more segments<br />

differ, the pattern is more likely suppletive unless all the segments can be altered (or<br />

deleted or inserted) via a single ph<strong>on</strong>ological rule. If multiple rules are required, is each<br />

of the rules independently motivated in the language or do we have to posit multiple,<br />

separate, item-specific ph<strong>on</strong>ological rules just to describe the pattern of allomorphy for<br />

<strong>on</strong>e morpheme (in which case it is probably suppletive allomorphy)?<br />

29


Criteri<strong>on</strong> (c), involving ph<strong>on</strong>ological vs. morphological locality, is somewhat less<br />

useful than (a) and (b) since the questi<strong>on</strong> of whether suppletive allomorphy can be<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed at a distance is an empirical questi<strong>on</strong> being investigated here. We have not<br />

yet established whether allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong> can be determined by any element in the<br />

word including those that occur ‘outside’ the morph in questi<strong>on</strong> (as predicted by P >> M)<br />

or <strong>on</strong>ly by an element in the stem to which the morph attaches. Both of these situati<strong>on</strong>s<br />

might be said to observe ‘morphological locality’. We also have not established that<br />

PCSA does not obey ph<strong>on</strong>ological locality. In fact, as will be seen in the examples to be<br />

presented here, PCSA does appear to obey ph<strong>on</strong>ological locality, making criteri<strong>on</strong> (c)<br />

irrelevant in deciding between rule-derived and suppletive allomorphy.<br />

Similarly, criteri<strong>on</strong> (d) involving ordering is of little use, though in this case due<br />

to theoretical c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s. In OT, particularly in a versi<strong>on</strong> of OT allowing P >> M, the<br />

c<strong>on</strong>cept of allomorphy being ordered after all morpholexical rules or before all<br />

morphoph<strong>on</strong>emic rules has no status. Thus, if we want to talk about examples of<br />

allomorphy in terms of OT in order to compare possible analyses, we cannot rely <strong>on</strong><br />

criteri<strong>on</strong> (d) to determine how to classify the examples.<br />

In summary, though some of Kiparsky’s (1996) criteria for identifying suppletive<br />

vs. n<strong>on</strong>-suppletive allomorphy are useful, others are not, and the set of criteria as a whole<br />

leaves a substantial gray area, so that subjective judgment will sometimes decide the<br />

categorizati<strong>on</strong> of a particular case. The existence of this gray area is not surprising, since<br />

many examples of suppletive allomorphy probably result from historical processes of rule<br />

telescoping and/or the restricti<strong>on</strong> of productive ph<strong>on</strong>ological rules to particular<br />

morphological c<strong>on</strong>texts. Thus, they may have many of the properties of regular<br />

30


ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes but also lack some of those properties. Fortunately, the distincti<strong>on</strong><br />

between suppletive and n<strong>on</strong>-suppletive allomorphy is not crucial to the argument made in<br />

this dissertati<strong>on</strong>. Since the P >> M mechanism in effect extends a ph<strong>on</strong>ological model to<br />

handle some morphological processes, we expect that the mechanism should handle the<br />

purely ph<strong>on</strong>ological (i.e., n<strong>on</strong>-suppletive) examples well and that the problematic cases<br />

(if any) should be the suppletive <strong>on</strong>es. This means that if anything, if we admit any cases<br />

of rule-derived allomorphy into our discussi<strong>on</strong> of suppletive allomorphy, we will err <strong>on</strong><br />

the side of including too many examples that favor the P >> M approach. To offset any<br />

such bias, in making generalizati<strong>on</strong>s about PCSA I will focus <strong>on</strong> the clearest cases of<br />

suppletive allomorphy and not rely too heavily <strong>on</strong> examples that fall into the gray area.<br />

2.1.2 Examples<br />

2.1.2.1 Assimilati<strong>on</strong>/harm<strong>on</strong>y<br />

Given that the P >> M mechanism accounts for suppletive allomorphy using the<br />

same ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints that drive purely ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes, this model<br />

predicts that every ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint can show effects in morphology. That is,<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straints that comm<strong>on</strong>ly drive ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes in the world’s languages should<br />

also c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> suppletive allomorph selecti<strong>on</strong>. Assimilati<strong>on</strong> is a very comm<strong>on</strong> type of<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological process with roots in coarticulati<strong>on</strong>, and the P >> M model therefore leads<br />

us to expect assimilati<strong>on</strong> to c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> suppletive allomorphy. Several c<strong>on</strong>straints have<br />

been proposed to drive harm<strong>on</strong>y and other assimilati<strong>on</strong> of various types, including<br />

AGREE, SPREAD, and ALIGN (see Pulleyblank 2002 for a summary of approaches to<br />

31


harm<strong>on</strong>y). Under the P >> M approach, any <strong>on</strong>e of these comm<strong>on</strong>ly used c<strong>on</strong>straints (at<br />

least <strong>on</strong>e of which must be highly ranked in any language exhibiting assimilati<strong>on</strong>) could<br />

outrank a morphological c<strong>on</strong>straint; this should give rise to PCSA driven by assimilati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong>, I discuss five languages where allomorphy could be claimed to result in<br />

assimilati<strong>on</strong> of c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant or vowel features.<br />

One example of PCSA resulting in harm<strong>on</strong>izati<strong>on</strong> of vowel features is found in<br />

Kwamera (Central-Eastern Oceanic, Vanuatu; Lindstrom and Lynch 1994). The<br />

perfective prefix in Kwamera has two allomorphs that are distributed based <strong>on</strong> the initial<br />

vowel/segment of the stem (see below), and their distributi<strong>on</strong> results for the most part in<br />

words that are harm<strong>on</strong>ic in terms of vowel height. The Kwamera vowel system is as<br />

follows (Lindstrom and Lynch 1994: 3):<br />

(2) Fr<strong>on</strong>t Central Back<br />

High i u<br />

Mid e ɨ o<br />

Low a<br />

The perfective prefix allomorphs are distributed as follows (Lindstrom and Lynch 1994:<br />

12): /ɨn-/ occurs before verbs beginning with /a/, /ɨ/, and /o/, as well as most verbs<br />

beginning with /e/. As seen above, these are the n<strong>on</strong>-high vowels of Kwamera. The /uv-/<br />

allomorph occurs before verbs beginning with c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants, /i/, /u/, and a few verbs<br />

beginning with /e/ (and in these cases, /e/ surfaces as [a]). Examples are shown below<br />

with page numbers from Lindstrom and Lynch 1994.<br />

(3) a. r-p-ua ia-p-ɨn-ata ia-p-ɨn-osi<br />

3sg-COND-state 1exc-COND-PERF-see 1exc-COND-PERF-hit<br />

‘If I had seen it, I would have hit it’ (10)<br />

32


ik-ɨn-ata iakunóuihi óuihi nah ua<br />

2-PERF-see child small PREVREF or<br />

‘Did you see that small child?’ (21)<br />

b. in r-uv-kusi kafete<br />

he/she 3sg-PERF-weave mat<br />

‘She wove a mat’ (10)<br />

iak-uv-regi kwanage ira<br />

1exc-PERF-hear story LOC:3sg<br />

‘I heard his/her story (the <strong>on</strong>e told about him/her)’ (23)<br />

Thus, the /ɨn-/ allomorph is used when the following vowel is [-high] ((3)a), and the /uv-/<br />

allomorph is used elsewhere ((3)b), including before [+high] vowels (though the /uv-/<br />

prefix is <strong>on</strong>ly shown before c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-initial roots am<strong>on</strong>g Lindstrom and Lynch’s<br />

examples). The result of the allomorphy is therefore to harm<strong>on</strong>ize the prefix vowel with<br />

the first vowel of the stem in terms of vowel height (recall that /ɨ/ is a n<strong>on</strong>-high vowel in<br />

Kwamera). Note, however, that this cannot be attributed to a rule of vowel harm<strong>on</strong>y,<br />

since the two prefix allomorphs also differ in their c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants (n vs. v). The difference in<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants is ph<strong>on</strong>ologically neutral, having no obvious effect <strong>on</strong> the well-formedness of<br />

the word.<br />

The Kwamera example dem<strong>on</strong>strates, first, that vowel height is a vowel feature<br />

that apparently can c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> PCSA resulting in an assimilatory pattern. Sec<strong>on</strong>d, note that<br />

the affix in questi<strong>on</strong> is a prefix and that the stem vowel that c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s the allomorphy is<br />

the leftmost vowel of the stem. As will be seen throughout the presentati<strong>on</strong> of examples<br />

in this chapter, this is a comm<strong>on</strong> property of examples of PCSA. Prefix allomorphy is<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by elements at the left edge of the stem, while suffix allomorphy is<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by elements at the right edge of the stem.<br />

33


Another example of PCSA resulting in vowel harm<strong>on</strong>y is found in Hungarian<br />

(Kenesei, Vago, and Fenyvesi 1997 [KVF], Rounds 2001). The 3sg suffix in definite<br />

present tense forms has two variants, /-i/ and /-ja/, whose distributi<strong>on</strong> is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by<br />

the quality of the stem vowel. After a back vowel, the form -ja is used ((4)a); after a fr<strong>on</strong>t<br />

vowel, -i is used ((4)b) (Rounds 2001: 28). Examples below are from Rounds (2001: 29)<br />

except where noted.<br />

(4) a. ad-ja ‘he gives’ ró-ja ‘he carves’ (KVF 290)<br />

olvas-sa ‘he reads’ játsz-sza ‘he plays’<br />

b. visz-i ‘he carries’ (KVF 290) főz-i ‘he cooks’<br />

kér-i ‘he asks for’ lö-vi ‘he shoots’ (KVF 291)<br />

There are two minor complicati<strong>on</strong>s to the descripti<strong>on</strong> of the pattern. The first is that, as<br />

seen above, when -ja follows a stem-final sibilant, /j/ assimilates to the sibilant (Rounds<br />

2001: 27). The sec<strong>on</strong>d is that, as also seen above, when -i follows a vowel-final stem, [v]<br />

is inserted before the suffix vowel (KVF 291). These can be attributed to purely<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological rules/c<strong>on</strong>straints that apply after <strong>on</strong>e of the two suppletive forms of the<br />

suffix has been selected. The Hungarian example shows that in additi<strong>on</strong> to height,<br />

backness can also c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> PCSA. 2<br />

2<br />

This example is somewhat problematic for the GDFAC, as Hungarian is <strong>on</strong>e of <strong>on</strong>ly<br />

two languages in the survey to exhibit allomorphy c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by an element that is not<br />

at the immediate edge of the stem; a set of similar examples comes from Bari, to be<br />

discussed below. In both cases, allomorphy is triggered by an edgemost vowel that is not<br />

the edgemost segment of the stem (i.e., a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant intervenes between the triggering<br />

vowel and the stem edge). To account for these examples in the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> model,<br />

<strong>on</strong>e might modify the GDFAC to state that the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing element must be the<br />

edgemost element <strong>on</strong> its C/V tier. This would mean that the element either must be the<br />

initial/final vowel or the initial/final c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant of the stem, but not necessarily the<br />

initial/final segment. I avoid making this move because <strong>on</strong>ly two languages motivate it<br />

and no language exhibits a type of allomorphy in which the initial/final c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant<br />

triggers PCSA across a vowel. Therefore, a better approach to Hungarian and Bari may<br />

be to appeal to something like extrametricality for the intervening c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants, rather than<br />

34


Other types of assimilati<strong>on</strong> including c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant harm<strong>on</strong>y across a vowel are also<br />

comm<strong>on</strong> but are not represented in this survey am<strong>on</strong>g examples of PCSA. There are two<br />

examples of what may have originated in leniti<strong>on</strong> that could be related to C-to-V feature<br />

assimilati<strong>on</strong>. One of these is found in Yidiɲ (Pama-Nyungan, Australia; Dix<strong>on</strong> 1977). In<br />

Yidiɲ, the locative/instrumental/allative allomorphs are distributed based <strong>on</strong> whether the<br />

stem is c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final or vowel final (Dix<strong>on</strong> 1980: 296). Their distributi<strong>on</strong> is as follows:<br />

-la occurs after vowel-final stems, 3 as in (5)a, while -da (with assimilati<strong>on</strong> of the initial<br />

stop to the place of a preceding nasal and predictable lengthening of the last vowel of the<br />

stem) occurs after c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems, as in ((5)b). Examples are shown below<br />

(examples are from Dix<strong>on</strong> 1977: 128-129 except where different page numbers are noted<br />

next to an example).<br />

(5) a. gabuḑu-la ‘white clay-LOC’ ḑimuru-la ‘house-LOC’ (518)<br />

b. muḑa:m-ba ‘mother-LOC’ warḑa:n-da ‘boat-LOC’<br />

muyga:l-da ‘hole, trap-LOC’ maŋgumbar-da ‘grub sp.-LOC’<br />

These allomorphs are not related through a general rule of the language, so the<br />

allomorphy is likely suppletive. One possible way of looking at the pattern is as leniti<strong>on</strong><br />

of the suffix-initial c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant between vowels. Perhaps in the surface form, the stem-<br />

modifying the GDFAC, the str<strong>on</strong>g versi<strong>on</strong> of which does hold for all other examples in<br />

the survey.<br />

3<br />

According to Dix<strong>on</strong> (1977: 128), a more precise statement of the distributi<strong>on</strong> is that<br />

vowel-final stems with an odd number of syllables take -la, while vowel-final stems with<br />

an even syllable count have their final vowel lengthened instead. However, Dix<strong>on</strong> points<br />

out (1977: 128) that these two allomorphs could relate to a single underlying form /-la/<br />

since, based <strong>on</strong> the usual ph<strong>on</strong>otactics of the language, -la would reduce to -:l for this<br />

stem type, and <strong>on</strong>e could therefore write a rule deleting [l] in this affix (though, as Dix<strong>on</strong><br />

menti<strong>on</strong>s, this would be an ad hoc rule). The possibility of a rule-based analysis of the<br />

post-vocalic allomorphs must be the reas<strong>on</strong> why Dix<strong>on</strong> (1980: 296) characterizes these<br />

allomorphs as having a single underlying form.<br />

35


final vowel and suffix-initial c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant share the [+c<strong>on</strong>tinuant] feature in a c<strong>on</strong>figurati<strong>on</strong><br />

just like <strong>on</strong>e that would result from feature spreading in a leniti<strong>on</strong> rule in ph<strong>on</strong>ology.<br />

Another example that may involve leniti<strong>on</strong> is found in Korean (Lee 1989), where<br />

the c<strong>on</strong>junctive suffix takes the form -wa or -kwa. The -wa form is used following a<br />

vowel-final stem ((6)a), while -kwa is used following a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stem ((6)b)<br />

(Lapointe 1999). Examples are shown below (examples are from Lee 1989: 113 except<br />

where noted).<br />

(6) a. ai-wa ‘child and X’ (Lapointe 1999: 271)<br />

sɛ-wa ‘bird and X’<br />

b. pap-kwa ‘rice and X’ (Lapointe 1999: 271)<br />

san-kwa ‘mountain and X’<br />

gaŋ-kwa ‘river and X’<br />

mul-kwa ‘water and X’<br />

This example is noteworthy because it seems to decrease well-formedness in terms of<br />

syllable structure. As pointed out by Bye (to appear), we might have expected the<br />

opposite distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs since this would have avoided <strong>on</strong>set c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant<br />

clusters. As will be seen in §2.1.2.3, Korean does exhibit PCSA that appears to optimize<br />

syllables by avoiding c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant clusters, so it is interesting that the example seen here<br />

has the opposite effect. As with the Yidiɲ example above, in this example it appears that<br />

the allomorphy relates to leniti<strong>on</strong>, since the ‘weaker’ c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant occurs in intervocalic<br />

positi<strong>on</strong>. If we assume that the initial w of -wa ends up sharing the [+c<strong>on</strong>tinuant] feature<br />

with the stem-final vowel, this could be seen as an example of PCSA involving<br />

assimilati<strong>on</strong> of a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant to a vowel feature.<br />

Another possible example of PCSA resulting in c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants assimilating to vowels<br />

is the allomorphy exhibited by some suffixes in the Sibe variety of Manchu (Tungusic,<br />

36


China; Li 1996). According to Li (1996: 201), there are five suffixes in Sibe whose initial<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant surfaces as either a velar or a uvular. If a low vowel occurs in the stem, the<br />

uvular-initial allomorph is used; otherwise, the velar-initial allomorph is used. The<br />

suffixes involved in the pattern are the adjectival diminutive (with the variants -kɨn, -kun,<br />

-qɨn, -qun), the comparative (-kɨndi, -kundi, -qɨndi, -qundi), the self-perceived immediate<br />

past (-xɨ, -xu, -χɨ, -χu), the n<strong>on</strong>-self-perceived past (-xɤi, -xui, -χɤi, -χui), and the self-<br />

perceived remote past (-xɨŋ, -xuŋ, -χɨŋ, -χuŋ). Examples of the self-perceived immediate<br />

past are shown below (Li 1996: 202).<br />

(7) tükɛ-χu ‘to watch’ gɨnɨ-xɨ ‘to go’<br />

bɔdu-χu ‘to c<strong>on</strong>sider’ türü-xu ‘to rent’<br />

lavdu-χu ‘to become more’ utu-xu ‘to dress’<br />

ömi-χɨ ‘to drink’ tɨsu-xu ‘to satisfy’<br />

This example is also discussed by Bye (2005), who has two arguments for why<br />

these examples should be c<strong>on</strong>sidered cases of PCSA. The first is that the pattern violates<br />

strict locality, since a high fr<strong>on</strong>t vowel can intervene between the triggering low vowel<br />

and the initial c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant of the stem, suggesting that this is not a regular ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

rule. The sec<strong>on</strong>d reas<strong>on</strong> is that not all velar-initial suffixes undergo the alternati<strong>on</strong>: for<br />

example, the imperative suffix surfaces as -kin even when the stem has a low vowel.<br />

Thus, Bye (2005) analyzes the suffixes as each having two underlying forms in a<br />

suppletive relati<strong>on</strong>ship. However, the problems for a purely ph<strong>on</strong>ological analysis that<br />

were pointed out by Bye seem to be less problematic than the loss of a generalizati<strong>on</strong> in<br />

the suppletive analysis. If the allomorphy is suppletive, we cannot explain why five<br />

suffixes exhibit the same pattern. If, <strong>on</strong> the other hand, we assume that the allomorphy is<br />

37


not suppletive, we have <strong>on</strong>ly to explain the transparency of high vowels and the failure of<br />

the imperative to participate.<br />

The transparency of high vowels can be achieved via underspecificati<strong>on</strong>. As <strong>on</strong>e<br />

might have noticed in looking at the examples above, there is no mid vowel category in<br />

Sibe, so the vowels /ɛ/, /ɔ/, and /ö/ pattern with /a/ in triggering the use of the uvular-<br />

initial suffix allomorphs. Therefore, we need <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>on</strong>e feature to describe vowel height in<br />

Sibe (see also Dresher and Zhang in press), and this means that if we specify the low<br />

vowels for height (either with [+low] or [-high]), then high vowels do not need any<br />

underlying height features in order for the c<strong>on</strong>trast to be maintained. We could say, for<br />

example, that the initial c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant in each of the five participating suffixes is a [-cor<strong>on</strong>al,<br />

-labial] suffix that is unspecified for [±high]. If the stem has a [-high] segment, then this<br />

feature will spread to the suffix-initial c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant, resulting in a uvular c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant.<br />

Otherwise, [+high] is filled in by default <strong>on</strong> both the unspecified vowels and the suffix-<br />

initial c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant, resulting in high vowels and a velar c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant, respectively. The<br />

underspecificati<strong>on</strong> analysis also allows us to account for the behavior of the imperative<br />

suffix. All that must be said is that unlike the five suffixes whose initial c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant is<br />

unpecified for [±high] and therefore alternates between velar and uvular, the initial<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant of the imperative suffix is prespecified as [+high], and it therefore invariably<br />

surfaces as a velar. Because five suffixes participate in this pattern and because we can<br />

formulate a straightforward ph<strong>on</strong>ological analysis using underspecificati<strong>on</strong>, I c<strong>on</strong>clude<br />

that this is probably not an example of PCSA. 4<br />

4<br />

I have included the example here for completeness since Bye (2005) categorizes it as an<br />

example of PCSA.<br />

38


To summarize, we have seen here that PCSA can be c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant or<br />

vowel features, resulting in assimilatory patterns. In each case, the stem segment bearing<br />

the feature c<strong>on</strong>ditioining the allomorphy occurs at the edge of the stem where the affix<br />

attaches.<br />

2.1.2.2 Dissimilati<strong>on</strong>/disharm<strong>on</strong>y<br />

Though perhaps less comm<strong>on</strong> than assimilati<strong>on</strong>, dissimilati<strong>on</strong>/disharm<strong>on</strong>y is<br />

comm<strong>on</strong> enough cross-linguistically that we expect to find some cases of PCSA resulting<br />

in dissimilatory or disharm<strong>on</strong>ic patterns. In ph<strong>on</strong>ology, dissimilati<strong>on</strong> is often accounted<br />

for in OT analyses using the Obligatory C<strong>on</strong>tour Principle (OCP; Leben 1973, McCarthy<br />

1986). One versi<strong>on</strong> of the OCP as an OT c<strong>on</strong>straint is given below (Pulleyblank 1996:<br />

330).<br />

(8) OBLIGATORY CONTOUR PRINCIPLE: A sequence of identical elements within a tier<br />

is prohibited.<br />

The P >> M model predicts that in some languages, this c<strong>on</strong>straint should drive PCSA,<br />

resulting in dissimilatory effects. We do in fact find some examples of this type, which<br />

will be discussed below.<br />

According to Hanss<strong>on</strong> (2001: 165-166), c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant place dissimilati<strong>on</strong>, even l<strong>on</strong>g-<br />

distance dissimilati<strong>on</strong>, is a relatively comm<strong>on</strong> phenomen<strong>on</strong>. The P >> M model therefore<br />

predicts that we should find cases of PCSA involving c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant place dissimilati<strong>on</strong>. As<br />

will be seen, this survey did reveal some such cases.<br />

One example of PCSA involving c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant place dissimilati<strong>on</strong> is found in<br />

Tahitian (Polynesian, French Polynesia; Try<strong>on</strong> 1970, Lazard and Peltzer 2000). The<br />

causative/factitive in Tahitian is marked by <strong>on</strong>e of two prefix forms, fa’a- or ha’a-. The<br />

39


ha’a- form occurs when the root begins with a labial (f, m, p, or v), and the fa’a- form<br />

occurs elsewhere (Lazard and Peltzer 2000: 224), with a small number of excepti<strong>on</strong>al<br />

roots that can take either form. The distributi<strong>on</strong> is shown below (Lazard and Peltzer<br />

2000: 225). 5<br />

(9) fiu ‘se lasser’ ha’a-fiu ‘ennuyer, s’ennuyer’<br />

mana’o ‘penser’ ha’a-mana’o ‘se rappeler’<br />

veve ‘pauvre’ ha’a-veve ‘appauvrir’<br />

’amu ‘manger’ fa’a-’amu ‘faire manger, nourrir’<br />

rave ‘faire’ fa’a-rave ‘faire faire’<br />

tai’o ‘lire’ fa’a-tai’o ‘faire lire’<br />

The allomorphy appears to be suppletive since a rule of place dissimilati<strong>on</strong><br />

needed to relate the allomorphs to a single underlying form would not be a general rule of<br />

the language. There do not seem to be any affixes with /f/ that we could compare with the<br />

causative, but we do find many surface counterexamples to /f/ dissimilati<strong>on</strong> in (apparent)<br />

reduplicated forms and within roots (10), some of which are seen below (Try<strong>on</strong> 1970:<br />

148-160).<br />

(10) fefe ‘twisted’ fe:fe: ‘a boil’<br />

fifi ‘to be in difficulties’ faufa’a ‘gain, profit, worth’<br />

Thus, there is no general ban against sequences of labial c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants (with intervening<br />

vowels and with or without intervening glottal stop). There is, however, some other<br />

evidence for a relati<strong>on</strong>ship between /f/ and /h/. According to Try<strong>on</strong> (1970: 2), there are<br />

5<br />

It is worth pointing out that there is a large number of roots (43, to be exact) that can<br />

take either form of the prefix (Try<strong>on</strong> 1970: 42), and there are several that take a form not<br />

predicted by Lazard and Peltzer’s generalizati<strong>on</strong>. For example, Try<strong>on</strong> (1970: 149-150)<br />

lists six f-initial roots and two m-initial roots that take fa’a-. However, all of the roots<br />

listed as taking ha’a- are, as predicted by Lazard and Peltzer, labial-initial. Perhaps the<br />

discrepancy reflects a dialectal difference. An interesting alternative is that the pattern<br />

may have been in the process of becoming regularized in 1970, and perhaps the<br />

difference simply reflects the result of this process over the 30 years that passed between<br />

the two studies.<br />

40


several words where we find ‘f and h as variants’. The examples that are cited are shown<br />

below.<br />

(11) pufa ~ puha ‘copra’<br />

u:fi ~ u:hi ‘yam’<br />

tufa’a ~ tuha’a ‘share’<br />

Still, since there is no indicati<strong>on</strong> of a synchr<strong>on</strong>ic rule of f → h in the language, I assume<br />

this to be an example of suppletive allomorphy. This example is noteworthy because the<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants that are, in effect, dissimilated by the suppletive allomorphy are not strictly<br />

adjacent or even adjacent <strong>on</strong> the CV tier, since vowels and a glottal stop intervene<br />

between the two c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants involved in the pattern. 6 But note that this is not problematic<br />

for the GDFAC, since the ‘c<strong>on</strong>straining’ (c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing) element (a stem-initial labial) is<br />

at the left edge of the stem and is therefore immediately adjacent to the ‘c<strong>on</strong>strained’<br />

element (the prefix).<br />

An example involving fricative dissimilati<strong>on</strong> is found in Hungarian (Kenesei,<br />

Vago, and Fenyvesi 1997, Rounds 2001). In present tense indefinite verbs, the 2sg is<br />

usually marked by [-s] (Kenesei, Vago, and Fenyvesi 1997: 289-290; note that [s]<br />

corresp<strong>on</strong>ds to Hungarian orthographic , as in the examples below). When the stem<br />

ends in CC or in a l<strong>on</strong>g vowel + t, a ‘linking vowel’ is used between the root and the<br />

suffix (Rounds 2001: 26). Examples using this allomorph are seen in (12)a. However,<br />

when the stem ends in a sibilant ((12)b), the 2sg is marked by -El (where E is a mid<br />

6<br />

The [’] in these forms is a full glottal stop (Try<strong>on</strong> 1970: 4-5), rather than a glottalizati<strong>on</strong><br />

feature <strong>on</strong> the vowel as is the case in other language families. For any sequence of two<br />

vowels (whether they are identical or not), [’] can occur before the first vowel, between<br />

the vowels, in both locati<strong>on</strong>s, or neither (Try<strong>on</strong> 1970: 5). According to Try<strong>on</strong> (1970:5),<br />

the sequence V’V is disyllabic, even if the two vowels are identical.<br />

41


vowel that undergoes backness and rounding harm<strong>on</strong>y). 7 Examples are from Ab<strong>on</strong>dolo<br />

(1988: 102), except where noted.<br />

(12) a. m<strong>on</strong>d-a-sz ‘you say’<br />

vág-sz ‘you cut’<br />

vár-sz ‘you wait’<br />

nyom-sz ‘you press’<br />

rak-sz ‘you place’<br />

b. v<strong>on</strong>z-ol ‘you attract’<br />

edz-el ‘you train’<br />

hajhász-ol ‘you seek’<br />

főz-öl ‘you cook’ (Rounds 2001: 27)<br />

I am treating the pattern seen here as suppletive for two reas<strong>on</strong>s. First, the allomorphs<br />

differ in more than <strong>on</strong>e segment since the -El form has an initial vowel that the -sz form<br />

lacks. Also, there is no general process of sibilant dissimilati<strong>on</strong> in the language. In fact,<br />

adjacent sibilants occur regularly and are subject to a rule of sibilant assimilati<strong>on</strong> in<br />

which the first sibilant assimilates in place of articulati<strong>on</strong> to the sec<strong>on</strong>d (Kenesei, Vago,<br />

and Fenyvesi 1997: 444-446). This case dem<strong>on</strong>strates that [+sibilant] is a feature that can<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> PCSA.<br />

In Caddo (Caddoan, Oklahoma; Melnar 2004), the simple future suffix exhibits<br />

allomorphy that results in dissimilati<strong>on</strong> of sequences of glottal stops. When the stem ends<br />

in glottal stop, the future suffix appears as -waɁ. Otherwise, the allomorph -Ɂ.aɁ. is used.<br />

Examples are provided below (Melnar 2004: 65; Melnar takes the examples from the<br />

mostly unpublished field notes of Wallace Chafe).<br />

7<br />

It is not clear whether this form is used with all sibilant-final stems. Rounds (2001: 26)<br />

states that it is used when the stem ends in s, sz, z, or dz, while Kenesei, Vago, and<br />

Fenyvesi (1997: 290) state that it is used when the stem ends in s, sz, or z and do not<br />

menti<strong>on</strong> dz (which they do treat as a single affricate segment rather than as a sequence of<br />

/d/+/z/ (1997: 383)). It may simply be that there there is a lack of stems ending in<br />

sibilants other than s, sz, and z that would allow us to distinguish whether or not the<br />

allomorphy extends to all sibilants. Since there do not appear to be any counterexamples<br />

given, I will assume that -El occurs after sibilants.<br />

42


(13) basisɁ.aɁ dikattumbakáiɁwaɁ<br />

/ba=sis-ɁaɁ/ /dikat#nu-n-baká=hiɁ-waɁ/<br />

boil-Future what.Inter#3Dat-App-have.to.say-Future<br />

‘it will boil’ ‘What will he have to say (to some<strong>on</strong>e)?’<br />

These allomorphs differ in <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>on</strong>e segment, and the use of a separate allomorph for<br />

glottal stop-final words appears to be functi<strong>on</strong>ally motivated since a series of two glottal<br />

stops might be difficult to produce. However, the rule relating these allomorphs would<br />

have to be item-specific, since elsewhere in the language, a sequence of two glottal stops<br />

simplifies to a single glottal stop, rather than dissimilating to [wɁ] (Melnar 2004: 203).<br />

Thus, in Caddo it seems that the dispreferred sequence /ɁɁ/ is repaired differently<br />

depending <strong>on</strong> whether we look at the behavior of the future suffix (which exhibits<br />

dissimilati<strong>on</strong>) or the general ph<strong>on</strong>ological pattern in the language (which fuses /ɁɁ/ into<br />

[Ɂ]). If both patterns were to be handled via a ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint such as *ɁɁ, as<br />

would be d<strong>on</strong>e under the P >> M approach, we would not have a way of accounting for<br />

the two different repair strategies without a specific c<strong>on</strong>straint referring to the future<br />

suffix.<br />

In additi<strong>on</strong> to c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant dissimilati<strong>on</strong>, this survey also revealed some unusual<br />

instances of PCSA involving vowel dissimilati<strong>on</strong>/disharm<strong>on</strong>y in Bari (Eastern Nilotic,<br />

Sudan; Spagnolo 1933). 8 Vowel disharm<strong>on</strong>y in itself seems to be relatively uncomm<strong>on</strong>,<br />

especially in comparis<strong>on</strong> to vowel harm<strong>on</strong>y. 9 Even more unusual in Bari is that several of<br />

8<br />

Hall and Yokwe’s (1981) discussi<strong>on</strong> of ATR harm<strong>on</strong>y includes examples of some of the<br />

affixes discussed by Spagnolo (1933) and accounts for some of the patterns seen here.<br />

Where relevant, Hall and Yokwe’s (1981) analysis is referred to below, though Spagnolo<br />

gives some disharm<strong>on</strong>ic examples that Hall and Yokwe (1981) do not menti<strong>on</strong> or account<br />

for in their analysis.<br />

9<br />

See Krämer 1998 for a model of harm<strong>on</strong>y/disharm<strong>on</strong>y that accounts for the relative<br />

rarity of vowel disharm<strong>on</strong>y.<br />

43


these instances of PCSA result in vowel disharm<strong>on</strong>y in terms of height and possibly ATR<br />

even in a language that appears to exhibit vowel harm<strong>on</strong>y. The vowel inventory of Bari is<br />

as follows (Spagnolo 1933: 8), with <strong>on</strong>e modificati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

(14) i u<br />

ɪ ʊ<br />

e o<br />

ɛ ɔ<br />

ə<br />

a<br />

The vowel given as [ə] above is described by Spagnolo as a ‘central vowel, between i and<br />

u... the sound is not lip-rounded’ (1933: 4). I characterize it above as being low, which is<br />

inc<strong>on</strong>sistent with Spagnolo’s descripti<strong>on</strong> of this vowel as being ‘between i and u’, but<br />

c<strong>on</strong>sistent with the way in which this sound behaves in the patterns to be described<br />

below. Spagnolo uses the symbol [ӧ] for this sound, suggesting Spagnolo himself did not<br />

intend it to be c<strong>on</strong>sidered a high vowel; regardless of its actual ph<strong>on</strong>etic realizati<strong>on</strong>, this<br />

vowel patterns as if it were the [+ATR] counterpart to /a/, as will be shown below. 10 In<br />

the examples to be discussed, I have replaced Spagnolo’s [ӧ] with [ə]. The feature values<br />

that I am assuming for the Bari vowels are as follows.<br />

(15) i u ɪ ʊ e ə o ɛ ɔ a<br />

high + + - + - - - - - -<br />

low - - - - - + - - - +<br />

back - + - + - + + - + +<br />

ATR + + - - + + + - - -<br />

10 This is also the analysis of Hall and Yokwe, who describe this vowel in Bari as ‘a<br />

somewhat raised and markedly centralized low vowel… slightly lower and slightly more<br />

back than the vowel in American English but’ (1981: 55). This vowel is also treated as<br />

the [+ATR] counterpart to /a/ in Kukú (a closely related language spoken in Uganda and<br />

Sudan). However, it is transcribed as [ɨ] in Kukú, and Cohen (2000: 6) describes it as ‘a<br />

central-like vowel of high-mid height’.<br />

44


The causative/reciprocative prefix exhibits height disharm<strong>on</strong>y as well as ATR<br />

harm<strong>on</strong>y. Both categories are marked by the prefix tV-, where V is a [+back, -low] vowel<br />

whose other features are determined by the vowel of the root, though not in an<br />

immediately obvious way, as shown in the examples below (Spagnolo 1933: 157).<br />

(16) nək ‘to suck’ tu-nək ‘to give suck’<br />

ŋa ‘to open’ tʊ-ŋa ‘to open with force’<br />

rik ‘to drive away’ to-rik ‘to pursue’<br />

gwut ‘to beat’ to-gwut ‘to beat each other’<br />

rem ‘to stab’ to-rem ‘to cause to stab; to stab each other’<br />

mor ‘to insult’ to-mor ‘to abuse violently; to insult each other’<br />

mɛt ‘to see’ tɔ-mɛt ‘to look at each other; to cause to see’<br />

kɔr ‘to divide’ tɔ-kɔr ‘to settle a dispute’<br />

yɪŋ ‘to hear’ tɔ-yɪŋ ‘to listen attentively; to attract attenti<strong>on</strong>’<br />

kʊr ‘to till’ tɔ-kʊr ‘to help each other with the tilling’<br />

This pattern can be schematized as follows. 11<br />

(17) Stem vowel Prefix vowel<br />

ə u<br />

a ʊ<br />

i, u, e, o o<br />

ɪ, ʊ, ɛ, ɔ ɔ<br />

The generalizati<strong>on</strong> can be stated as follows: stems with [-low] vowels take a suffix vowel<br />

that is [-high]; this vowel then undergoes ATR harm<strong>on</strong>y 12 with the stem vowel to be<br />

realized as either [o] or [ɔ]. Stems with other vowels (i.e., the [+low] vowels /ə/ and /a/)<br />

take a suffix vowel that is [+high], which also undergoes ATR harm<strong>on</strong>y with the stem<br />

vowel, surfacing as [u] or [ʊ]. This pattern is interesting because (assuming the feature<br />

specificati<strong>on</strong>s that I have laid out for the Bari vowel system) this is not straightforward<br />

dissimilati<strong>on</strong> involving a single feature, but rather a type of indirect dissimilati<strong>on</strong> that<br />

11 The exact same pattern is exhibited in Kukú for the same prefix (Cohen 2000: 17).<br />

12 A general process of ATR harm<strong>on</strong>y has been documented in Bari by Hall and Yokwe<br />

(1981).<br />

45


involves the interacti<strong>on</strong> of two related features, [±high] and [±low]. One observati<strong>on</strong> that<br />

can be made about the emphatic suffix pattern is that whatever value the stem vowel has<br />

for [±low], the prefix vowel will have the same value for [±high]. This is reminiscent of<br />

the so-called ‘α-rule’, which has since been argued to be too powerful a notati<strong>on</strong>al device<br />

since it predicts unattested rules (see, e.g., McCawley 1979). Thus, the pattern of PCSA<br />

seen here exemplifies a pattern of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed morphology that is not<br />

supposed to exist in pure ph<strong>on</strong>ology. This is problematic for the P >> M model, which, as<br />

has been discussed above, predicts that the same effects that are manifested in ph<strong>on</strong>ology<br />

should also be manifested in PCSA since the same ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints are supposed<br />

to be resp<strong>on</strong>sible for both.<br />

Several suffixes also show patterns of allomorphy determined by stem vowel<br />

quality in such a way as to produce vowel disharm<strong>on</strong>y. The emphatic verb suffix<br />

(Spagnolo 1933: 133-134) has the form -jV, where V is always a [+back] vowel that<br />

patterns as in the examples below (Spagnolo 1933: 134).<br />

(18) gir-jə ‘to wipe a plate, etc.’ kur-jə ‘to borrow’<br />

kər-ju ‘to spoil, c<strong>on</strong>taminate’ kar-ju ‘to spoil, ruin’<br />

kor-ju ‘to bore beads for threading’ ker-ju ‘to steer’<br />

kɛr-ja ‘to notch’ kər-ja ‘to divide, separate’<br />

dɪr-ja ‘to look at’ tʊr-ja ‘to pour in’<br />

The stem and suffix vowels corresp<strong>on</strong>d as follows.<br />

(19) Stem vowel Suffix vowel<br />

i, u ə<br />

ə, e, o, a u<br />

ɪ, ʊ, ɛ, ɔ a<br />

46


Stems with [+high, +ATR] vowels have a [-high, +low, +back, +ATR] suffix vowel ([ə]).<br />

Stems with a [-low, -ATR] vowel have the suffix vowel [a], which is [-high, +low,<br />

+back, -ATR]. All other stems take [u], which is [+high, -low, +back, +ATR]. In these<br />

examples, words are not fully harm<strong>on</strong>ic with respect to the feature [±ATR] (under our<br />

assumed feature system), since [a] is [-ATR] but corresp<strong>on</strong>ds as a stem vowel with the<br />

[+ATR] suffix vowel [u]. 13 A possible explanati<strong>on</strong> for this is that ATR harm<strong>on</strong>y (which I<br />

have assumed to be a ph<strong>on</strong>ological rule rather than part of a pattern of suppletive<br />

allomorphy) is stem-c<strong>on</strong>trolled and right-to-left. This would account for why the<br />

causative/reciprocal prefix undergoes ATR harm<strong>on</strong>y (as seen in the previous set of<br />

examples), but suffixes and stems do not. In this case, ATR harm<strong>on</strong>y could be part of the<br />

suppletive pattern. Thus, PCSA in the emphatic verb suffix results in both harm<strong>on</strong>y and<br />

disharm<strong>on</strong>y: ATR harm<strong>on</strong>y, but height disharm<strong>on</strong>y in some cases (i.e., in some instances<br />

a [+high] stem vowel is paired with a [-high] suffix vowel, and a [-low] stem vowel is<br />

paired with a [+low] suffix vowel. The pattern of harm<strong>on</strong>y/disharm<strong>on</strong>y is unlike a<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological rule of dissimilati<strong>on</strong> because two of the suffix allomorphs have the features<br />

[-high, +low], so the dissimilati<strong>on</strong> is <strong>on</strong>ly apparent when we compare the disharm<strong>on</strong>ic<br />

examples with what they would have looked like if they took the ‘elsewhere’ allomorph<br />

instead. If stems with /i/ and /u/ took the elsewhere (/-ju/) allomorph, then these words<br />

would be harm<strong>on</strong>ic in terms of both [±high] and [±low]. If stems with /ɪ, ʊ, ɛ, ɔ/ took the<br />

/-ju/ allomorph, the resulting words would be harm<strong>on</strong>ic in terms of [±low], though words<br />

13<br />

Hall and Yokwe (1981: 58) note that there are some regular excepti<strong>on</strong>s to vowel<br />

harm<strong>on</strong>y, including the fact that a [+high, +ATR] vowel in a suffix will ‘fail to interact<br />

with vowel harm<strong>on</strong>y’ in certain morphemes. The behavior of the suffix vowel u here is<br />

subsumed under this generalizati<strong>on</strong>, though Hall and Yokwe do not offer an explanati<strong>on</strong><br />

for it.<br />

47


with stem vowels /ɛ, ɔ/ would be disharm<strong>on</strong>ic in terms of [±high]. Thus, the PCSA seen<br />

here results in a pattern of disharm<strong>on</strong>y that n<strong>on</strong>etheless does not work in quite the same<br />

way as a pattern that is derived via the applicati<strong>on</strong> of a ph<strong>on</strong>ological rule or c<strong>on</strong>straint to<br />

a single underlying form. This is somewhat problematic for the P >> M model, which<br />

predicts that PCSA ought to behave just like other, purely ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes driven<br />

by P c<strong>on</strong>straints.<br />

A sec<strong>on</strong>d suffix in Bari exhibiting allomorphy is the emphatic imperative, which<br />

Spagnolo characterizes as having two allomorphs, /-é’/ and /-í’/ (1933: 136). Examples<br />

are shown below.<br />

(20) gir-jé’ ‘wipe a plate’ ’bidd-yé’ ‘beat’<br />

kur-jé’ ‘borrow’ jund-yé’ ‘vindicate’<br />

rəb-bí’ ‘wrapt’ [sic] ped-dí’ ‘tether’<br />

kɛg-gí’ ‘hit target’ gɪ’-yí’ ‘strip off’<br />

kam-bí’ ‘paddle’ s<strong>on</strong>-dí’ ‘send’<br />

jɔŋ-gí’ ‘take’ rʊ’-yí’ ‘press’<br />

The actual form of the suffix appears to be -CV because it appears (based <strong>on</strong> the available<br />

data) that the suffix has an initial c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant whose features come from the root-final<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant. Leaving this issue aside, we can characterize the ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing of<br />

the vowel alternati<strong>on</strong> as follows.<br />

(21) Stem vowel Suffix<br />

i, u /-é’/<br />

all others /-í’/<br />

The vowel of the suffix is a [-low, +ATR] whose distributi<strong>on</strong> is as follows: the /-é’/ form<br />

(whose vowel has the features [-high, -low, +ATR]) occurs after [+high, +ATR] stem<br />

vowels; /-í’/ ([+high, -low, +ATR]) occurs elsewhere (i.e., it occurs with stems whose<br />

48


vowel is either [-high] or [-ATR] or both). 14 The result is height disharm<strong>on</strong>y for most<br />

stem types, and [±ATR] disagreement for some stems. Once again, however, the pattern<br />

is different from pure ph<strong>on</strong>ological disharm<strong>on</strong>y because we can <strong>on</strong>ly understand it as<br />

disharm<strong>on</strong>ic given the incompatibility of the two features involved. One observati<strong>on</strong> that<br />

we can make is that if the stem vowel is not [+high, +ATR], then the suffix vowel has to<br />

disagree with it in at least <strong>on</strong>e of the features [±ATR] or [±high]. This is not a typical<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological rule type, again posing a potential problem for the P >> M model. It is<br />

reminiscent of the anti-identity effects described by, e.g., Alderete 2001, where an output<br />

segment must differ minimally from its corresp<strong>on</strong>dent in the input or in a<br />

morphologically related form, but these c<strong>on</strong>straints generally refer to a single feature<br />

(e.g., ¬IDENT(voice) discussed by Alderete 2001) and would therefore have to be<br />

formulated in a different way to account for the case being discussed here.<br />

Another suffix exhibiting ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy in Bari is the<br />

passive suffix, which has two variants, /-wɛ’/ and /-we’/. Unlike some of the Bari<br />

allomorphy described above, this suffix would appear to involve ATR dissimilati<strong>on</strong>,<br />

since Spagnolo states (1933: 144) that the distributi<strong>on</strong> of passive suffix variants is as<br />

follows.<br />

(22) Stem vowel Suffix<br />

i, u, ə, e, o /-wɛ’/<br />

a, ɛ, ɪ, ɔ, ʊ /-we’/<br />

This could be characterized as [ATR] dissimilati<strong>on</strong>, since [+ATR] stem vowels<br />

corresp<strong>on</strong>d with the [-ATR] suffix vowel variant, while [-ATR] stem vowels corresp<strong>on</strong>d<br />

14<br />

This is another example that falls under the category of excepti<strong>on</strong>s to ATR harm<strong>on</strong>y<br />

given by Hall and Yokwe (1981: 58), since the i here is a [+high, +ATR] vowel in a<br />

suffix.<br />

49


with the [+ATR] suffix vowel. However, Spagnolo’s characterizati<strong>on</strong> may have been in<br />

error, since the two examples that are presented c<strong>on</strong>tradict the generalizati<strong>on</strong>, and in a<br />

way that makes sense based <strong>on</strong> the ATR harm<strong>on</strong>y exhibited elsewhere, since both forms<br />

are harm<strong>on</strong>ic with respect to ATR. The examples are given below (Spagnolo 1933: 144).<br />

(23) yuŋ-we’ ‘to be born’ ’bɔk-wɛ’ ‘to be dug out’<br />

One cannot say for sure whether the initial characterizati<strong>on</strong> of the allomorphy was stated<br />

incorrectly since <strong>on</strong>ly two examples are given, but this seems likely since the pattern is<br />

otherwise highly unusual.<br />

A sec<strong>on</strong>d type of passive in Bari is marked by <strong>on</strong>e of three suffix allomorphs, all<br />

of which have the form -V (where the vowel is [+back, -high] and seems to exhibit height<br />

disharm<strong>on</strong>y with the stem vowel. Representative examples are shown below (Spagnolo<br />

1933: 107-108).<br />

(24) kət-ə ‘to be cleared away’ lip-ə ‘to be nagged’<br />

tur-ə ‘to be pursued’ ter-ə ‘to be steered’<br />

kor-o ‘to be bored for threading’ gwalak-a ‘to be smashed’<br />

tɛr-a ‘to be satisfied’ lɪp-a ‘to be skimmed off’<br />

kɔr-a ‘to be divided’ tʊr-a ‘to be poured in’<br />

kɪn-ʊ ‘to be closed’ kʊr-ʊ ‘to be cultivated’<br />

The allomorphs are distributed as follows.<br />

(25) Stem vowel Suffix vowel<br />

i, u, ə ə<br />

e, o o<br />

a, ɛ, ɪ, ɔ, ʊ a (sometimes ʊ after ɪ or ʊ)<br />

The generalizati<strong>on</strong> (apart from the roots that sometimes take [ʊ], which I assume are<br />

lexical excepti<strong>on</strong>s) is statable as follows: stems with [-high, -low, +ATR] vowels have<br />

the suffix vowel [o]. These words end up being harm<strong>on</strong>ic with respect to [±low]. Other<br />

50


stems take a [+low] suffix vowel, whose value for [±ATR] matches that of the stem<br />

vowel. Thus, words using this passive marker end up being harm<strong>on</strong>ic in terms of ATR,<br />

and those with stem vowels /e, o, ə/ are also harm<strong>on</strong>ic in terms of height, but those with<br />

stem vowels /i, u, ɪ, ʊ, ɛ, ɔ/ end up being disharm<strong>on</strong>ic with respect to [±low]. Thus, the<br />

allomorphy in this passive suffix does not have a uniform effect <strong>on</strong> the harm<strong>on</strong>y or<br />

disharm<strong>on</strong>y of vowels in a word: for some stems, it is harm<strong>on</strong>izing, while for others, it<br />

causes disharm<strong>on</strong>y. 15<br />

A final example from Bari is the imperative active, which is marked by <strong>on</strong>e of<br />

three suffix allomorphs (Spagnolo 1933: 111): /-í/, /-é/, or /-ɛ́/. Examples are shown<br />

below.<br />

(26) ’bət-í ‘skin’ lip-é ‘nag’<br />

tur-é ‘pursue’ ter-é ‘steer’<br />

kor-é ‘bore and thread’ kam-ɛ́ ‘paddle’<br />

tɛr-ɛ́ ‘satiate’ lɪp-ɛ́ ‘skim off the best’<br />

kɔr-ɛ́ ‘divide’ kʊr-ɛ́ ‘till’<br />

The allomorphs are distributed as follows.<br />

(27) Stem vowel Suffix vowel<br />

ə i<br />

i, u, e, o e<br />

a, ɛ, ɪ, ɔ, ʊ ɛ<br />

The generalizati<strong>on</strong> for the distributi<strong>on</strong> of the active imperative suffix allomorphs is as<br />

follows. Stems with the [+low, +ATR] vowel take a [+high, -low, -back, +ATR] suffix<br />

vowel. All other stems take a [-high, -low, -back] suffix vowel, which agrees with the<br />

15 Hall and Yokwe (1981: 58) account for this pattern by positing a rule of Mid-Vowel<br />

Assimilati<strong>on</strong>, in which a [+low, +back, +ATR] vowel becomes [-low, -high] following a<br />

[-low, -high, +ATR] vowel. Given this and a rule of ATR harm<strong>on</strong>y, all of the allomorphs<br />

of this passive suffix could be reduced to /-a/.<br />

51


stem vowel in ATR. The suffix allomorphs both have a vowel that is [-low, -back], which<br />

might suggest a single underlying suffix form with a [-low, -back] vowel that undergoes<br />

ATR harm<strong>on</strong>y. However, the specificati<strong>on</strong> for [±high] is not derivable from the stem<br />

vowel via any normal ph<strong>on</strong>ological rule. Thus, it seems we have to stipulate that stems<br />

with the vowel /ə/ take the /i/ suffix vowel. This is reminiscent of the pattern seen above<br />

in the causative/reciprocal prefix where the affix vowel has the same value for [±high] as<br />

the stem vowel has for [±low]. However, in this case, the pattern holds <strong>on</strong>ly for stems<br />

with the /ə/ vowel.<br />

To summarize the Bari examples presented above, in each case, the affix vowel<br />

quality is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by the root vowel, but not in any c<strong>on</strong>sistent way. In several cases,<br />

the effect of the allomorphy is dissimilatory, but not always in the same dimensi<strong>on</strong>. The<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong> of affix vowels almost seems random, yet the ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> the<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong> are straightforwardly statable. Since in each case, the allomorphs are<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>etically similar (all -V, all -CV, etc.), it might seem reas<strong>on</strong>able to posit single<br />

underlying forms for each set of alternants and to relate the allomorphs through item-<br />

specific rules based <strong>on</strong> the generalizati<strong>on</strong>s given for each example. However, this would<br />

violate Kiparsky’s generalizati<strong>on</strong> that n<strong>on</strong>-suppletive allomorphy results from rules that<br />

are not item-specific, since no <strong>on</strong>e set of rules could account for the behavior of all of the<br />

affixes, and in fact, in the case of ATR, some of the affixes exhibit harm<strong>on</strong>y while others<br />

sometimes disagree with the stem in ATR (and the passive may even exhibit disharm<strong>on</strong>y,<br />

though this could have been a descriptive error). This fact would be difficult to handle<br />

under a P >> M account where all of the allomorphy (including pure ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

allomorphy, in this case including ATR harm<strong>on</strong>y) is driven by a single set of P<br />

52


c<strong>on</strong>straints interranked with M c<strong>on</strong>straints. We could get a P >> M analysis to work if we<br />

assumed separate co-ph<strong>on</strong>ologies (with different c<strong>on</strong>straint rankings) for each of the<br />

affixes described above, but the standard versi<strong>on</strong> of OT incorporating the P >> M schema<br />

does not make use of the co-ph<strong>on</strong>ology c<strong>on</strong>cept. Furthermore, if we did posit individual<br />

co-ph<strong>on</strong>ologies for each affix, some would have patterns that are c<strong>on</strong>tradictory to each<br />

other, and this could not be modeled via a simple difference in the ranking of a small<br />

number of c<strong>on</strong>straints as is usually the case in analyses making use of co-ph<strong>on</strong>ologies.<br />

Thus, even if <strong>on</strong>e is willing to posit affix-specific co-ph<strong>on</strong>ologies, they would probably<br />

be incompatible with each other. It seems therefore that these patterns of allomorphy in<br />

Bari are suppletive, and furthermore that they would be somewhat difficult to account for<br />

using the P >> M approach.<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong>, we have seen several cases of PCSA resulting in dissimilatory<br />

patterns. The Bari vowel disharm<strong>on</strong>y examples discussed here are of particular interest<br />

(and worthy of future study). Such a case is unexpected under P >> M since there are<br />

several different patterns that c<strong>on</strong>tradict each other in terms of harm<strong>on</strong>y vs. disagreement<br />

or disharm<strong>on</strong>y, making it difficult to account for the overall pattern in terms of a single<br />

set of ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints, as would be d<strong>on</strong>e in the P >> M approach.<br />

2.1.2.3 Syllable structure optimizati<strong>on</strong><br />

Many ph<strong>on</strong>ological rules/c<strong>on</strong>straints seem to serve the purpose of optimizing<br />

syllable structure. In fact, it was ‘c<strong>on</strong>spiracies’ such as the ‘law of open syllables’ in<br />

Slavic (see, e.g., Martinet 1952, Mareš 1965) that provided part of the impetus for<br />

Optimality Theory. This is because rule-based approaches have no way of formally<br />

53


encoding the fact that in many languages, multiple different rules often work together in<br />

producing a particular kind of outcome, especially in the domain of syllable structure. In<br />

most languages, the ‘optimal’ syllable has an <strong>on</strong>set and has no coda, or a simple coda.<br />

Candidates with optimal syllable structures are selected by c<strong>on</strong>straints such as ONSET,<br />

NOCODA, and COMPLEXCODA, which feature prominently in the ph<strong>on</strong>ological systems of<br />

many languages. We therefore expect under the P >> M model that we should find<br />

examples of PCSA resulting in optimal syllables. It does appear that there are several<br />

such cases (although, as will be seen in §2.1.2.5, there seem to be just as many cases in<br />

which PCSA referring to the C/V distincti<strong>on</strong> fails to optimize syllables).<br />

An example of PCSA that optimizes syllable structure by avoiding complex codas<br />

is found in Russian (Timberlake 2004). According to Timberlake (2004), the Russian<br />

reflexive marker exhibits both morphologically and ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed<br />

suppletive allomorphy. The reflexive suffix has two allomorphs, [s j a] and [s j ]. The [s j a]<br />

variant is always used in active participle forms. In other forms, the [s j a] variant occurs<br />

after c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants, while the [s j ] variant occurs after vowels (Timberlake 2004: 345). This<br />

pattern has the effect of eliminating a potential final coda cluster that would be created by<br />

affixing [s j ] to a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stem. The examples below are from Wade (2002: 137)<br />

(the transliterati<strong>on</strong>s are mine).<br />

(28) a kupaju-s j ‘I bathe myself’ <strong>on</strong> kupajet-s j a ‘he bathes himself’<br />

kupajt j e-s j<br />

‘bathe yourselves!’ kupaj-s j a ‘bathe yourself!’<br />

<strong>on</strong>a kupala-s j<br />

‘she bathed herself’ <strong>on</strong> kupal-s j a ‘he bathed himself’<br />

Though the allomorphs are ph<strong>on</strong>etically similar, I treat this as suppletive allomorphy<br />

since the pattern does not result from the applicati<strong>on</strong> of any general rule of the language<br />

to a single underlying form for the suffix. In this example, the allomorphy optimizes<br />

54


syllables since if -s j were used with c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems, the result would be word-final<br />

CC clusters. Therefore, under P >> M, this pattern could be accounted for using<br />

*COMPLEXCODA.<br />

Turkish (Lewis 1967) exhibits an alternati<strong>on</strong> in the causative that is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed<br />

by the stem-final segment and by syllable count, the result of which may be said to<br />

optimize syllable structure. The causative is marked by -t with polysyllabic stems ending<br />

in vowels, /r/, or /l/; the suffix -DIr (where D is a cor<strong>on</strong>al stop having surface alternants<br />

[t] and [d], and I is a high vowel) is used with all other stems (except for some specific<br />

m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic stems that take a different, lexically determined allomorph). Some<br />

examples are shown below (Haig to appear: 6).<br />

(29) bekle-t- ‘wait-CAUS’ öl-dür- ‘die-CAUS’<br />

bayil-t- ‘faint-CAUS’ ye-dir- ‘eat-CAUS’<br />

getir-t- ‘bring-CAUS’ çalis-tir- ‘work-CAUS’<br />

There are two ways in which this pattern may be said to be optimizing. The first is in<br />

terms of syllable structure, since the avoidance of -t after obstruent-final stems prevents<br />

causative stems from ending in a sequence of two low-s<strong>on</strong>ority c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants. The sec<strong>on</strong>d is<br />

that, as pointed out by Haig (to appear: 6), the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs is such that in<br />

words with multiple causatives, there is never a sequence of two ph<strong>on</strong>ologically identical<br />

causative suffixes. Some examples involving multiple causatives are shown below.<br />

(30) öl-dür-t- ‘cause to kill, have killed’ (Haig to appear: 5)<br />

die-CAUS-CAUS-<br />

ye-dir-t- ‘cause to feed’ (Németh 1962: 88)<br />

eat-CAUS-CAUS-<br />

kapa-t-tɪr- ‘cause to make closed’ (Underhill 1976: 353)<br />

close-CAUS-CAUS-<br />

55


The distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs prevents two identical causative suffixes from occurring<br />

next to each other. Causative stems formed with the -DIr suffix will always be<br />

polysyllabic and /r/-final and will therefore take the -t allomorph if another causative is to<br />

be added. Stems formed with -t end in an obstruent and will therefore always take the<br />

suffix -DIr if a sec<strong>on</strong>d causative is used. Though Haig resists formulating specific<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straints against repeated morphs, he does acknowledge (to appear: 10) that the<br />

Turkish causative allomorphy ‘appears to c<strong>on</strong>spire to avoid’ adjacent suffixes that are<br />

identical in both their form and their meaning. Thus, it could be the case that the pattern<br />

seen here is ph<strong>on</strong>ologically optimizing, not in terms of syllable structure, but in terms of<br />

the avoidance of morpheme repetiti<strong>on</strong>. Note, however, that this cannot be what drives the<br />

allomorphy, since a c<strong>on</strong>straint against morpheme repetiti<strong>on</strong> would account for the<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs <strong>on</strong>ly in words with double causatives.<br />

An example of PCSA in a clitic that appears to optimize syllable structure is<br />

found in Moroccan Arabic (Harrell 1962; also discussed by Mascaró 1996). The 3sg<br />

masculine object/possessor clitic takes the form =h after a vowel-final stem and =u after<br />

a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stem (Harrell 1962: 135). Some examples are shown below (Harrell<br />

1962: 136).<br />

(31) xt ˁ a=h ‘his error’ mɛa=h ‘with him’<br />

šafu=h ‘they saw him’<br />

ktab=u ‘his book’ menn=u ‘from him’<br />

šaf=u ‘he saw him’<br />

Mascaró uses the c<strong>on</strong>straints ONSET and NOCODA to select the allomorphs, since the<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong> of the allomorphs maximizes <strong>on</strong>sets and minimizes coda c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants. This is<br />

our first example of PCSA involving a clitic rather than an affix (though since clitics<br />

56


ehave like affixes for ph<strong>on</strong>ological purposes, we expect them to exhibit PCSA just as<br />

affixes do).<br />

The a ~ an alternati<strong>on</strong> in the English indefinite article has been characterized as<br />

suppletive (Zwicky 1986) since there is no l<strong>on</strong>ger any general rule deleting /n/ before<br />

another c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant or epenthesizing [n] between vowels. Any such rule would have to be<br />

limited to applying <strong>on</strong>ly to the indefinite article. If we accept that the alternati<strong>on</strong> does<br />

involve suppleti<strong>on</strong>, we may view it as optimizing syllable structure because it provides an<br />

<strong>on</strong>set to V-initial words while avoiding a coda c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant. This then is another example of<br />

a clitic (in this case, a proclitic) participating in PCSA.<br />

Another example that seems to maximize alternating C-V sequences is found in<br />

Tzeltal (Mayan, Mexico; Slocum 1948, Kaufman 1971). The 2sg is marked by aw- before<br />

V-initial stems and by a- before C-initial stems in this language. Slocum (1948: 80)<br />

appears to assume that V-initial stems begin with underlying glottal stop, which would<br />

mean that the distributi<strong>on</strong> is determined by the presence of glottal stop. However, it<br />

seems possible that V-initial stems do not have underlying initial glottal stops, and<br />

Slocum does not provide evidence for them. Some examples are given below (Slocum<br />

1948: 80).<br />

(32) Ɂinam ‘wife’ aw-inam ‘your wife’<br />

(a)h-kanan ‘idol’ aw-ah-kanan ‘your idol’<br />

lumal ‘land’ a-lumal ‘your land’<br />

mamlal ‘husband’ a-mamlal ‘your husband’<br />

If the stems taking aw- do not have initial glottal stops, then we can say that the pattern<br />

maximizes <strong>on</strong>sets, since the use of a- with a vowel-initial stem would yield two <strong>on</strong>setless<br />

syllables. On the other hand, if these stems do have initial glottal stops, then the<br />

motivati<strong>on</strong> is not clear; for the moment, I will assume that these stems do not have initial<br />

57


glottal stops. According to Kaufman (1971: 11), [w] is allowed to occur in the<br />

envir<strong>on</strong>ment V_C, so the observed alternati<strong>on</strong> does not result from a general c<strong>on</strong>straint<br />

against wC in the language. Assuming there are true vowel-initial stems, then this<br />

example is parallel to the English a/an example in that it maximizes alternating C-V<br />

sequences and avoids both codas and vowel hiatus.<br />

Another example of PCSA possibly motivated by syllable structure c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s<br />

in Tzeltal is found in the 1sg marker. In Tzeltal, the 1sg is marked by k- with V-initial<br />

stems and h- with C-initial stems (Slocum 1948: 80).<br />

(33) (a)h-Ɂat’el ‘workman’ k-ah-Ɂat’el ‘my workman’<br />

Ɂakan ‘leg’ k-akan ‘my leg’<br />

k’ab ‘hand’ h-k’ab ‘my hand’<br />

talel ‘character’ h-talel ‘my character’<br />

The characterizati<strong>on</strong> of this pattern is complicated by the fact that, as menti<strong>on</strong>ed earlier,<br />

Slocum (1948: 80) apparently assumes that V-initial stems are underlyingly glottal stop-<br />

initial and undergo glottal stop deleti<strong>on</strong>. No evidence is given for this positi<strong>on</strong>. If it is true<br />

that these stems are glottal stop-initial, then the generalizati<strong>on</strong> here is that /k-/ occurs<br />

before glottal stop and /h-/ occurs before other c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants (or ‘elsewhere’). Either way,<br />

this appears to be a case of suppletive allomorphy because any rule of h → k before<br />

vowels (or before glottal stop, depending <strong>on</strong> the analysis) would be specific to the 1sg.<br />

The pattern could be driven by syllable structure c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s since hC is a<br />

pr<strong>on</strong>ounceable <strong>on</strong>set and could therefore be straightforwardly syllabified, while kC in<br />

many instances would result in an <strong>on</strong>set sequence that is difficult to produce and might<br />

therefore need to be broken up via epenthesis. This is avoided because of the distributi<strong>on</strong><br />

of allomorphs.<br />

58


A third example of PCSA in Tzeltal resulting in syllable structure optimizati<strong>on</strong> is<br />

in the 3rd pers<strong>on</strong> marker, which surfaces as y- before V-initial stems and s- before C-<br />

initial stems (Slocum 1948: 80).<br />

(34) Ɂahwal ‘ruler’ y-ahwal ‘his ruler’<br />

Ɂat’el ‘work’ y-at’el ‘his work’<br />

mul ‘sin’ s-mul ‘his sin’<br />

k’op ‘language’ s-k’op ‘his language’<br />

As with the 1sg prefix described above, the allomorphs of the 3rd pers<strong>on</strong> prefix could<br />

<strong>on</strong>ly be related to a single underlying form via an item-specific rule, so based <strong>on</strong><br />

Kiparsky’s (1996) criteria, this should be c<strong>on</strong>sidered suppletive allomorphy. As with the<br />

1sg prefix, the distributi<strong>on</strong> seen here optimizes syllables since it produces pr<strong>on</strong>ounceable<br />

<strong>on</strong>set clusters when the stem is c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-initial. If y- occurred in this positi<strong>on</strong>, we would<br />

have <strong>on</strong>sets with falling s<strong>on</strong>ority, which are universally dispreferred. Thus, <strong>on</strong>ce again,<br />

the pattern seen here can be said to optimize syllables.<br />

Modern Western Armenian (And<strong>on</strong>ian 1999) exhibits another example of PCSA<br />

that appears to optimize syllable structure, in this case by maximizing <strong>on</strong>sets and<br />

minimizing coda clusters. The definite article surfaces as -n after a vowel-final stem, and<br />

-ə after a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stem. Examples are shown below (And<strong>on</strong>ian 1999: 18, except<br />

where noted; transliterati<strong>on</strong>s based <strong>on</strong> And<strong>on</strong>ian 1999: 8-9).<br />

(35) lezu-n ‘t<strong>on</strong>gue’<br />

kini-n ‘wine’<br />

gadu-n ‘the cat’ (Vaux 1998: 252)<br />

atorr-ə ‘the chair’<br />

kirk-ə ‘the book’<br />

hat-ə ‘the piece’ (Vaux 1998: 252)<br />

The distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs results in an alternating C-V pattern that seems to be<br />

universally preferred. However, it should be noted that although this pattern does have<br />

59


the effect of providing <strong>on</strong>sets and preventing coda clusters, it creates codas when the<br />

stem is vowel-final; codas are said to be universally dispreferred, and therefore although<br />

the pattern is optimizing in some respects, this comes at a price. Thus, this example,<br />

though it can be said to optimize syllables, also foreshadows some examples (such as in<br />

Haitian Creole) to be discussed in §2.1.2.5 in which PCSA patterns referring to the C/V<br />

distincti<strong>on</strong> actually make syllable structure less optimal, not more.<br />

In Warrgamay (Pama-Nyungan, Australia; Dix<strong>on</strong> 1980: 266) as well as some<br />

other Pama-Nyungan languages (including Yidiɲ and Biri) 16 , ergative is marked by the<br />

suffix /-ŋgu/ after a vowel-final stem, or /-du/ after a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stem, as shown<br />

below.<br />

(36) ŋulmburu-ŋgu ‘woman-ERG’ wurrbi-ŋgu ‘big-ERG’<br />

wurrbi-bajun-du ‘very big-ERG’<br />

In this example, the optimizing effect is that CCC sequences are avoided. However, there<br />

is no reas<strong>on</strong> why the vowel-final stems could not also take the -du allomorph. If -du were<br />

the <strong>on</strong>ly surface form of the ergative suffix, this would also satisfy UNIFORMEXPONENCE<br />

or whatever other c<strong>on</strong>straint is used to ensure that in the usual case, each morphological<br />

category is marked by a single affix. Thus, we must have some way of making clear that<br />

the -du allomorph occurs <strong>on</strong>ly in the special case and that -ŋgu is the ‘elsewhere’<br />

allomorph. This problem is addressed by Wolf and McCarthy (to appear), who analyze a<br />

similar example in Dyirbal by stipulating a ‘priority relati<strong>on</strong>ship’ between the two<br />

allomorphs such that the higher priority suffix must be ‘tried first’, and if this fails to<br />

produce a well-formed output, then the other allomorph is used. Of course, this noti<strong>on</strong> of<br />

16<br />

These and other examples of ergative allomorphy in Pama-Nyungan are discussed in<br />

chapter 4, §4.2.<br />

60


the specific vs. elsewhere allomorphs must be accounted for regardless of the framework<br />

that is used to analyze the pattern. However, this seems less problematic in a<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>-based approach than in an approach where OT c<strong>on</strong>straints select the<br />

allomorphs, since the OT analysis advanced by Wolf and McCarthy seems to require the<br />

grammar to ‘try’ allomorphs in a sequential order that is antithetical to the parallel nature<br />

of OT. 17 Pama-Nyungan ergative allomorphy, including the Dyirbal example menti<strong>on</strong>ed<br />

here, will be discussed further in chapter 4 since many related cases involve c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing<br />

by syllable count rather than (or in additi<strong>on</strong> to) having to do with syllable structure as is<br />

the case here.<br />

An interesting example of syllable-optimizing allomorphy is found in Midob<br />

(Nubian, Sudan; Werner 1993), where the verbal extensi<strong>on</strong> denoting ‘affirmati<strong>on</strong>’ takes<br />

the form -nò- before a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-initial suffix and -nòn- before a vowel-initial suffix<br />

(Werner 1993: 50). The two available examples are reproduced below (Werner 1993: 49;<br />

interlinear glosses mine).<br />

(37) tii-nò-hèm tii-nòn-ùwà<br />

drink-affirm-1sg.perfect drink-affirm-1sg.c<strong>on</strong>tinuous.indicative<br />

‘I drank (completely/really)’ ‘I really drink completely’<br />

This example is striking because <strong>on</strong>e would assume that the order of affixati<strong>on</strong> is the<br />

same as the surface order of the morphemes. If true, this would mean that the grammar<br />

has to ‘look ahead’ when selecting the form of the affirmative affix since its distributi<strong>on</strong><br />

is based <strong>on</strong> whether the initial segment of the following morpheme is a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant or<br />

17 It is possible that Wolf and McCarthy’s characterizati<strong>on</strong> of this sequential ordering of<br />

tasks is <strong>on</strong>ly metaphorical and that the ‘priority relati<strong>on</strong>ship’ could be encoded in a way<br />

that does not require sequential ordering; Wolf and McCarthy do not spell out the specific<br />

mechanism by which the priority relati<strong>on</strong>ship is manifested.<br />

61


vowel. However, the example does not necessarily involve suppletive allomorphy; the<br />

fact that the two allomorphs are very similar is <strong>on</strong>e indicati<strong>on</strong> that it does not. A possible<br />

analysis not involving suppleti<strong>on</strong> is to say that the -nò form is based <strong>on</strong> /-nòn/ and<br />

undergoes deleti<strong>on</strong> of /n/ before another c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant. This analysis would not require any<br />

‘lookahead’ <strong>on</strong> the part of the grammar. However, the rule deleting /n/ would have to be<br />

specific to this c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>, because nC sequences are permitted elsewhere in the<br />

language, as in the following examples provided by Werner: èdéekìndóohèm ‘I sold’<br />

(1993: 23), kándír ‘<strong>on</strong> top’ (1993: 23), kúndúl ‘name of well’ (1993: 32), àndèn ‘that’<br />

(1993: 38), tìdánwà ‘I am a Midob’ (1993: 57), and àrdànkírídnûm ‘it surrounded’ (1993:<br />

81).<br />

An alternative, n<strong>on</strong>-suppletive analysis of this Midob example is in terms of a<br />

‘ghost’ or ‘latent’ c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant, as in some examples discussed by Zoll (1996). 18 Following<br />

the analysis assumed by Zoll for, e.g., latent c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants in French (1996: 32-33), we<br />

could assume that the affirmative suffix in Midob is /-nò(n)/, where the final /n/ is a latent<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant that <strong>on</strong>ly surfaces when followed by a vowel. We could formulate a rule or<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straints resulting in the inserti<strong>on</strong> of a root node in the envir<strong>on</strong>ment V_V, and the<br />

features of the latent /n/ could associate to this root node, so that the suffix would end up<br />

having the shape [-nòn]. In envir<strong>on</strong>ments in which a root node was not inserted (namely,<br />

before a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-initial ending), the features of the latent /n/ would simply be stray-<br />

erased, resulting in [-nò].<br />

On either analysis, the example does not necessarily involve suppletive<br />

allomorphy. This is important because, as menti<strong>on</strong>ed above, this would have been our<br />

18 Thanks to Shar<strong>on</strong> Inkelas for pointing out this alternative analysis.<br />

62


first example that seemed to be sensitive to properties of an affix ‘outside’ the affix in<br />

questi<strong>on</strong>, a situati<strong>on</strong> that otherwise seems not to be attested. This type of situati<strong>on</strong> is<br />

predicted by OT using P >> M, since in its standard form, this model has not included<br />

any sensitivity to morphological c<strong>on</strong>stituency, and therefore it predicts that PCSA can be<br />

sensitive to ph<strong>on</strong>ological elements anywhere in the word. The Midob example could<br />

therefore have c<strong>on</strong>firmed a predicti<strong>on</strong> of P >> M that otherwise has yet to be attested in<br />

the literature. However, because there are alternative analyses available (discussed above)<br />

that do not require lookahead, we cannot rely <strong>on</strong> this example as c<strong>on</strong>firmati<strong>on</strong> of the<br />

predicti<strong>on</strong>. What is needed is a similar example in which the allomorphs are so<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>etically distinct as to eliminate the possibility of an analysis in terms of latent<br />

segments. 19<br />

19<br />

Another similar example is found in Kashaya (Pomoan, northern California; Oswalt<br />

1960, Buckley 1994), where the negative suffix has two ph<strong>on</strong>ologically selected<br />

allomorphs, -t h and -t h i (Buckley 1994: 334). According to Buckley, the -t h allomorph<br />

occurs before a vowel, while the -t h i allomorph occurs before a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant, and the [i] in<br />

the prec<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal allomorph cannot be treated as epenthetic (Buckley 1994: 334). This<br />

pattern is of interest because, as in the Midob example, the selecti<strong>on</strong> of the negative in<br />

Kashaya seems to require the grammar to ‘look ahead’ to see what suffix will be added<br />

next and whether it begins with a vowel or a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant. The examples cited are moh-t h ‘it<br />

isn’t running across’ and moh-t h i-q h ‘it didn’t run out’ (Oswalt 1960: 234). Based <strong>on</strong> these<br />

forms, the generalizati<strong>on</strong> would have to refer to underlying segments rather than surface<br />

segments. Both of these forms in are claimed to c<strong>on</strong>tain the factitive marker, which<br />

appears to c<strong>on</strong>sist of a mora (since it lengthens a preceding vowel) and a t<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>tour<br />

which ‘...c<strong>on</strong>sists of a pause of variable durati<strong>on</strong> coupled with a slight lengthening of a<br />

preceding vowel, s<strong>on</strong>orant, or [mora]... and a fall in t<strong>on</strong>e and fade-out or diminuti<strong>on</strong> in<br />

force <strong>on</strong> the preceding syllable’ (Oswalt 1960: 30). It apparently does not affect<br />

obstruents, which is why it is omitted in the examples cited here. However, Oswalt seems<br />

to assume that the mora c<strong>on</strong>tributed by the factitive counts as a vowel for the purposes of<br />

the negative allomorphy. It is not clear whether there may be examples where the -t h<br />

allomorph occurs before a vowel that surfaces, or whether there may be some different<br />

generalizati<strong>on</strong> (for example, based solely <strong>on</strong> the examples provided, the generalizati<strong>on</strong><br />

could be that [i] is epenthesized between -t h and a following c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant). Even if the<br />

generalizati<strong>on</strong> is correct, we could analyze the [i] in terms of a latent /i/ (al<strong>on</strong>g the lines<br />

of the latent /n/ proposed for Midob above), since here again the allomorphs are very<br />

63


The durative suffix in Kashaya (Pomoan, northern California; Oswalt 1960,<br />

Buckley 1994) exhibits another pattern of allomorphy that seems to optimize syllable<br />

structure, though in this case there is no issue of ‘lookahead’. According to Buckley, the<br />

allomorphs are distributed as follows (1994: 328). ‘After a vowel-final stem, two<br />

allomorphs occur: -cin’ if the visible stem is m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic, otherwise -men’. When the<br />

stem ends in an /n’/ which is part of a suffix (rather than the root), the Durative is -icen'.<br />

After any c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant except the alveopalatals /c, c’/, including the case of /n’/ at the end<br />

of a root, the Durative is -an’.’ The uses of the durative suffix that are not covered in the<br />

descripti<strong>on</strong> given above involve very complex c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s that are partly morphologically<br />

determined and will not be discussed here. Some examples are shown below (Oswalt<br />

1960: 212-213). 20<br />

(38) sime-sime-ciˑd-u ‘to keep <strong>on</strong> sprinkling’ buwi-ciˑd-u ‘to keep <strong>on</strong> stringing’<br />

duk’ilci-meˑd-u ‘to keep pointing <strong>on</strong>ce’ mohqa-méˑd-u ‘to drive’<br />

mom-áˑd-u ‘to keep running across’ duhlud-áˑd-u ‘to keep picking <strong>on</strong>e’<br />

The shape of the allomorphs relates to the shape of the stems since the vowel-final stems<br />

take <strong>on</strong>e of two -CVC allomorphs, while most c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems take a -VC<br />

allomorph. This avoids both c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant clusters and vowel hiatus, and can therefore be<br />

said to have an overall optimizing effect <strong>on</strong> the syllable structure of the word.<br />

Also in Kashaya, the plural movement suffix (which denotes plural people or<br />

objects moving) has two variants whose distributi<strong>on</strong> could be said, at least in part, to<br />

similar, suggesting that they can reduce to a single underlying form and do not have a<br />

suppletive relati<strong>on</strong>ship.<br />

20<br />

Note that what Buckley refers to as -cin’ is transcribed as [ciˑd], Buckley’s -men’ is<br />

transcribed as [meˑd], and Buckley’s -an is transcribed as [aˑd].<br />

64


optimize syllable structure. The allomorphs are -h-, which is infixed before the final<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant of a C-final root, and -ht, which is suffixed after V-final roots (Buckley 1994:<br />

323). Some examples are provided below (Oswalt 1960: 154, 178).<br />

(39) mo-ht-an’- ‘they run al<strong>on</strong>g (caused by some outside force)’<br />

mo-ht-ac’ ‘they run al<strong>on</strong>g (of their own will)’<br />

ké,h,l-ala-w ‘several to peer down’<br />

du-k’í,h,s-im-’ ‘to scratch across several’<br />

The pattern seen here always results in stems ending in hC. This is suggestive of a pattern<br />

of ‘imbricati<strong>on</strong>’ 21 since all surface forms that are marked with some particular<br />

morphological category have a comm<strong>on</strong> shape that may be arrived at by fusing some part<br />

of the stem with some part of the affix. When necessary, a full versi<strong>on</strong> of the affix<br />

attaches in order to achieve the necessary surface shape, but in some cases the stem<br />

already c<strong>on</strong>tains some part of the output that would otherwise have been supplied by the<br />

affix, and it is in these instances where the imbricati<strong>on</strong> or fusi<strong>on</strong> occurs. In the case of the<br />

Kashaya plural movement suffix, we could say that forms marked for plural movement<br />

need to end in hC, and that if the stem ends in a vowel, the required hC is supplied<br />

straightforwardly by the -ht suffix. However, if the stem already ends in C, then the t of<br />

the suffix fuses with the final c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant of the stem, giving the appearance of having<br />

infixed -h-. This would account for the ph<strong>on</strong>etic similarity between the suffix allomorph<br />

and the apparent infixing allomorph.<br />

Under an analysis involving two separate allomorphs, -ht and -h-, this could still<br />

be viewed an example of PCSA that functi<strong>on</strong>s in order to fulfill a particular surface<br />

requirement. It also optimizes words in a more general way, in that it avoids a possible<br />

21<br />

This is a term used by Bantuists to describe patterns where an affix fuses with part of a<br />

stem; see Bastin 1983, Hyman 1995, and Hyman and Inkelas 1997.<br />

65


CCC cluster that would occur and need to undergo epenthesis if c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems<br />

took the -ht form. Thus, it optimizes syllable structure, and in particular it allows the<br />

grammar to avoid having to fix the syllable structure using the general strategy of<br />

epenthesis that is otherwise applied in order to break up c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant clusters. Under the<br />

analysis with two suppletive allomorphs, this is an example of an infix alternating with a<br />

suffix (which is an effect that is predicted by P >> M, though this is the first such<br />

example that we have seen so far). 22 Recall, however, that under an imbricati<strong>on</strong> analysis<br />

we would not necessarily assume that there are multiple underlying forms that mark<br />

plural movement in Kashaya.<br />

Another example where suppletive allomorphs differ in their positi<strong>on</strong> in the word<br />

is found in Biak (West New Guinean, New Guinea; discussed by Booij 2005: 174-175).<br />

In this language, the 2sg is marked by -w- or wa-, and the 3sg is marked by -y- or i-. The<br />

choice of whether a stem will take the prefix or the infix variant is lexically determined,<br />

but there is a clear ph<strong>on</strong>ological generalizati<strong>on</strong> involved as well, which is that all stems<br />

22<br />

Another Californian language that may have exhibited PCSA was Chimariko (Northern<br />

Hokan, Northwestern California; Dix<strong>on</strong> 1910). According to C<strong>on</strong>athan (2002), based <strong>on</strong><br />

the unpublished field notes of George Grekoff, a set of pr<strong>on</strong>ominal markers had different<br />

forms and positi<strong>on</strong>s in the word that may have been ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed, such that<br />

vowel-initial stems took prefixes while c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-initial stems took suffixes. There are<br />

two classes of verbs (C<strong>on</strong>athan’s set I and set II) that take different sets of affixes, and<br />

there may have been additi<strong>on</strong>al factors involved, but Grekoff’s analysis was purely<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological aside from the distincti<strong>on</strong> between sets I and II (C<strong>on</strong>athan 2002: 24).<br />

Examples from Grekoff’s notes appear to support the generalizati<strong>on</strong> (if <strong>on</strong>e assumes that<br />

some roots assumed by Dix<strong>on</strong> (1910) to be vowel-initial actually have underlying initial<br />

glottal stops). These include forms (C<strong>on</strong>athan 2002: 20) with vowel-initial roots /y-ama/<br />

‘I eat’ (set I) and /čhu-iman-damu-t/ ‘I fell down’ (set II), and forms with c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antinitial<br />

roots /kow-Ɂi/ ‘I holler’ (set I) and /čheleɁ-či-t/ ‘I am black’ (set II). However, this<br />

is not a clear-cut example of PCSA since other researchers (e.g., Dix<strong>on</strong> 1910) proposed<br />

other analyses involving semantic rather than ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing.<br />

66


with an initial c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant cluster take the prefix variants for both affixes. Some examples<br />

are shown below (Booij 2005: 175).<br />

(40) stem 2sg 3sg gloss<br />

a. ra r,w,a r,y,a to go<br />

b. rov wa-rov i-rov to fly<br />

c. kvok wa-kvok i-kvok to stand up<br />

snai wa-snai i-snai to be clear<br />

smai wa-smai i-smai to have<br />

A comparis<strong>on</strong> of examples (40)a and b shows that the allomorphy is partly lexically<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed, since these stems have the same <strong>on</strong>set but take different allomorphs of the<br />

2sg and 3sg affixes. The examples in (40)c, <strong>on</strong> the other hand, are representative of all<br />

stems in the language having an initial c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant cluster. Stems of this type invariably<br />

take the prefix allomorphs. This can be seen as an example of syllable structure<br />

optimizati<strong>on</strong> because if these stems took the infixing allomorphs, the result would be<br />

initial CCC clusters, which are avoided by using the prefix allomorphs of the 2sg and<br />

3sg.<br />

In Korean, as discussed by Odden (1993), some suffixes exhibit allomorphy based<br />

<strong>on</strong> whether the stem-final segment is a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant or a vowel. The accusative is marked<br />

by -rɨl after a vowel and -ɨl after a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant; the topic marker takes the form -nɨn after a<br />

vowel and -ɨn after a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant, and the nominative is marked by -i after a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant and<br />

-ka after a vowel (Odden 1993: 133). Some examples are shown below (this example is<br />

reproduced directly from Odden 1993: 133).<br />

(41) citati<strong>on</strong>: param pori<br />

nominative: param-i pori-ka<br />

accusative: param-ɨl pori-rɨl<br />

topic: param-ɨn pori-nɨn<br />

‘wind’ ‘barley’<br />

67


Odden advocates writing (presumably item-specific) rules deleting the initial c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants<br />

of the CVC forms of the accusative and topic suffixes to generate the postc<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal<br />

allomorphs. The nominative alternati<strong>on</strong> looks more like suppletive allomorphy, but<br />

Odden posits a rule of Nominative Destructuring (1993: 134), which derives the -i<br />

allomorph from /-ka/ by deleting all of the segmental c<strong>on</strong>tent of /-ka/, resulting in a mora<br />

not associated to any segmental features. The mora then acquires some features via<br />

default rules, and ends up surfacing as [i]. While it seems reas<strong>on</strong>able in some cases to<br />

posit item-specific rules rather than suppletive allomorphs, this is probably best limited to<br />

cases where the allomorphs are very similar in their surface ph<strong>on</strong>ological shape (not the<br />

case with -i vs. -ka) and where the rule relating the allomorphs is a natural rule that is<br />

also attested in other languages (also not true of the proposed Nominative Destructuring<br />

rule). Although we cannot rule out the possibility that the allomorphs do have a single<br />

underlying form and that Nominative Destructuring is resp<strong>on</strong>sible for the allomorphy, I<br />

will assume for cases like this that there are two underlying forms, not <strong>on</strong>ly for the<br />

reas<strong>on</strong>s given above but also because it seems likely that a language learner will posit<br />

multiple underlying forms if the allomorphs are not similar in shape. Thus, I c<strong>on</strong>clude<br />

that the nominative -i ~ -ka should count as a case of suppletive allomorphy c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed<br />

by C vs. V-final stems and resulting in well-formed syllables. The accusative and topic<br />

allomorphy examples, <strong>on</strong> the other hand, are not necessarily suppletive since both could<br />

be derived via a rule deleting a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant after another c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant (which, even if not a<br />

general rule of the language, would generalize at least to these two suffixes).<br />

Also in Korean (Martin 1954: 28, 37-39) there two main verb classes, determined<br />

by whether the root is c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant- or vowel-final. Although Martin characterizes these as<br />

68


lexical classes, they are n<strong>on</strong>etheless unified by a ph<strong>on</strong>ological criteri<strong>on</strong>. There are several<br />

verb suffixes that have separate forms for the two classes of roots, including the<br />

h<strong>on</strong>orific, formal, prospective, processive, declarative, imperative, modifier, adversative<br />

and extended adversative, sequential and extended sequential, substantive, c<strong>on</strong>junctive<br />

and extended c<strong>on</strong>junctive, c<strong>on</strong>tingent, assumptive, intentive, purportive, frustrated<br />

intentive, prospective assertive, prospective attentive, intentive assertive, and cajolative<br />

suffixes. Interestingly, the difference between the two forms of each suffix is not the<br />

same in every case. For example, some suffixes (such as the authoritative indicative<br />

assertive -so ~ -o) have an initial s with vowel-final roots corresp<strong>on</strong>ding to Ø with<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final roots; others (such as the c<strong>on</strong>junctive -mye ~ -umye) have initial u with<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final roots corresp<strong>on</strong>ding to Ø with vowel-final roots; others (such as the<br />

formal indicative assertive -sumnita ~ -mnita) have both s and u with c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final<br />

roots corresp<strong>on</strong>ding to Ø with vowel-final roots; while yet others (such as the plain<br />

processive assertive -nunta ~ -nta) have n and u after c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final roots corresp<strong>on</strong>ding<br />

to Ø with vowel-final roots. Because the different suffixes have different<br />

corresp<strong>on</strong>dences between allomorphs that occur with c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant vs. vowel-final roots, any<br />

rules written to derive the allomorphy would have to be specific to certain affixes or sets<br />

of affixes. We could potentially approach these examples using a ‘latent segment’<br />

analysis such as the <strong>on</strong>es proposed earlier for Midob and Kashaya. Thus, each of these<br />

affixes may not necessarily exhibit PCSA.<br />

Kager (1996) discusses a case of allomorphy in Dja:bugay (Pama-Nyungan,<br />

Australia; Patz 1991) that seems to optimize syllable structure. In Dja:bugay, the genitive<br />

suffix has an -n allomorph that occurs with vowel-final stems, and a -ŋun allomorph that<br />

69


follows c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems. Some examples are shown below (examples are from Patz<br />

1991: 269 except where a different page number is given in parentheses).<br />

(42) guludu-n ‘dove-GEN’ girrgirr-ŋun ‘bush canary-GEN’<br />

gurra:-n ‘dog-GEN’ gaɲal-ŋun ‘goanna-GEN’<br />

djama-n ‘snake-GEN’ bibuy-ŋun ‘child-GEN’<br />

ɲurra-n ‘2sg-GEN’ (272)<br />

According to Kager (1996: 155), Dja:bugay does not allow coda clusters, which could<br />

account for the fact that c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems take -ŋun instead of -n. However, as Kager<br />

acknowledges (1996: 156), this accounts for <strong>on</strong>ly part of the distributi<strong>on</strong>, since there<br />

appears to be no reas<strong>on</strong> why vowel-final stems cannot also take -ŋun. This means that we<br />

must have some way of encoding the noti<strong>on</strong> of the specific allomorph and the elsewhere<br />

allomorph. A similar problem was encountered in the Warrgamay example in §2.1.2.3.<br />

In Dakota (Siouan, northern United States; Shaw 1980), the 1du/pl marker is<br />

marked by either ų- or ųk- depending <strong>on</strong> whether the stem begins with a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant or a<br />

vowel, respectively. Examples of the prec<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal allomorph are shown below (Shaw<br />

1980: 77). 23<br />

(43) ų-híyu ‘we (dual) start to come’<br />

ų-híyaya ‘we (dual) go past’<br />

ų-xá=pi ‘we (pl.) bury’<br />

ų-xą́=pi ‘we (pl.) do, work’<br />

ų-k’a ‘we dig it’ (Shaw 1980: 193) 24<br />

23<br />

Shaw includes the word-initial glottal stops that are inserted by rule; I omit these here.<br />

24<br />

This example is from the Tet<strong>on</strong> dialect rather than the Santee dialect, which is the<br />

primary source of Shaw’s data.<br />

70


As seen below, vowel-initial stems take the ųk- prefix (Shaw 1980: 71; data are from the<br />

Tet<strong>on</strong> dialect).<br />

(44) ųk-ípi ‘we go’<br />

ųk-úpi ‘we are coming’<br />

ųk-ų́spepi ‘we know how’<br />

However, there is further evidence from the behavior of Ɂ-initial stems suggesting that the<br />

pattern of allomorphy seen here may not be suppletive. Ɂ-initial stems, rather than<br />

patterning with other c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-initial stems in taking the ų- allomorph (as would be<br />

predicted under the ONSET-driven approach), take the ųk- allomorph, as shown below<br />

(Shaw 1980: 71). The glottal stop surfaces as glottalizati<strong>on</strong> of the /k/ of the prefix.<br />

(45) ųk-’į́yąka ‘we run’<br />

ųk-’į́pi ‘we wear it’<br />

ųk-’ų́pi ‘we use it’<br />

ųk-’ópi ‘we shoot it’<br />

In these examples, the roots must have underlying initial glottal stops, because they differ<br />

minimally from the true vowel-initial stems in glottalizing the /k/ of the prefix. There are<br />

near-minimal pairs in the data above that illustrate this point; e.g., ųk-úpi ‘we are coming’<br />

vs. ųk-’ų́pi ‘we use it’.<br />

We can account for the behavior of the glottal stop-initial stems if we assume that<br />

the 1du/pl marker has a single underlying form, /ųk-/. The /k/ is deleted before another<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant, with the excepti<strong>on</strong> of /Ɂ/ (this is Shaw’s analysis (1980:77)). The<br />

excepti<strong>on</strong>ality of /Ɂ/ can be handled in <strong>on</strong>e of at least two different ways. The first would<br />

be to assume that the rule deleting /k/ is triggered by a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant with a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-place<br />

71


node. This would prevent /Ɂ/ from triggering the rule if we assume that /Ɂ/ has no place<br />

features. Alternatively, we could capture the pattern using rule ordering or its equivalent<br />

translati<strong>on</strong> into OT c<strong>on</strong>straints, the idea being that the fusi<strong>on</strong> of the glottal stop with the<br />

/k/ of the prefix prevents the deleti<strong>on</strong> of /k/, either because fusi<strong>on</strong> applies ‘first’ or<br />

because it is preferenced by the c<strong>on</strong>straint ranking. 25<br />

We have seen a number of examples here in which allomorphy is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by<br />

the C/V distincti<strong>on</strong> and results in optimal syllable structure (in terms of eliminating codas<br />

or c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant clusters, or providing syllable <strong>on</strong>sets). In every case, it is the stem that<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s allomorphy in an affix, and the stem segment that c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s the allomorphy is<br />

immediately adjacent to the affix in questi<strong>on</strong>.<br />

2.1.2.4 Syllable c<strong>on</strong>tact c<strong>on</strong>straint satisfacti<strong>on</strong><br />

Another ph<strong>on</strong>ological factor that we might expect to c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> PCSA is syllable<br />

c<strong>on</strong>tact. In many languages (see Gouskova 2004 for examples and discussi<strong>on</strong>), codas are<br />

required to have higher s<strong>on</strong>ority than a following <strong>on</strong>set, or at least not to exceed the<br />

following <strong>on</strong>set in s<strong>on</strong>ority by more than a specified amount. The Syllable C<strong>on</strong>tact Law<br />

(SCL) was formulated for this purpose (see Davis 1998, Rose 2000b for recent<br />

25<br />

McCarthy and Prince (1993a) discuss this affix in Dakota, but focus <strong>on</strong> a set of stems<br />

including ali ‘climb’ and manų ‘steal’ that are said to be lexically specified as taking<br />

infixed rather than prefixed pers<strong>on</strong> marking (Shaw 1980 does not discuss these stems).<br />

McCarthy and Prince cite two examples, ųk-ali ‘we (du.) climb’ and ma-ų-nų ‘we (du.)<br />

steal’ (1993a: 114) in support of the claim that the use of prefixed ųk- in ųk-ali is<br />

determined by ranking the ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint ONSET over the morphological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straint ALIGN-ROOT. Though it is implied that these c<strong>on</strong>straints are also resp<strong>on</strong>sible<br />

for the selecti<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs, the selecti<strong>on</strong> follows naturally from the generalizati<strong>on</strong><br />

that vowel-initial stems take ųk- while c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-initial stems take ų-, and it is really the<br />

placement of the affix (prefix vs. infix) that is relevant in McCarthy and Prince’s<br />

discussi<strong>on</strong>.<br />

72


implementati<strong>on</strong>s). Most recently, Gouskova (2004) has proposed a hierarchy of relati<strong>on</strong>al<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straints to account for the range of syllable c<strong>on</strong>tact effects found in a number of<br />

languages. Regardless of the specific implementati<strong>on</strong>, many analyses make use of<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints to account for syllable c<strong>on</strong>tact phenomena, and therefore the P<br />

>> M model predicts that we should find cases of PCSA driven by these c<strong>on</strong>straints. Two<br />

possible examples of this were found in the present survey, both in Martuthunira (Pama-<br />

Nyungan, Australia; Dench 1995), though as will be discussed, these may not be true<br />

cases of suppletive allomorphy.<br />

The first example is found in the accusative and genitive suffixes in Martuthunira,<br />

which exhibit allomorphy based <strong>on</strong> the root-final segment when marking comm<strong>on</strong> nouns<br />

(Dench 1995: 63). Following a nasal, the accusative and the genitive take the form -ku<br />

((46)a). Following a lateral or rhotic, both suffixes take the form -yu ((46)b) (the <strong>on</strong>ly<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants allowed at the end of a word are nasals, laterals, and rhotics (Dench 1995:<br />

30); this apparently holds for roots as well). With vowel-final stems, the accusative<br />

lengthens the final vowel, while the genitive is marked by -wu ((46)c) (examples are from<br />

Dench 1995: 91 except where page numbers are given).<br />

(46) a. tharlwan-ku-wuyu<br />

tame-ACC-SIDE<br />

‘<strong>on</strong> the tame side’ (98)<br />

b. tharratal-yu<br />

bird(sp.)-GEN<br />

‘tharratal’s’<br />

c. nhartu-u nganaju-wu-lu yaan-tu<br />

something-ACC 1SG.OBL-GEN-EFF spouse-EFF<br />

‘(about) something’ (98) ‘...by my wife’<br />

The alternati<strong>on</strong> involving c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant feature assimilati<strong>on</strong> is the -ku ~ -yu alternati<strong>on</strong><br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by nasal vs. liquid-final roots, respectively. According to Dench, ‘a number<br />

73


of morphemes’ exhibit leniti<strong>on</strong> of k to y after a stem-final lateral or rhotic (1995: 38), but<br />

the <strong>on</strong>ly morpheme that is cited as exhibiting the alternati<strong>on</strong> aside from the accusative<br />

and genitive is the ‘body-noise’ verbal derivati<strong>on</strong>al suffix, which takes the form -karri<br />

after nasals and -yarri after laterals and rhotics (1995: 38). It is not clear what form the<br />

body-noise suffix takes after vowels since the suffix is not fully productive.<br />

Another, related example is the ‘bel<strong>on</strong>ging’ suffix in Martuthunira, which takes<br />

the form -ngura when marking proper nouns, pr<strong>on</strong>ouns, and dem<strong>on</strong>stratives; otherwise,<br />

the suffix -kura is used after nasals ((47)a), and -wura after a vowel, rhotic, or lateral<br />

((47)b) (Dench 1995: 64). Some examples are given below (Dench 1995: 91).<br />

(47) a. ngurnu-ngura parnparn-kura<br />

that.OBL-BELONG budgerigar-BELONG<br />

‘...bel<strong>on</strong>ging to that budgerigar...’<br />

b. yirna-tharra-wura-a kanparr-wura<br />

this.OBL-DU-BELONG-ACC spider-BELONG<br />

‘...the <strong>on</strong>es bel<strong>on</strong>ging to these two’ ‘...of the spider’s...’<br />

The relevant alternati<strong>on</strong> here is the k ~ w alternati<strong>on</strong> between nasals vs. rhotics and<br />

laterals. This parallels the situati<strong>on</strong> for the accusative, genitive, and body-noise suffixes<br />

described above, except that in this case k alternates with w instead of y. The bel<strong>on</strong>ging<br />

suffix is apparently the <strong>on</strong>ly suffix to exhibit this particular alternati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

C<strong>on</strong>sidering <strong>on</strong>ly the allomorphs that occur after c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants here, both of these<br />

examples from Martuthunira can be analyzed in terms of syllable c<strong>on</strong>tact. In both cases, a<br />

possible generalizati<strong>on</strong> is that s<strong>on</strong>ority is not allowed to increase by three or more points<br />

<strong>on</strong> the syllable c<strong>on</strong>tact scale as formulated by Gouskova (2004: 211). Gouskova (2004:<br />

208) uses the s<strong>on</strong>ority scale laid out by Jespersen (1904: 191): glides > rhotics > laterals<br />

> nasals > voiced fricatives > voiced stops > voiceless fricatives > voiceless stops.<br />

74


Applying this scale to the accusative/genitive suffix, we see that the sequence n.k is<br />

permitted, and r.y is permitted, while n.y does not occur. On Gouskova’s scale, these<br />

sequences would corresp<strong>on</strong>d to a change in s<strong>on</strong>ority of -4, +1, and +3, respectively. If the<br />

grammar does not allow an increase of three points between the coda and following<br />

<strong>on</strong>set, then we can account for why n.y is not allowed and why the accusative/genitive<br />

surfaces as -ku instead of -yu after nasals. The same principle can be applied to the<br />

bel<strong>on</strong>ging suffix allomorphs -kura and -wura. The sequence n.w would result in a change<br />

of +3, which is not allowed, and therefore the -kura allomorph is used after nasals. We<br />

could use the relati<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>straints used by Gouskova (2004) to account for this<br />

phenomen<strong>on</strong> in a P >> M analysis.<br />

However, a P >> M analysis may not be necessary. It is unclear whether glide ~ k<br />

alternati<strong>on</strong>s involve suppletive allomorphy. If we assumed that the glide-initial allomorph<br />

were the underlying form in each case, then we could write a single ph<strong>on</strong>ological rule or<br />

set of c<strong>on</strong>straints that could change a glide into [k] after a nasal, either because of the<br />

syllable c<strong>on</strong>tact principles discussed here, or perhaps because the feature [-c<strong>on</strong>tinuant]<br />

spreads from the nasal to the glide. This would account for all of the forms of the<br />

bel<strong>on</strong>ging suffix and also the postc<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal allomorphs of the accusative/genitive<br />

suffixes, leaving <strong>on</strong>ly the postvocalic forms of the accusative/genitive to account for. We<br />

may need to posit separate postvocalic allomorphs /-V/ and /-wu/ for the accusative and<br />

genitive suffixes, respectively. These would probably be c<strong>on</strong>sidered suppletive<br />

allomorphs, and note that their distributi<strong>on</strong> does not appear to be optimizing; this<br />

anticipates some examples to be discussed in the following secti<strong>on</strong> in which entire<br />

patterns of suppletive allomorphy are n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing or even detrimental in terms of<br />

75


well-formedness.<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong>, we have seen two examples from Martuthunira in which<br />

allomorphy seems to result in optimized syllable c<strong>on</strong>tact c<strong>on</strong>figurati<strong>on</strong>s. As discussed,<br />

though, these cases may not necessarily involve suppletive allomorphy, and therefore we<br />

cannot be sure that we have a case of PCSA driven by syllable c<strong>on</strong>tact c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s.<br />

2.1.2.5 N<strong>on</strong>-optimizati<strong>on</strong><br />

Though the examples in the preceding secti<strong>on</strong>s have all been cases where the<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs can be c<strong>on</strong>strued as ph<strong>on</strong>ologically optimizing or at least could<br />

arguably be accounted for using ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints that have already been<br />

proposed in the literature, this is by no means always the case (see, e.g., Paster 2005a <strong>on</strong><br />

n<strong>on</strong>-optimizati<strong>on</strong> in ‘syllable-counting allomorphy’, a type of PCSA to be discussed in<br />

chapter 4; see also Bye to appear for several examples and discussi<strong>on</strong> of n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing<br />

PCSA). In many instances, PCSA is neutral or even detrimental with respect to the<br />

overall well-formedness of the word. Such ‘n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing’ examples are discussed in<br />

this secti<strong>on</strong>. An important point should made here, which is that I do not claim that there<br />

are no ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints that have ever been proposed or will be proposed that<br />

could possibly account for the allomorphy exhibited in these examples. Presumably there<br />

is some P >> M account that could be proposed for every example if we allow the use of<br />

stipulated, language-specific P c<strong>on</strong>straints. However, as will become clear in the<br />

presentati<strong>on</strong> of examples, characterizing these examples in terms of optimizati<strong>on</strong> would<br />

be to mischaracterize them. They do not appear to relate to any universal well-<br />

76


formedness generalizati<strong>on</strong>s, nor does any example appear to follow from the general<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>otactics of the language.<br />

Under P >> M, we do not expect n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing PCSA to be very comm<strong>on</strong> since<br />

their ph<strong>on</strong>ological counterparts, ‘crazy rules’ (Bach and Harms 1972), though attested,<br />

are not particularly comm<strong>on</strong> and do not result from universal ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints. 26<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong>, we will see many examples of PCSA that are n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing. In an OT<br />

account using P >> M, each of these cases would require a language-specific, stipulated<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straint to create the pattern of allomorphy. This is also true of crazy rules, but the<br />

PCSA examples are more problematic because it seems that n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing examples of<br />

PCSA are more frequent relative to the total number of examples of PCSA than crazy<br />

rules are to the total number of attested ph<strong>on</strong>ological rules.<br />

There are 12 examples to be discussed in this secti<strong>on</strong>. The first set of examples<br />

includes cases where PCSA is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by the C/V distincti<strong>on</strong> but the pattern<br />

n<strong>on</strong>etheless does not seem to involve syllable structure optimizati<strong>on</strong>. These examples can<br />

be c<strong>on</strong>trasted with those presented in §2.1.2.3, where some instances of C/V c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed<br />

allomorphy seemed to optimize syllables by avoiding c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant clusters and/or vowel<br />

hiatus. The existence of the examples to be discussed here dem<strong>on</strong>strates that PCSA can<br />

refer directly and arbitrarily to the C/V distincti<strong>on</strong>, and that this does not always reduce to<br />

syllable structure c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s. As will be seen, in every case, the relevant c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant or<br />

vowel of the stem is at the edge of stem where the affix attaches.<br />

26<br />

In fact, if we assume a versi<strong>on</strong> of OT in which c<strong>on</strong>straints are universal and cannot be<br />

language-specific, then under P >> M we would never expect to find n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing<br />

PCSA (though a versi<strong>on</strong> of OT with universal c<strong>on</strong>straints would have difficulty handling<br />

crazy rules as well, so presumably whatever ‘patch’ were applied to the model to account<br />

for crazy rules could also account for n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing PCSA).<br />

77


One example of apparently n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing allomorphy c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by the C/V<br />

distincti<strong>on</strong> is found in Turkish (Lewis 1967). The Turkish passive is marked by -n<br />

following a stem ending in a vowel ((48)a) or in /l/ ((48)b), and by -l elsewhere ((48)c).<br />

Examples are shown below (Underhill 1976: 332).<br />

(48) a. ara-n- ‘be sought’<br />

de-n- ‘be said’<br />

oku-n- ‘be read<br />

b. çal-ɪn- ‘be struck’<br />

bil-in- ‘be known’<br />

c. kullan-ɪl- ‘be used’<br />

yor-ul- ‘be tired’<br />

kaybed-il- ‘be lost’<br />

We can treat the alternati<strong>on</strong> between -C and -VC forms of each allomorph as epenthetic,<br />

so we are left with two underlying forms, -n and -l, whose distributi<strong>on</strong> is determined<br />

primarily by the C/V distincti<strong>on</strong> with no apparent optimizing effect <strong>on</strong> syllable structure<br />

or any other aspect of well-formedness. This is an example in which C/V c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed<br />

PCSA cannot be driven by syllable structure c<strong>on</strong>straints. The overall pattern of<br />

allomorphy in the passive suffix is not entirely arbitrary, however, since the use of -n<br />

with stems ending in /l/ is dissimilatory. Turkish does not exhibit s<strong>on</strong>orant dissimilati<strong>on</strong><br />

elsewhere in the system (Kornfilt 1997: 510-511), so this aspect of the allomorphy could<br />

be suppletive as well, though the dissimilati<strong>on</strong> could also be said to result from an item-<br />

specific dissimilati<strong>on</strong> rule. Regardless, the pattern of allomorphy involving the distincti<strong>on</strong><br />

between c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant- and vowel-final stems does not appear to be optimizing in any way.<br />

An interesting observati<strong>on</strong> about this pattern is that, as with the Turkish causative<br />

suffixes described in §2.1.2.3, the allomorphy prevents sequences of identical affixes, as<br />

discussed by Haig (to appear). In Turkish words with a ‘double passive’, the two passive<br />

allomorphs will never have the same shape, since the attachment of <strong>on</strong>e variant to form<br />

78


the first passive automatically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s the use of the other variant to form the double<br />

passive. When the first passive is marked by -n, then the sec<strong>on</strong>d passive is marked by -l,<br />

and vice versa. Examples are from Underhill (1976: 332), except where noted.<br />

(49) de-n-il- ‘say (double passive)’<br />

iste-n-il- ‘want (double passive)’<br />

döv-ül-ün- ‘hit (double passive)’ (Haig to appear: 5)<br />

It is possible that avoidance of repeated morphemes had something to do with the<br />

historical origins of the modern allomorphy pattern, but just as in the causative example<br />

discussed earlier, this cannot be resp<strong>on</strong>sible for the overall pattern. Using a c<strong>on</strong>straint<br />

against repeated morphemes would account <strong>on</strong>ly for the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs in<br />

words with double causatives and would not explain the pattern as a whole. Thus, we still<br />

need either an item-specific rule of dissimilati<strong>on</strong> or a subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>al requirement to<br />

account for the use of -n with l-final stems.<br />

An unusual case of n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing C/V-sensitive PCSA is found in Mafa<br />

(Chadic, Camero<strong>on</strong>). Le Bleis and Barreteau (1987) report that in the verbal suffix<br />

indicating ‘le directi<strong>on</strong>nel de rapprochement’ occurs as -ká when preceding a word that<br />

begins with a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant, and as -káɗá elsewhere (Le Bleis and Barreteau 1987: 108-109;<br />

English translati<strong>on</strong>s mine).<br />

(50) á mbálə-ká kəda<br />

il-INACC chasser-RAPPR chien<br />

‘il court après le chien vers nous’<br />

[‘he runs after the dog towards us’]<br />

m ɓálə-ká yim (á duwzlak)<br />

(no interlinear glosses provided)<br />

‘il a puisé de l’eau (l’a versée dans la jarre) et l’a rapportée’<br />

[‘he drew some water (poured it in the jar) and brought it back’]<br />

79


n tə́v-káɗa aa gírzhe<br />

il-ACC m<strong>on</strong>ter-RAPPR sur rocher<br />

‘il est m<strong>on</strong>té sur le rocher (qui se trouve entre l’endroit d’où il vient et celui où se<br />

trouve le locateur)’<br />

[‘he climbed <strong>on</strong>to the rock (which is located between the locati<strong>on</strong> from which he<br />

came and the locati<strong>on</strong> of the speaker)’]<br />

kalədə-káɗá<br />

tomber.CAUS-RAPPR<br />

‘jette-le vers moi!’<br />

[‘throw it towards me!’]<br />

This example is particularly interesting in that the allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong> seems to be<br />

determined by a property of a separate word from the <strong>on</strong>e to which the affix in questi<strong>on</strong><br />

bel<strong>on</strong>gs. No other examples having this property were revealed by the survey. Even in the<br />

case of English a/an discussed in §2.1.2.3, the morpheme that is affected is a clitic and<br />

therefore part of the same ph<strong>on</strong>ological word as what follows despite being a separate<br />

morphosyntactic word. We do not have evidence for the directi<strong>on</strong>al morpheme in Mafa<br />

being a clitic; it is not described as having other properties that we could use to argue that<br />

it is a clitic rather than an affix (for example, it seems always to occur immediately after<br />

the verb stem rather than allowing other words to intervene). However, perhaps with<br />

more data we could argue that this morpheme is, in fact, a clitic. In any case, since it is<br />

the <strong>on</strong>ly apparent example exhibiting c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing by a separate ph<strong>on</strong>ological word, we<br />

do not have enough evidence to c<strong>on</strong>clude that PCSA in an affix can refer to a property of<br />

a separate ph<strong>on</strong>ological word.<br />

Aside from the problem of the word-external c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing, another point to be<br />

made regarding the Mafa example is that there is no apparent functi<strong>on</strong>al motivati<strong>on</strong> for<br />

the distributi<strong>on</strong> of the allomorphs. Both allomorphs are vowel-final and should syllabify<br />

equally well with the following word regardless of whether it is c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant- or vowel-<br />

80


initial. Therefore, this is another case of PCSA whose effect is neutral rather than<br />

optimizing.<br />

Another case of PCSA c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants vs. vowels is found in<br />

Winnebago (Siouan, Wisc<strong>on</strong>sin; Lipkind 1945). Here, the declarative is marked by the<br />

suffix /-nə̃/ after vowel-final roots and by /-səńə̃/ after c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final roots, as shown in<br />

the examples below (Lipkind 1945: 33). No examples of the postc<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal allomorph<br />

are given.<br />

(51) wa-jəra sepsə́-nə̃ nãná tira-je-nə̃<br />

boat-DEF black-DEC tree-DEF move-standing.positi<strong>on</strong>-DEC<br />

‘the boat was black’ ‘the tree is growing’<br />

wasí-nə̃-gi nã-wãnã-nə̃<br />

dance-COND-SUBORD sing.1sg-COND-DEC<br />

‘if he danced I would sing’<br />

Despite the fact that we can recognize the post-vocalic allomorph in the shape of the<br />

post-c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal allomorph, this is a clear case of suppleti<strong>on</strong> because if these allomorphs<br />

reduced to a single underlying form, we would have to write a highly unnatural and<br />

unusual rule inserting or deleting [sə́]. It is possible that /sə́/ could be a separate<br />

morpheme, perhaps an empty morpheme that is added to c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final roots to form<br />

stems. However, even if this is true, there is no apparent motivati<strong>on</strong> for its presence in<br />

that envir<strong>on</strong>ment. Regardless of whether /sə́/ is a separate morpheme or just a part of the<br />

/-səńə̃/ allomorph, its distributi<strong>on</strong> is still arbitrary and n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing since it does not<br />

affect syllable structure or any other apparent factor in the well-formedness of words in<br />

Winnebago. The c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> allomorphy (the C/V distincti<strong>on</strong>) does not seem to relate to<br />

the differences between the allomorphs (the most salient of which is their syllable count).<br />

81


Another case in which PCSA is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by the C/V distincti<strong>on</strong> but does not<br />

result in syllable structure optimizati<strong>on</strong> is found in Jivaro (Jivaroan, Ecuador; de Maria<br />

1918). In Jivaro, the negative is marked by <strong>on</strong>e of two suffix allomorphs, as follows (de<br />

Maria 1918: 9). Am<strong>on</strong>g nouns, adjectives, and adverbs, all stems ending in a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant<br />

take the negative suffix -cha. Also, ‘some’ verbs take -cha (this is not addressed further,<br />

so apparently verbs have lexically specified negative forms). Am<strong>on</strong>g vowel-final stems,<br />

there is a distincti<strong>on</strong> between m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic and polysyllabic stems. All polysyllabic<br />

vowel-final stems take -chu. Am<strong>on</strong>g m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic stems, those ending in /e/, /i/, or /a/<br />

take -cha. All other stems are said to take -chu (though no examples of m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic<br />

stems not ending in /e/, /i/, or /a/ are given). The distributi<strong>on</strong> is shown in the examples<br />

below (de Maria 1918: 9).<br />

(52) Apár-cha ‘no padre’<br />

Puéngar-cha ‘no bueno’<br />

Aho-chu ‘no él’<br />

Tuná-chu ‘no t<strong>on</strong>to’<br />

Ví-cha-itijae ‘no soy yo’<br />

Though this is a complicated pattern, the element of PCSA here seems to be that<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems take the -cha allomorph and vowel-final stems take the -chu<br />

allomorph (though, as to be discussed, the vowel of this suffix undergoes a vowel<br />

harm<strong>on</strong>y rule that complicates the picture). Looking <strong>on</strong>ly at the suppletive distributi<strong>on</strong> of<br />

allomorphs based <strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant- vs. vowel-final stems, this is an example of n<strong>on</strong>-<br />

optimizing allomorphy because there is no apparent way in which the distributi<strong>on</strong><br />

improves the overall well-formedness of words c<strong>on</strong>taining either type of stem. What is<br />

interesting about this case, as in the Winnebago example described above, is that<br />

82


although the allomorphs are distributed based <strong>on</strong> whether the stem is c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant- or<br />

vowel-final, the pattern ends up having no effect <strong>on</strong> syllable structure.<br />

The distributi<strong>on</strong> of -chu vs. -cha <strong>on</strong> vowel-final stems can be derived by rule from<br />

underlying /-chu/. One thing to notice about the distributi<strong>on</strong> of these allomorphs is that<br />

-cha occurs when the stem has a fr<strong>on</strong>t vowel (assuming that /a/ is a fr<strong>on</strong>t vowel) and<br />

when the suffix can form a single disyllabic foot with the stem (i.e., when the stem is<br />

m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic). This suggests that there could be a foot-bounded fr<strong>on</strong>ting harm<strong>on</strong>y<br />

process resp<strong>on</strong>sible for the change of /u/ to [a] in the suffix. When the stem has two<br />

syllables, even if the stem-final syllable has a fr<strong>on</strong>t vowel, the suffix vowel surfaces as<br />

[u] because the stem forms its own foot to the exclusi<strong>on</strong> of the suffix, and therefore the<br />

suffix vowel /u/ is outside the domain of fr<strong>on</strong>ting harm<strong>on</strong>y. The <strong>on</strong>e troubling fact about<br />

this proposed harm<strong>on</strong>y rule is that we would expect it to change /u/ to its high, fr<strong>on</strong>t<br />

counterpart [i] rather than the low vowel [a]. However, given that the process appears to<br />

be so regular and that it accounts for a pattern of allomorphy that is otherwise mystifying,<br />

we should accept this <strong>on</strong>e complicati<strong>on</strong> to the rule. There is further reas<strong>on</strong> to assume that<br />

this is a regular rule of the language, which is that it also applies to the genitive suffix, to<br />

be described below.<br />

The genitive suffix in Jivaro exhibits allomorphy that is very similar to that of the<br />

negative suffix, except that there are four surface allomorphs. The generalizati<strong>on</strong> is as<br />

follows (de Maria 1918: 6). All stems ending in a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant take the -na suffix. All stems<br />

ending in /e/ take -ña. Am<strong>on</strong>g stems ending in /i/, polysyllabic stems take -ñu, while<br />

m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic stems take -ña. All other stems (that is, stems ending in any vowel except i<br />

83


or e) take -nu. 27 Examples are shown below (de Maria 1918: 6). 28<br />

(53) Yátzúm Yatzúm-na<br />

Gé Gé-ña<br />

Nucurí Nucurí-ñu ‘your mother’s’<br />

Vi Vi-ña ‘my’<br />

Apa Apá-nu ‘father’s’<br />

Aho Aho-nu ‘his’<br />

Núcu Nucú-nu<br />

The number of underlying forms can be reduced if we assume that the n ~ ñ alternati<strong>on</strong><br />

results from palatalizati<strong>on</strong> following i or e. 29 This leaves us with two suppletive<br />

allomorphs, distributed as follows: stems ending in a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant take -na. Stems ending in<br />

/e/ take -na. Am<strong>on</strong>g stems ending in /i/, those with <strong>on</strong>e syllable take -na. All other stems<br />

take -nu. We can simplify this, as we did above for the negative, as follows. C<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-<br />

final stems take -na, and vowel-final stems take -nu. The same vowel fr<strong>on</strong>ting harm<strong>on</strong>y<br />

described above applies to the suffix vowel when the stem vowel is fr<strong>on</strong>t and when the<br />

suffix syllable can form a foot with the stem, resulting in -na.<br />

There are two minor problems with this. The first is that, unlike for the negative,<br />

we have examples of the genitive suffix combining with trisyllabic stems. Under the<br />

analysis assuming a foot-based harm<strong>on</strong>y domain, we would expect trisyllabic forms to<br />

behave like m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic stems, since the first two syllables of the stem can form a<br />

disyllabic foot, leaving the stem-final syllable to form a foot al<strong>on</strong>g with the suffix,<br />

27<br />

In the very closely related language/dialect Achuar, the genitive allomorphs are -nau<br />

and -nu (Fast Mowitz et al 1996: 31). Though the distributi<strong>on</strong> of these allomorphs is not<br />

discussed, the two examples given (áints-nau ‘de un hombre’ and nuwá-nu ‘de una<br />

mujer’) are c<strong>on</strong>sistent with the distributi<strong>on</strong> in Jivaro if we assume that Achuar -nau<br />

corresp<strong>on</strong>ds to Jivaro -na.<br />

28<br />

Examples are not glossed; the glosses here are from Fast Mowitz et al (1996) and Jintia<br />

et al (2000).<br />

29<br />

Fast Mowitz et al (1996: 15) document a rule in Achuar in which some c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants are<br />

palatalized following /i/.<br />

84


thereby creating a domain in which the harm<strong>on</strong>y rule can apply. However, as seen in the<br />

example Nucurí-ñu above, this is not what happens. Instead, trisyllabic stems behave like<br />

disyllabic stems in not triggering the vowel harm<strong>on</strong>y rule. A possible explanati<strong>on</strong> for this<br />

is that perhaps Jivaro allows trisyllabic feet in cases where this would allow the right<br />

edge of a stem to be aligned with the right edge of a foot. Thus, the example Nucurí-ñu<br />

would be footed as (Nucurí)Ft-ñu, thus explaining the failure of the suffix vowel to<br />

undergo harm<strong>on</strong>y. The sec<strong>on</strong>d problem is that, unlike the in negative example described<br />

above, the genitive suffix vowel is claimed not to surface as [a] when the stem vowel is<br />

/a/. The <strong>on</strong>ly genitive example provided that has a stem-final /a/ happens also to have a<br />

disyllabic stem, so the suffix vowel would not be expected to undergo harm<strong>on</strong>y in this<br />

example anyway. With no further examples, I will assume that m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic stems with<br />

final /a/ do take the -na allomorph, since otherwise the applicati<strong>on</strong> of the harm<strong>on</strong>y rule to<br />

the genitive suffix exactly parallels its applicati<strong>on</strong> to the negative suffix.<br />

The PCSA seen in both the genitive and the negative suffixes in Jivaro has been<br />

argued to reduce to allomorphy c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by whether the stem ends in a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant or a<br />

vowel. As in the Winnebago example discussed above, this example is of interest because<br />

unlike some other examples involving c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing of this type, the pattern seen here<br />

does not optimize syllable structure. Therefore, the distributi<strong>on</strong> based <strong>on</strong> the C/V<br />

distincti<strong>on</strong> is not simply an artifact of syllable optimizati<strong>on</strong>. If the allomorphy optimized<br />

syllables, we might have been able to state the generalizati<strong>on</strong> in terms of syllable types<br />

and structures such as ‘<strong>on</strong>set,’ ‘nucleus,’ and ‘coda’ instead of C and V. Since this is not<br />

the case, we must c<strong>on</strong>clude that the mechanism resp<strong>on</strong>sible for PCSA is able to refer<br />

directly to C and V.<br />

85


Another example of C/V c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy is found in Haitian Creole (Hall<br />

1953, Klein 2003). In this language, there is a determiner whose form varies between -a<br />

and -la in a pattern that is the exact opposite of what would be expected if the pattern<br />

optimized CV syllable structure: -a occurs after vowel-final stems while -la occurs after<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems. Some examples are shown below (Hall 1953: 32).<br />

(54) panié-a ‘the basket’ pitit-la ‘the child’<br />

trou-a ‘the hole’ ãj-la ‘the angel’<br />

figi-a ‘the face’ kay-la ‘the house’<br />

chẽ-ã ‘the dog’ madãm-lã ‘the lady’<br />

In this example, if regular ph<strong>on</strong>ological well-formedness c<strong>on</strong>straints were resp<strong>on</strong>sible for<br />

the allomorphy, we would have expected the opposite distributi<strong>on</strong>, since this would avoid<br />

coda c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants and vowel hiatus. In this case, then, the allomorphy is not <strong>on</strong>ly n<strong>on</strong>-<br />

optimizing, but it is ‘perverse’ in the sense that it makes words less ph<strong>on</strong>ologically<br />

optimal with respect to syllable structure (see also Bye to appear for discussi<strong>on</strong> of this<br />

example). 30<br />

We could analyze this as n<strong>on</strong>-suppletive allomorphy resulting from deleti<strong>on</strong> of /l/<br />

between vowels. However, this would not be a general rule of the language, and it is also<br />

30<br />

B<strong>on</strong>et et al (in press) propose an analysis of this example in terms of P c<strong>on</strong>straints <strong>on</strong><br />

syllable c<strong>on</strong>tact and alignment of stems with syllable boundaries. Such an analysis<br />

requires proposing a PRIORITY c<strong>on</strong>straint stipulating that the /a/ allomorph takes<br />

precedence over the /la/ allomorph. The analysis requires many c<strong>on</strong>straints and is<br />

arguably much more complex than a subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> account, but B<strong>on</strong>et et al reject the<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach to this example in footnote 11 <strong>on</strong> the grounds that ‘… just<br />

stating the distributi<strong>on</strong> misses a ph<strong>on</strong>ological generalizati<strong>on</strong>; the choice is not random but<br />

systematic, and the systematicity is directly related to ph<strong>on</strong>ological informati<strong>on</strong>.’ If<br />

‘systematic’ here is meant to mean ‘ph<strong>on</strong>ologically natural’, then it is not clear that the<br />

statement is true at all, since the c<strong>on</strong>straint-based analysis crucially depends <strong>on</strong> a<br />

stipulated priority relati<strong>on</strong>ship between allomorphs. If, instead, ‘systematic’ merely<br />

means ‘able to be captured via reference to a c<strong>on</strong>sistent ph<strong>on</strong>ological generalizati<strong>on</strong>,’<br />

then the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach is just as well-equipped to capture the generalizati<strong>on</strong><br />

as is the account proposed by B<strong>on</strong>et et al.<br />

86


an unnatural rule since it results in VV sequences and since V_V is an ideal envir<strong>on</strong>ment<br />

for a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant to be perceived and produced. Thus, even if this were analyzed as a<br />

‘crazy rule’ rather than PCSA, we would still have difficulty accounting for it using<br />

regular, natural ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints.<br />

Another potential alternative analysis is a ‘ghost c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant’ analysis as discussed<br />

for the Midob example in §2.1.2.3 (in fact, analyses of Haitian involving ghost<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants (or ‘floating segments’) are proposed by Cadely 2002 and Nikiema 1999).<br />

The determiner could be represented as /-(l)a/ with a ‘latent’ /l/ c<strong>on</strong>sisting of c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant<br />

features not attached to any root node (following the representati<strong>on</strong> advocated by Zoll<br />

1996: 48) that would <strong>on</strong>ly surface when a root node is inserted for its features to associate<br />

to. One problem for such an analysis is that we would have to explain why a root node is<br />

inserted in the c<strong>on</strong>text C_V but not in the c<strong>on</strong>text V_V; the pattern would still be n<strong>on</strong>-<br />

optimizing even if it were not analyzed as suppletive. Another problem for a ‘ghost<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant’ analysis of this phenomen<strong>on</strong> is that when the stem has a final [+ATR] vowel,<br />

a glide is inserted between the stem and suffix (Klein 2003), as seen below.<br />

(55) pape[j]-a ‘the paper’<br />

bato[w]-a ‘the boat’<br />

lapli[j]-a ‘the father’<br />

tu[w]-a ‘the hole’<br />

In an OT analysis involving a latent suffix-initial /l/, we would have to explain why a<br />

different c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant gets inserted in this c<strong>on</strong>text. Since the choice of the inserted glide is<br />

predictable from the roundness of the stem-final vowel, we would not want to supply the<br />

inserted glide with underlying c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant features. However, if the glide inserti<strong>on</strong> rule<br />

simply inserted a root node, then we might expect the root node to take <strong>on</strong> the features of<br />

the latent /l/ rather than taking <strong>on</strong> features from the preceding vowel, since this would<br />

87


avoid the violati<strong>on</strong> of MAX that would be incurred when the latent features of /l/ failed to<br />

surface.<br />

Two points should be made regarding glide inserti<strong>on</strong> in the Haitian Creole<br />

examples. First, there is the questi<strong>on</strong> of whether this example can be claimed to be ‘n<strong>on</strong>-<br />

optimizing’, given that these examples with the -a suffix do end up having well-formed<br />

CV syllables <strong>on</strong> the surface. Since glide inserti<strong>on</strong> applies <strong>on</strong>ly to stems ending in a<br />

[+ATR] vowel, the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphy still does create VV sequences in words<br />

where the stem ends in a [-ATR] vowel. Therefore, the result of the allomorphy is that<br />

some words are indeed less well-formed, with respect to the c<strong>on</strong>straint ONSET, than they<br />

would be with the opposite distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs. A sec<strong>on</strong>d point is that in words<br />

which undergo glide inserti<strong>on</strong>, the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> that determines allomorphy (C- vs. V-final<br />

stem) is rendered opaque, since the suffix in these words does end up being preceded by a<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant rather than a vowel. This suggests that glide inserti<strong>on</strong> operates <strong>on</strong> the output of<br />

suffixati<strong>on</strong>, rather than applying at the same time as the suffix allomorph is selected. In<br />

§2.1.2.6, I discuss more examples in which c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong> are<br />

rendered opaque by ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes.<br />

Some examples of n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing PCSA involve c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing by features of a<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant or vowel in the stem. As with the C/V-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed cases described above, in<br />

these examples the triggering segment of the stem is always at the same edge at which the<br />

affix attaches. In these examples, unlike in the assimilatory and dissimilatory examples<br />

presented in §2.1.2.1 and §2.1.2.2, the features that c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> allomorphy do not seem to<br />

be related to features of the suppletive allomorphs. This makes it difficult to account for<br />

these examples in terms of any well-known ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints.<br />

88


Harris (1979: 288-289) discusses an interesting case of allomorphy in Spanish<br />

that is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by vowel quality. According to Harris, the imperfective aspect is<br />

marked by -a following /i/, and as -ba elsewhere. Examples are provided below (Harris<br />

1979: 288).<br />

(56) viví-a ‘lived’ pasá-ba ‘passed’<br />

caí-a ‘fell’ tomá-ba ‘took’<br />

Harris (1979: 289) proposes a rule of b → Ø after /i/ and a morpheme boundary, but since<br />

the rule would <strong>on</strong>ly apply to the imperfective suffix and since this rule is apparently not<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>etically motivated, it seems more reas<strong>on</strong>able to posit two separate underlying forms,<br />

/-a/ and /-ba/. This does not seem to be a comm<strong>on</strong> rule type cross-linguistically, and there<br />

is no immediately apparent ph<strong>on</strong>etic motivati<strong>on</strong> for deleting /b/ after a high vowel.<br />

A sec<strong>on</strong>d example in which PCSA is triggered by stem-final vowel features is<br />

found in Yucunany Mixtepec Mixtec (Otomanguean, Mexico; Paster and Beam de<br />

Azc<strong>on</strong>a 2005). This language exhibits another pattern of allomorphy that does not seem<br />

to maximize ph<strong>on</strong>ological well-formedness (though as to be discussed, depending <strong>on</strong><br />

<strong>on</strong>e’s perspective, the pattern could be said to be optimizing in a different way). In this<br />

language, the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs of the third pers<strong>on</strong> singular familiar (subject and<br />

possessor) is determined by the final vowel of the root. The allomorphs, -à and -ì, occur<br />

in place of the final vowel of the verb or noun phrase and are selected based <strong>on</strong> the<br />

quality of the final vowel. When the final vowel is [i], the third pers<strong>on</strong> singular familiar is<br />

marked using the à allomorph; with all other final vowels, the -ì allomorph is used. All<br />

native roots end in vowels, but there are some c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final Spanish loanwords that<br />

take -ñaà; this is allomorph is probably better viewed as being specific to loanwords<br />

89


ather than c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by the root-final segment. Examples of the -à allomorph are given<br />

below (Paster and Beam de Azc<strong>on</strong>a 2005: 74; underlining indicates nasalizati<strong>on</strong>).<br />

(57) sì’i ‘leg’ sì’aà ‘his leg’<br />

kachìí ‘cott<strong>on</strong>’ kachìáà ‘his cott<strong>on</strong>’<br />

tzí’ì yù ‘I am dying’ tzí’à ‘she is dying’<br />

Occurrences of the -ì allomorph are shown below (Paster and Beam de Azc<strong>on</strong>a 2005: 74).<br />

(58) sàmá ‘clothing’ sàmíì ‘his clothing’<br />

vàá’a ‘bad’ vàá’ì ‘it is bad’<br />

tá’a ‘relative’ tá’ì ‘his relative’<br />

nda’á ‘hand’ nda’íì ‘her hand’<br />

ma tzá’nu ‘grandmother’ ma tzá’nì ‘her grandmother’<br />

kù’ù ‘woman’s sister’ kù’ì ‘her sister’<br />

This pattern does not make more well-formed words in any obvious way. It does,<br />

however, have the effect of preventing homoph<strong>on</strong>y with the plain form, since plain stems<br />

ending in L-t<strong>on</strong>ed [i] would be homoph<strong>on</strong>ous with their 3sg familiar forms if the -à<br />

allomorph were not available. In additi<strong>on</strong>, the use of -à prevents homoph<strong>on</strong>y with the 1sg<br />

form of underlyingly H-M and M-M roots ending in [i], which would otherwise take the<br />

same form in the 3sg familiar. Both allomorphs c<strong>on</strong>sist of a single vowel that takes the<br />

place of the root-final vowel, but the pattern is not derivable via a regular ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

rule of the language. I c<strong>on</strong>clude that the allomorphy is suppletive, and though it<br />

apparently does not optimize the ph<strong>on</strong>ological well-formedness of individual words, <strong>on</strong>e<br />

might argue that it maximizes distinctness am<strong>on</strong>g morphologically related words. If <strong>on</strong>e<br />

is willing to posit ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints enforcing n<strong>on</strong>-homoph<strong>on</strong>y within paradigms,<br />

then perhaps this example could be analyzed al<strong>on</strong>g these lines using the P >> M model.<br />

90


The survey also revealed some examples in which allomorphy is triggered by<br />

features of stem-peripheral c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants. For example, the locative suffix in Martuthunira<br />

(Dench 1995) exhibits n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing allomorphy based <strong>on</strong> both the root-final segment<br />

and <strong>on</strong> mora count. Bimoraic stems with a final vowel take -ngka, stems with three or<br />

more morae with a final vowel take -la, stems with final n take -ta, stems with final rn<br />

(apico-postalveolar nasal) take -rta (rt is an apico-postalveolar stop), stems with final ny<br />

or nh (lamino-palatal or lamino-dental nasal) take -tha, (th is a lamino-dental stop) and<br />

stems with a final rhotic or lateral take -a (Dench 1995: 64). The effector suffix has the<br />

same shape as the locative in all of these c<strong>on</strong>texts, except that in each case, the effector<br />

suffix has /u/ rather than /a/. The sensitivity to mora count seen here will be taken up in<br />

chapter 4; for our present purposes, we will focus <strong>on</strong> the allomorphy that relates to<br />

whether the stem ends in a nasal or a liquid. Examples are given below (with page<br />

numbers from Dench 1995 in parentheses), though no examples of the -rta or -tha form<br />

are provided.<br />

(59) panyu-ngka-a yartapalyu-la<br />

good-LOC-ACC other.group-LOC<br />

‘in a better (tree)’ (73) ‘...out of that other mob’ (75)<br />

kalyaran-ta-a kuyil-a<br />

tree-LOC-ACC bad-LOC<br />

‘in a tree’ (73) ‘<strong>on</strong> that bad (hill)’ (94)<br />

The aspect of this pattern of interest here is the -ta ~ -rta ~ -tha ~ -a alternati<strong>on</strong> in the<br />

locative suffix, and the corresp<strong>on</strong>ding -tu ~ -rtu ~ -thu ~ -u pattern of the effector suffix.<br />

It seems possible that /t/ is not part of the locative or effector suffixes, but some kind of<br />

stem-former or empty morpheme that can be used with the locative and effector suffixes;<br />

regardless of whether it bel<strong>on</strong>gs to the suffixes or the stem, the alternati<strong>on</strong> exhibited in<br />

91


the c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant in this positi<strong>on</strong> should be explained. Dench (1995: 41) proposes an<br />

assimilati<strong>on</strong> rule to account for the first three of each of these allomorph sets, leaving us<br />

with two basic locative allomorphs, /-ta/ and /-a/, and two basic effector allomorphs, /-tu/<br />

and /-u/. Assuming Dench’s assimilati<strong>on</strong> rule, we still need to explain the -V form of the<br />

suffixes after a rhotic or lateral. This could be handled via a rule specific to this affix that<br />

deletes /t/ following a liquid, but the rule would be unmotivated since if anything, liquids<br />

seem to make better codas than other c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants. The result of this case of PCSA can<br />

therefore be said to be ph<strong>on</strong>etically unnatural. Here the feature that distinguishes nasals<br />

from other s<strong>on</strong>orant c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants (whether it is [±liquid], [±nasal], [±c<strong>on</strong>tinuant], or some<br />

combinati<strong>on</strong> of these is not important here) causes an allomorph to be used that has no<br />

initial c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant; this is parallel to a ph<strong>on</strong>ological rule deleting the initial c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant of<br />

the suffix after a [liquid] c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant. We could analyze this in terms of a c<strong>on</strong>straint such<br />

as *LT banning voiceless c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants after a liquid, an extensi<strong>on</strong> of the *NT c<strong>on</strong>straint<br />

(referred to as *NC̥) used by, e.g., Pater (1999). Paster (2004: 389) proposed a c<strong>on</strong>straint<br />

*NT/lT banning voiceless c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants after nasals and /l/, but the use of that particular<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straint for Martuthunira would not work since in that case we would expect the<br />

vowel-initial suffix allomorph to occur after nasals as well as liquids. We would therefore<br />

need a more specific c<strong>on</strong>straint *LT referring <strong>on</strong>ly to liquids and not nasals; we would<br />

also need to explain why *NT was not also active in a language with *LT, since *NT<br />

effects seem to be comm<strong>on</strong> and are ph<strong>on</strong>etically well-motivated, probably by the same<br />

mechanism that would be resp<strong>on</strong>sible for *LT. 31 It may thus be possible to account for<br />

this pattern if we propose a new c<strong>on</strong>straint, but it is not at all clear that the overall pattern<br />

31 See Pater 1999 for further discussi<strong>on</strong> of *NT.<br />

92


is optimizing. Certainly, this example is not like the other Martuthunira examples seen in<br />

the previous secti<strong>on</strong> that appear to be driven by syllable c<strong>on</strong>tact c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s. Since<br />

nasals are c<strong>on</strong>sidered to be less s<strong>on</strong>orous than /l/, we might expect that the sequence l.t<br />

should be preferred over n.t and therefore that the t-initial suffix allomorphs should occur<br />

after /l/ and not after nasals. Viewed in this way, we might almost say that the pattern of<br />

allomorphy here is the exact opposite of what we would expect if it were optimizing.<br />

A sec<strong>on</strong>d example of apparently n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing PCSA c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant<br />

features is found in Nishnaabemwin (Alg<strong>on</strong>quian, Ontario; Valentine 2001), where the<br />

c<strong>on</strong>junct order third pers<strong>on</strong> suffix takes the form -g following a nasal-final stem and -d<br />

following other stems (except in some c<strong>on</strong>junct negatives) (Valentine 2001: 227). Some<br />

examples are provided below. 32<br />

(60) dgoshin-g ‘if/when ANsg arrives’<br />

boodwe-d ‘if/when ANsg builds a fire’<br />

dgoshnini-d ‘if/when ANsg (obv.) arrives’<br />

There is no indicati<strong>on</strong> of a general rule of d → g elsewhere in the language, and there do<br />

exist nd sequences, including coda clusters, as in the examples below (nd sequences<br />

appear in bold; page numbers are from Valentine 2001).<br />

(61) bbaamaandwe ‘climb around’ (375)<br />

gaandnan ‘push X (with an instrument’ (427)<br />

naagdawenmind ‘(CONJ) ANsg is taken care of’ (563)<br />

niinwind ‘we/us/our’ (574)<br />

aanind ‘some’ (575)<br />

Although the -g and -d allomorphs have a similar ph<strong>on</strong>ological shape, an item-specific<br />

rule changing d to g after nasals would be unnatural since there is no apparent ph<strong>on</strong>etic<br />

32 Valentine indicates (2001:74) that final ng reduces to [ŋ]; it is not clear whether this<br />

applies <strong>on</strong>ly to ng or to final nasal+stop sequences in general. A general postnasal stop<br />

deleti<strong>on</strong> rule is not included in the discussi<strong>on</strong> of ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes applying to<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants (Valentine 2001: 73-89).<br />

93


motivati<strong>on</strong> for such a rule. This is an example where PCSA has a ‘neutral’ effect (i.e., no<br />

effect) <strong>on</strong> the well-formedness of words, since there is no ph<strong>on</strong>ological optimizati<strong>on</strong> in<br />

this pattern, and the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs could just as easily be reversed or reduced<br />

to a single allomorph in all envir<strong>on</strong>ments without any change in the number of violati<strong>on</strong>s<br />

of ph<strong>on</strong>ological well-formedness c<strong>on</strong>straints. 33<br />

In Kashaya, the absolutive involves suppleti<strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed in part by the final<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant of the stem (Buckley 1994: 336, Oswalt 1960: 265). Buckley states that the<br />

allomorphs of the absolutive are distributed as follows: the suffix -w occurs after a vowel<br />

((62)a), -i occurs after n’ (and later undergoes [+round] inserti<strong>on</strong>, surfacing as [u])<br />

((62)b), and -ʔ occurs elsewhere ((62)c). 34 Examples are from Oswalt 1960: 265, except<br />

where noted.<br />

33<br />

Another example involving c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing by a stem-final nasal is found in Northern<br />

Sotho (Bantu, South Africa; Kosch 1998). According to Kosch (1998: 35-36), Northern<br />

Sotho exhibits ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy in the past tense suffix -ile / -e.<br />

The past tense is marked with -ile (e.g. -rut-ile ‘teach-past’) except after certain verb<br />

roots, all of which end in a nasal (e.g. -em-e ‘stand-past’ and -b<strong>on</strong>-e [no gloss]). This<br />

suggests that the selecti<strong>on</strong> of the -e allomorph may be c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by the presence of a<br />

root-final nasal, though Kosch acknowledges that there are some cases in which a nasalfinal<br />

root takes -ile (e.g. -rom-ile ‘send-past’). It is unclear how many nasal-final roots<br />

take -ile, but Kosch implies that there are several. However, Kosch claims that the<br />

allomorphy was strictly ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed at an earlier stage of the language.<br />

The allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong> seems to have nothing to do with the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing factor,<br />

namely the presence of a final nasal. One possibility is that there is a dispreference for a<br />

high vowel following a nasal, though there does not appear to be any such dispreference<br />

exhibited elsewhere in the language. Thus, ‘pre-Northern Sotho,’ if it did indeed exhibit<br />

excepti<strong>on</strong>less ph<strong>on</strong>ological allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong>, would c<strong>on</strong>stitute another example<br />

where allomorphy is not obviously optimizing and the nasal feature that triggers the<br />

allomorphy has no clear relati<strong>on</strong>ship with the shape of the allomorphs.<br />

34<br />

This is essentially the same as Oswalt’s (1960: 265) characterizati<strong>on</strong> except that<br />

Buckley’s n’ corresp<strong>on</strong>ds to Oswalt’s d, and Oswalt assumed that the absolutive<br />

allomorph for stems ending in this segment was /-u/ rather than /-i/ with [+round]<br />

inserti<strong>on</strong>.<br />

94


(62) a. mo-ˑla-w ‘to run down’<br />

bahcú-w ‘to jump’ (Buckley 1994: 61)<br />

ca-hcí-w ‘to sit down’ (Buckley 1994: 61)<br />

b. mo-laˑmed-u ‘to keep running down’<br />

c. mom-’ ‘to run across’<br />

c’ihwín-’ ‘get red hot’ (Oswalt 1960: 171, via Buckley 1994)<br />

dahal-’ ‘dig (a hole)’ (Oswalt 1960: 171. via Buckley 1994)<br />

Under an analysis without [+round] inserti<strong>on</strong>, in which the underlying form of the<br />

absolutive suffix was /-u/, the u ~ w distributi<strong>on</strong> could be accounted for by post-vocalic<br />

glide formati<strong>on</strong> (u → w). However, [u] and [w] do not easily relate to [’], and there is no<br />

apparent reas<strong>on</strong> why /d/ should behave differently from other c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants in not triggering<br />

a rule of u → ʔ. Even if we assume, with Buckley, that [d] corresp<strong>on</strong>ds to /n’/, we cannot<br />

explain its behavior as being related to its already being glottalized, since this segment<br />

still behaves differently from other glottalized segments, in that stems ending in other<br />

glottalized c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants do not take -u. In fact, according to Buckley (1994: 73), in general<br />

when a glottal stop occurs to the right of an already glottalized segment, the glottal stop<br />

simply deleted. The distributi<strong>on</strong> of w vs. ’ might be argued to optimize syllable structure<br />

since adding /w/ to the end of a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stem would create a complex coda that<br />

would have to be repaired via epenthesis (Buckley 1994: 249), where as adding /’/ <strong>on</strong>ly<br />

glottalizes the c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant. However, the behavior of d-final stems is arbitrary and<br />

puzzling, and it seems that we cannot account for it based <strong>on</strong> any well-known<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints.<br />

A final example of seemingly arbitrary, n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing PCSA is found in Coptic<br />

(Kramer 2005, to appear). In this unusual example, allomorphy appears to be driven by<br />

the number of c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants in the stem. According to Kramer (2005: 14), the quality of the<br />

vowel that marks the stative in Coptic root and pattern morphology can be predicted<br />

95


ased <strong>on</strong> the number of c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants making up the root of the verb. Roots with a single<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant ((63)a) take eu, roots with two c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants ((63)b) take e, roots with three<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants ((63)c) take ɔ, and roots with four c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants ((63)d) or five c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants<br />

((63)e) take o. 35 Examples of stative forms are shown below (Kramer 2005: 4, 9, 14-15,<br />

23; capital letters indicate syllabic c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants, and periods indicate syllable boundaries).<br />

(63) a. seu ‘is sated’<br />

tʃeu ‘is sown’<br />

weu ‘has become distant’<br />

ʃeu ‘is measured’<br />

b. pet ‘has run’<br />

keβ ‘has been made cool’<br />

seh ‘is written’<br />

ket ‘is built’<br />

c. sɔ.tM ‘to be listened to’<br />

kɔ.nS ‘to be stinky’<br />

mɔ.səɁ ‘to be born’<br />

sɔ.βK ‘to be few’<br />

d. wS.t<strong>on</strong> ‘is broadened’<br />

tN.t<strong>on</strong> ‘is likened’<br />

sL.sol ‘is c<strong>on</strong>soled’<br />

ʃF.ʃof ‘has burrowed’<br />

e. srM.rom ‘is dazed’<br />

ʃtR.tor ‘is disturbed’<br />

k j lM.lom ‘is twisted’<br />

slK j .lok j ‘is made smooth’<br />

This example is unusual and difficult to characterize. It is undesirable to allow the<br />

grammar to refer to the number of root c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants in selecting the stative vowel, and yet<br />

the pattern is straightforward, and we would like to capture it rather than say that the<br />

stative vowel quality is lexically determined (in which case the generalizati<strong>on</strong> about the<br />

35<br />

Though most quadric<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal stems and all quinquic<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal roots look like<br />

reduplicants <strong>on</strong> the surface, Kramer argues persuasively that they do not result from any<br />

synchr<strong>on</strong>ic reduplicati<strong>on</strong> process since the form and meaning of the apparent reduplicants<br />

is not c<strong>on</strong>sistent, and in some cases there is no shorter root that could have been the base<br />

for reduplicati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

96


number of root c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants would be lost). A possible way around this problem is to refer<br />

to the number and/or shape of syllables in the output form. Though it does not appear that<br />

this would allow us to explain the particular vowel that is used with each root type, we at<br />

least have a way to characterize the pattern without allowing the grammar to ‘count’ root<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants. In the case of m<strong>on</strong>oc<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal roots, the use of eu does make some sense<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ologically, since the output form ends up c<strong>on</strong>sisting of a single syllable, and perhaps<br />

using eu allows the word to be bimoraic. Similarly, for the bic<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal roots, we could<br />

say that the e allomorph occurs when the word will c<strong>on</strong>sist of a closed syllable. Likewise,<br />

the ɔ allomorph occurs in an initial open syllable, and the o allomorph occurs in a final<br />

closed syllable in words with two syllables. Note that except in the case of the diphth<strong>on</strong>g<br />

used with m<strong>on</strong>oc<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal roots, there is no apparent principled relati<strong>on</strong> between the<br />

quality of the vowel and the number of root c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants or the CV structure of the word.<br />

A particularly interesting c<strong>on</strong>trast is between stems with two vs. four or five c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants.<br />

In both cases, the vowel ends up in a word-final CVC syllable, yet with bic<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal<br />

roots it surfaces as e, while with quadri- or quinquic<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal roots it surfaces as o.<br />

Thus, although the pattern can be described in terms of syllable structure and syllable<br />

count (rather than c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant count), it does not optimize syllable structure, with the<br />

possible excepti<strong>on</strong> of words with m<strong>on</strong>oc<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal roots. We can therefore capture the<br />

pattern in ph<strong>on</strong>ological terms, but we cannot do this by using regular ph<strong>on</strong>ological well-<br />

formedness c<strong>on</strong>straints in OT. This case is therefore not easily handled using P >> M.<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong>, we have seen numerous examples of PCSA that do not maximize<br />

well-formedness, and some in which the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs actually makes words<br />

less well-formed. As has been discussed throughout, these examples are problematic for<br />

97


the P >> M approach, because that approach seeks to account for ph<strong>on</strong>ological effects in<br />

morphology using the same c<strong>on</strong>straints that account for purely ph<strong>on</strong>ological, n<strong>on</strong>-<br />

suppletive allomorphy, and yet unlike ph<strong>on</strong>ology, which is usually ‘natural’ (though cf.<br />

Anders<strong>on</strong> 1981), many cases of PCSA are not at all natural. A model in which suppletive<br />

and n<strong>on</strong>-suppletive allomorphy are analyzed in exactly the same way is incapable of<br />

accounting for this asymmetry.<br />

2.1.2.6 Opaque c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing<br />

There is another class of examples of PCSA that are problematic for the P >> M<br />

model. This survey revealed a number of cases in which the ph<strong>on</strong>ological element that<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s the distributi<strong>on</strong> of suppletive allomorphs does not appear in the surface form,<br />

rendering opaque the ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> PCSA. Though the original versi<strong>on</strong> of<br />

OT was intended to be purely surface-based, later versi<strong>on</strong>s incorporated two-level<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straints, sympathy, c<strong>on</strong>joined c<strong>on</strong>straints, and other strategies to account for opaque<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological interacti<strong>on</strong>s. Thus, by incorporating some of these mechanisms, current OT<br />

is equipped to model opacity and, by extensi<strong>on</strong>, to model opaque interacti<strong>on</strong>s in PCSA.<br />

Given this, the P >> M model does predict the existence of opaque c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing in<br />

PCSA. However, just as opaque ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes have been problematic for OT in<br />

making it necessary to c<strong>on</strong>tinually add new mechanisms to the model, opaque c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s<br />

<strong>on</strong> PCSA are equally problematic. This survey revealed several such examples, to be<br />

discussed below.<br />

In Turkish (Lewis 1967), the 3rd pers<strong>on</strong> possessive suffix exhibits allomorphy<br />

whose c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing is rendered opaque by a regular process of velar deleti<strong>on</strong>. The suffix<br />

98


takes the form -I following a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stem and -sI following a vowel-final stem,<br />

as seen in the examples below (examples are from Aranovich et al 2005 and from Gizem<br />

Karaali, p.c.; note that vowel alternati<strong>on</strong>s are due to regular vowel harm<strong>on</strong>y).<br />

(64) bedel-i ‘its price’ fire-si ‘its attriti<strong>on</strong>’<br />

ikiz-i ‘its twin’ elma-sɪ ‘its apple’<br />

alet-i ‘its tool’ arɪ-sɪ ‘its bee’<br />

A prop<strong>on</strong>ent of the P >> M approach might cite this as an example of syllable structure<br />

optimizati<strong>on</strong> since the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs serves to avoid both vowel hiatus and<br />

syllable codas. However, as pointed out by Aranovich et al (2005), there are examples in<br />

which the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs is rendered opaque by a regular ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

process. Turkish exhibits a regular process of Velar Deleti<strong>on</strong> (see, e.g., Sezer 1981),<br />

which deletes /k/ in intervocalic positi<strong>on</strong>. This interacts with the third pers<strong>on</strong> possessive<br />

suffix allomorphy in an interesting way: underlyingly /k/-final stems take the /-i/ suffix<br />

allomorph since the stems are underlyingly c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final, but then because of the<br />

additi<strong>on</strong> of the vowel suffix, the /k/ is in intervocalic positi<strong>on</strong> and is therefore deleted.<br />

Thus, as seen in (65), the interacti<strong>on</strong> of PCSA and Velar Deleti<strong>on</strong> produces the very<br />

vowel hiatus that the distributi<strong>on</strong> of /-i/ vs. /-si/ was supposed to avoid.<br />

(65) açlɪ-ɪ ‘its hunger’ (cf. açlɪk ‘hunger’)<br />

bebe-i ‘its baby’ (cf. bebek ‘baby’)<br />

gerdanlɪ-ɪ ‘its necklace’ (cf. gerdanlɪk ‘necklace’)<br />

ekme-i ‘its bread’ (cf. ekmek ‘bread’)<br />

The explanati<strong>on</strong> for this situati<strong>on</strong> seems to be that suppletive allomorph selecti<strong>on</strong><br />

takes place first in the morphology, and then the regular ph<strong>on</strong>ology of the language<br />

(including Velar Deleti<strong>on</strong>) applies to the output of morphology, in some cases rendering<br />

the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> PCSA opaque. This is easy to capture in the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> model,<br />

since we can say that /-i/ subcategorizes for stems that are c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final in the input,<br />

99


and then the output of morphology is the input to ph<strong>on</strong>ology. It is much more difficult to<br />

capture using P >> M because the c<strong>on</strong>straints <strong>on</strong> allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong> are not surface-<br />

true. The distributi<strong>on</strong> cannot be stated using <strong>on</strong>ly output-based c<strong>on</strong>straints in P >> M<br />

because that model does ph<strong>on</strong>ology and morphology together in parallel; it is crucial that<br />

morphology apply before ph<strong>on</strong>ology in this case.<br />

In Sa’ani Arabic (Egypt; Wats<strong>on</strong> 2002), there is another pattern of PCSA in which<br />

the result appears to be neutral with respect to ph<strong>on</strong>ological well-formedness, and in<br />

which the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> PCSA are not transparent <strong>on</strong> the surface. In this language, some<br />

subject suffixes have ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy determined by whether the<br />

stem ends in a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant or a vowel. According to Wats<strong>on</strong> (2002: 178, 184), the perfect<br />

aspect 3pl masculine suffix is -ū after c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final verb stems and -aw after vowel-<br />

final verb stems. Some examples are shown below (Wats<strong>on</strong> 2002: 185). Note that the<br />

stems taking -aw have underlying final vowels that are lost.<br />

(66) katab-ū ‘they (masc.) wrote’ ram-aw ‘they (masc.) threw’<br />

libis-ū ‘they (masc.) wore’ mall-aw ‘they (masc.) filled’<br />

Because of the deleti<strong>on</strong> of stem-final vowels, the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong> is<br />

lost <strong>on</strong> the surface in these examples.<br />

Also in Sa’ani Arabic, The perfective aspect 3sg feminine suffix has the form -at<br />

following c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final roots, and -it following vowel-final roots. Examples are given<br />

below (Wats<strong>on</strong> 2002: 185); again, the forms taking the postvocalic allomorph have root-<br />

final vowels that are lost.<br />

(67) katab-at ‘she wrote’ ram-it ‘she threw’<br />

libis-at ‘she wore’ mall-it ‘she filled’<br />

100


Here, the stem-final vowel that triggers the use of -it is lost, rendering the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong><br />

PCSA opaque. In this case, even if the stem-final vowel had been retained, there is no<br />

immediately apparent way in which the allomorphy is optimizing, since both allomorphs<br />

have the structure -VC.<br />

Thus, in both of the Sa’ani Arabic examples, we see that PCSA can be<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by a ph<strong>on</strong>ological element that is lost <strong>on</strong> the surface via the applicati<strong>on</strong> of a<br />

regular ph<strong>on</strong>ological rule or c<strong>on</strong>straint. This type of example is problematic for the P >><br />

M model. In OT, ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints generally either optimize output well-<br />

formedness or maximize faithfulness to the input. In the P >> M model, the same<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints that are active in the ph<strong>on</strong>ological grammar are also resp<strong>on</strong>sible<br />

for PCSA, and therefore we expect cases of PCSA either to be optimizing or to maximize<br />

faithfulness (the latter being somewhat improbable since faithfulness to the input form of<br />

an affix would have the effect of preventing allomorphy, not producing it). In Sa’ani<br />

Arabic, PCSA does not seem to result in surface optimizati<strong>on</strong> in any way, and therefore<br />

modeling it using regular ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints is problematic. We can account for it<br />

by writing specific c<strong>on</strong>straints that specify which allomorph to use in which envir<strong>on</strong>ment,<br />

but this defeats the purpose of modeling PCSA using P >> M, since the P >> M model<br />

was designed to account for examples where PCSA can be said to follow from general<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints.<br />

Another example that exhibits PCSA c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by an element that is later<br />

deleted is found in Kimatuumbi (Bantu, Tanzania; Odden 1996). According to Odden<br />

(1996), the perfective has four allomorphs: -i̹te, -i̹i̹le, -i̹i̹ye, and the infix -i̹-. The<br />

allomorphs are distributed according to both segmental and syllable count-based factors<br />

101


as follows (Odden 1996: 51-53). M<strong>on</strong>osyllabic verbs (of shape (C)V(V)C), as well as<br />

stems whose final vowel is l<strong>on</strong>g, take -i̹te. Polysyllabic stems (except those with a final<br />

l<strong>on</strong>g vowel) take the -i̹- infix, which is inserted into the stem-final syllable; these forms<br />

also take the final vowel e rather than a. Stems ending in yaan or waan take the -i̹i̹ye<br />

suffix variant, and of particular interest here is the fact that glide-final roots take the -i̹i̹le<br />

allomorph, as shown below in (68)a-b (Odden 1996: 52) and that root-final [y] undergoes<br />

deleti<strong>on</strong> in the examples in (68)b.<br />

(68) a. naa-bóyw-i̹i̹le ‘catch’ ni-chékw-i̹i̹le ‘shave’<br />

b. tu-sák-i̹i̹le ‘germinate’ naa-égel-i̹i̹le ‘approach’<br />

The overall generalizati<strong>on</strong> is as follows: am<strong>on</strong>g polysyllabic stems, glide-final stems take<br />

-i̹i̹le, and all other polysyllabic stems take -i̹- unless a more specific factor selects some<br />

other allomorph (such as a final l<strong>on</strong>g vowel, or as in the case of stems in yaan/waan). The<br />

post-glide allomorph does not readily derive from the same underlying form as the<br />

general allomorph that occurs with polysyllabic stems (-i̹-). Therefore, this appears to be<br />

a case of suppleti<strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by the presence of a stem-final glide. What is<br />

particularly interesting is that the glide that c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s the selecti<strong>on</strong> of the -i̹i̹le allomorph<br />

is not actually present in some examples, as in examples such as naa-égel-i̹i̹le ‘approach’,<br />

corresp<strong>on</strong>ding to the infinitive form égelya. The perfective form undergoes glide deleti<strong>on</strong><br />

in this example through a general rule of the language, Homorganic Glide Deleti<strong>on</strong><br />

(Odden 1996: 108), which deletes glides before a homorganic vowel. The fact that the<br />

glide that c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s suppleti<strong>on</strong> is itself not present in the surface form presents a<br />

problem for any approach that would attempt to account for allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong> solely<br />

102


through surface c<strong>on</strong>straints. This can <strong>on</strong>ly be handled in the P >> M approach if we make<br />

our P c<strong>on</strong>straints refer to underlying glides that do not surface.<br />

To summarize, in this secti<strong>on</strong> we have seen examples in which the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong><br />

allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong> are rendered opaque by other ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes. These<br />

examples cannot be handled by surface well-formedness c<strong>on</strong>straints. Since they do not<br />

produce better-formed outputs, these examples can be said to be n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing just like<br />

the examples seen in the preceding secti<strong>on</strong>, the <strong>on</strong>ly difference being that in some cases<br />

we can account for the opaque examples using regular ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints, provided<br />

that we allow these c<strong>on</strong>straints to refer to underlying elements that do not surface. As has<br />

been pointed out throughout this secti<strong>on</strong>, the existence of opaque PCSA is problematic<br />

for P >> M. However, it is predicted and easily accounted for in the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

approach that I advocate here, since in this approach, the selecti<strong>on</strong> of affixes for stems<br />

takes place in morphology, which precedes the applicati<strong>on</strong> of ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes at<br />

each level.<br />

2.1.3 Summary<br />

In the preceding discussi<strong>on</strong>, we have seen examples of PCSA resulting in<br />

assimilati<strong>on</strong>, dissimilati<strong>on</strong>, syllable structure optimizati<strong>on</strong>, and syllable c<strong>on</strong>tact<br />

optimizati<strong>on</strong> (perhaps). We have also discussed a number of examples that do not<br />

optimize surface forms, including examples in which the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> allomorph<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong> fail to surface, due to regular ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes. As has been discussed,<br />

the C/V distincti<strong>on</strong> as well as a range of ph<strong>on</strong>ological features can c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> PCSA, and<br />

in some cases the results look similar to the results of ph<strong>on</strong>ological rules. This is a pattern<br />

103


that we would predict under the P >> M model of PCSA. On the other hand, we have<br />

seen a number of examples that do not c<strong>on</strong>form well to the predicti<strong>on</strong>s of P >> M. For<br />

example, in Bari, we found a number of affixes exhibiting PCSA that resulted in vowel<br />

harm<strong>on</strong>y or disharm<strong>on</strong>y or a combinati<strong>on</strong> of both. In some cases the pattern for <strong>on</strong>e<br />

allomorph was the opposite of that for another allomorph, making it virtually impossible<br />

to capture the whole pattern using a single set of P c<strong>on</strong>straints for the language as a<br />

whole. We also saw a number of n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing PCSA examples. These are also<br />

problematic for the P >> M model, which was designed to account for optimizing PCSA.<br />

Though we can still analyze at least the neutral examples using P >> M, it is not clear<br />

why we would want to do this, since we lose the original motivati<strong>on</strong> for analyzing PCSA<br />

using the same ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints that are used to drive purely ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

processes. In the following secti<strong>on</strong>, I propose an analysis for these cases in terms of<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> frames. As will be seen, we can account for PCSA straightforwardly<br />

using such an approach, and we avoid the problems that come up when we try to model<br />

PCSA using ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints.<br />

2.2 Analysis<br />

In the preceding secti<strong>on</strong>, I presented examples of suppletive allomorphy<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by segments or their features. Here, I outline a general strategy of analysis<br />

for examples of this type. The analysis is in terms of subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>. The<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach to morphology has been advanced in various forms by Lieber<br />

1980, Kiparsky 1982b, Selkirk 1982, Orgun 1996, and Yu 2003, am<strong>on</strong>g others. In this<br />

approach, affixati<strong>on</strong> is handled through subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> frames, which include<br />

104


specificati<strong>on</strong>s for the type of element an affix will attach to (whether the element is a<br />

stem of a certain category or having certain features or properties, or a ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

element, or any combinati<strong>on</strong> of these). Affixes can subcategorize for any element in the<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological representati<strong>on</strong> of the stem (as well as for elements of morphological,<br />

lexical, and other aspects of the stem), the <strong>on</strong>ly apparent restricti<strong>on</strong> being that the affix in<br />

questi<strong>on</strong> must end up adjacent to the ph<strong>on</strong>ological element for which it subcategorizes. 36<br />

Affixati<strong>on</strong> is the selecti<strong>on</strong> of affixes for stems in such a way as to satisfy the<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>al requirements of each morpheme, including ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

requirements.<br />

Taking Hungarian 2sg suffix allomorphy as a representative example, I will now<br />

dem<strong>on</strong>strate how a subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach can be used to analyze cases of suppletive<br />

allomorphy c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by features of the stem-initial or stem-final c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant. Recall<br />

from §2.1.2.2 that in Hungarian in the present indefinite, the 2sg is marked by /-El/ suffix<br />

when the root ends in a sibilant; otherwise, it is marked by /-s/. A set of subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

frames for these suffix allomorphs is shown below.<br />

(69) Hungarian 2sg present indefinite c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> A<br />

[[ [sibilant]#] stem El 2sg pres indef suffix ] 2sg pres indef word<br />

Hungarian 2sg centripetal c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> B (‘elsewhere’)<br />

[[ ] stem s 2sg pres indef suffix ] 2sg pres indef word<br />

The subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> frames are interpreted as follows. In c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> A, which uses<br />

the suffix allomorph found in the more specific c<strong>on</strong>text, -El will attach to the right edge<br />

of any stem (modulo the n<strong>on</strong>-ph<strong>on</strong>ological requirements, which I omit here) that ends in<br />

a segment that is specified [sibilant]. The result of the affixati<strong>on</strong> of -El to the stem is a<br />

36 This restricti<strong>on</strong> is predicted by the Generalized Determinant Focus Adjacency<br />

C<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> (Inkelas 1990), to be discussed later in this secti<strong>on</strong>.<br />

105


word that is marked as 2sg, present indefinite. In c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> B, the ‘elsewhere’ case, 37<br />

-s attaches to the right edge of any eligible stem regardless of its ph<strong>on</strong>ological shape, and<br />

the result of the affixati<strong>on</strong> is again a word that is marked as 2sg. present indefinite.<br />

Suppletive allomorphy c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by the stem-initial or stem-final vowel can be<br />

handled in the same way. For example, in §2.1.2.5, I described a situati<strong>on</strong> in Yucunany<br />

Mixtepec Mixtec where 3sg is marked by -à <strong>on</strong> i-final stems and by -ì elsewhere. Under<br />

the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach, we can say simply that /-à / selects for a stem with a final<br />

/i/, while /-ì/ selects for any stem. This is schematized below.<br />

(70) Yucunany Mixtepec Mixtec 3sg c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> A<br />

[[i#] stem à 3sg suffix ] 3sg word<br />

Yucunany Mixtepec Mixtec 3sg c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> B (‘elsewhere’)<br />

[[ ] stem ì 3sg suffix ] 3sg word<br />

C<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> B involves the further complicati<strong>on</strong> that the -ì suffix replaces the final<br />

vowel of the stem, but this can be handled in the ph<strong>on</strong>ology and therefore is not<br />

problematic for the simple analysis provided here.<br />

37<br />

The noti<strong>on</strong> of the ‘elsewhere’ case may be implemented in any number of different<br />

ways; for example, in an OT model of morphology, some morphological c<strong>on</strong>straint<br />

requiring 2sg to be marked by -s could be outranked by another morphological c<strong>on</strong>straint<br />

requiring 2sg to be marked by -El, which could in turn be outranked by an undominated<br />

(and perhaps inviolable) c<strong>on</strong>straint prohibiting subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> frames from being<br />

disobeyed. Under such a ranking, a hypothetical stem that satisfies both the ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> requirements for the more specific -El allomorph and the (n<strong>on</strong>existent)<br />

requirements for the -s allomorph can have two 2sg candidates that satisfy the highest<br />

ranked c<strong>on</strong>straint against violati<strong>on</strong> of subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> frames, but the candidate<br />

satisfying the highly ranked 2sg=-El c<strong>on</strong>straint will win out over the candidate satisfying<br />

2sg=-s, and therefore the allomorph with the more specific envir<strong>on</strong>ment will always be<br />

used when that envir<strong>on</strong>ment is met. In a different hypothetical case where the stem does<br />

not meet the requirements for affixati<strong>on</strong> of the more specific allomorph, the inviolable<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straint against violating subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> frames will filter out candidates that<br />

incorrectly use the more specific allomorph.<br />

106


This approach can also easily handle suppletive allomorphy c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed based <strong>on</strong><br />

whether the stem-initial/final segment is a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant or vowel. Ergative allomorphy in<br />

Warrgamay (Dix<strong>on</strong> 1980), discussed in §2.1.2.3, is an example of this. As described<br />

above, in Warrgamay the ergative is marked by -ŋgu after a vowel-final stem, or by -du<br />

after a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stem. Subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> frames for these two suffixes are shown<br />

below. Note that I have not characterized either suffix as the ‘elsewhere’ form since the<br />

two allomorphs exhibit perfect complementarity and neither occurs in a more specific<br />

envir<strong>on</strong>ment than the other.<br />

(71) Warrgamay ergative c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> A<br />

[[V#] stem du ergative suffix ] ergative word<br />

Warrgamay ergative c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> B<br />

[[C#] stem ŋgu ergative suffix ] ergative word<br />

Because the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> frames do not encode the apparent optimizati<strong>on</strong> that<br />

results from some examples of C/V-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed PCSA, the exact same analysis can be<br />

used with equally good results for both the optimizing and n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing examples of<br />

this type.<br />

So far in this discussi<strong>on</strong> we have not addressed <strong>on</strong>e of the most interesting<br />

properties comm<strong>on</strong> to all of the examples presented in this chapter: namely, that the<br />

affixes involved in the suppletive relati<strong>on</strong>ship are always adjacent to the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing<br />

segment or feature of the stem. This is result of the survey is of theoretical interest for<br />

two reas<strong>on</strong>s. The first reas<strong>on</strong> is that it c<strong>on</strong>firms a predicti<strong>on</strong> inherent in a claim made by<br />

Inkelas (1990) building <strong>on</strong> Poser 1985, relating to a different phenomen<strong>on</strong> (namely,<br />

extrametricality). Extending Poser’s (1985) Determinant Focus Adjacency C<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>,<br />

Inkelas (1990) proposed a Generalized Determinant Focus Adjacency C<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong><br />

107


(GDFAC), given below (this was also discussed in chapter 1).<br />

(72) Generalized Determinant Focus Adjacency C<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>: Each ph<strong>on</strong>ologically<br />

c<strong>on</strong>strained element must be adjacent to each c<strong>on</strong>straining element.<br />

If the GDFAC is a true principle of grammar, then the adjacency phenomen<strong>on</strong><br />

observed in the survey can be said to follow from this principle. However, there is<br />

another possible explanati<strong>on</strong> for the fact that PCSA always involves local c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing.<br />

This relates to the historical development of PCSA, which I hypothesize to arise, in many<br />

cases, from a general ph<strong>on</strong>ological rule whose domain of applicati<strong>on</strong> somehow becomes<br />

restricted to a single morphological c<strong>on</strong>text. This hypothesis is supported by the<br />

difficulty, pointed out above, in distinguishing suppletive allomorphy from allomorphy<br />

derived via ph<strong>on</strong>ological rules specific to particular morphological envir<strong>on</strong>ments. If it is<br />

true that PCSA often or usually arises via the restricti<strong>on</strong> of a ph<strong>on</strong>ological rule to a<br />

particular morpheme, then this could explain why allomorphs are adjacent to the edge of<br />

the stem that determines their distributi<strong>on</strong>. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g> rules generally apply locally (if<br />

we expand the term ‘local’ to refer not <strong>on</strong>ly to strictly adjacent segments but to features<br />

that are tier-adjacent), so the morphological patterns of suppleti<strong>on</strong> that arise from the<br />

alloph<strong>on</strong>y derived by these rules should also occur at the same edge of the stem. Thus,<br />

the GDFAC may not be the ultimate explanati<strong>on</strong> for the adjacency effect observed in<br />

PCSA, but as a principle of grammar it is c<strong>on</strong>sistent with the results of this survey, and it<br />

provides us with a way of accounting for the adjacency effects within the<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach.<br />

We have thus seen that the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach is well equipped to model<br />

the locality generalizati<strong>on</strong> observed in the data. Under the P >> M approach, <strong>on</strong> the other<br />

hand, examples of n<strong>on</strong>-locally c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed PCSA are predicted to exist. For example, an<br />

108


OCP c<strong>on</strong>straint banning multiple instances of a particular feature in a word (e.g., [labial])<br />

could force the grammar to choose a different allomorph if an -m suffix were to be<br />

attached to a labial-initial stem. This type of example is unattested in the surveyed<br />

languages, so in this domain it appears that the P >> M model overpredicts and is too<br />

powerful. This is therefore an important difference between the two models, since as<br />

discussed above, the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> rules out the unattested n<strong>on</strong>-local c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing of<br />

PCSA.<br />

2.3 C<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong><br />

In this chapter we have seen a number of examples in which suppletive<br />

allomorphy is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by segments and/or their features. Some observati<strong>on</strong>s that<br />

were made about these examples were as follows. First, we have seen that c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong><br />

PCSA are local, in that the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> is always at the edge of the stem where the affix<br />

allomorphs attach. Sec<strong>on</strong>d, it was dem<strong>on</strong>strated that a wide range of features, in additi<strong>on</strong><br />

to the C/V distincti<strong>on</strong>, can determine allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong>. Third, we have seen many<br />

examples that are not obviously optimizing. Finally, we have seen examples of opaque<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> PCSA, which show that allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong> is sensitive to input<br />

properties of the stem, not output properties.<br />

An analysis of these examples based <strong>on</strong> subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> for ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

elements was proposed in §2.2. We have seen that subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> can handle the<br />

examples described above without difficulty. As has been discussed, the P >> M model<br />

does not fare as well in dealing with some of the cases presented here. P >> M was<br />

c<strong>on</strong>ceived in order to account for cases of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically optimizing PCSA that follows<br />

109


from well-known ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints. When PCSA seems not to be optimizing or<br />

would require stipulating unnatural or language-specific c<strong>on</strong>straints, we lose the<br />

advantage of generality and explanatory power that has compelled researchers to use the<br />

P >> M model to account for PCSA in the past. This problem is avoided in the<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> model, which does not rely <strong>on</strong> ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints to account for<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological effects in morphology.<br />

In chapters 3 and 4, I discuss further results of the cross-linguistic survey<br />

involving suppletive allomorphy c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by other types of ph<strong>on</strong>ological factors, and I<br />

propose analyses for those examples al<strong>on</strong>g the same lines as the analysis outlined in this<br />

chapter. As we will see, the other types of PCSA to be discussed pose similar challenges<br />

for P >> M and lend themselves equally well to subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>-based analyses.<br />

110


Chapter 3: T<strong>on</strong>e/stress c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy<br />

In this chapter, I c<strong>on</strong>sider cases of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive<br />

allomorphy (PCSA) where the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing factor is the t<strong>on</strong>e or stress pattern of the stem.<br />

This survey revealed few such cases in comparis<strong>on</strong> to the other types of PCSA described<br />

in chapters 2 and 4, but each case is robust enough so that there can be no questi<strong>on</strong> that<br />

the phenomen<strong>on</strong> exists. This chapter is structured as follows. First, in §3.1, I give<br />

examples of PCSA c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by t<strong>on</strong>e or stress. In §3.2, I give a subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>-<br />

based analysis of this phenomen<strong>on</strong> al<strong>on</strong>g the same lines as the analyses provided in<br />

chapters 2 and 4 for different types of PCSA. I c<strong>on</strong>clude in §3.3.<br />

3.1 Survey results<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong>, I present examples of PCSA that involve c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing by stress or<br />

t<strong>on</strong>e. These examples were revealed by a cross-linguistic survey of PCSA, the details of<br />

which were described in chapter 1. A search of over 600 grammars revealed 137 cases of<br />

PCSA in 67 different languages. Of these, eight cases (from seven different languages)<br />

are stress- or t<strong>on</strong>e-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed; these are the cases that I will discuss here. The relatively<br />

small number of cases of this type in comparis<strong>on</strong> to other types of PCSA is somewhat<br />

puzzling. Languages with t<strong>on</strong>e or a prominent stress pattern often exhibit several<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological rules or c<strong>on</strong>straints resulting in t<strong>on</strong>e or stress pattern effects (such as high<br />

t<strong>on</strong>e dissimilati<strong>on</strong>, t<strong>on</strong>al plateauing, t<strong>on</strong>e spreading, and stress clash and lapse<br />

avoidance), so we might expect this to extend to PCSA as well.<br />

C<strong>on</strong>trary to this expectati<strong>on</strong>, few cases of PCSA c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by stress or t<strong>on</strong>e<br />

were found. There is the possibility that some cases were missed by the survey, but given<br />

111


the efforts to make the survey large and balanced, it seems unlikely that such a significant<br />

class of examples could have been systematically neglected. One possible factor in the<br />

apparent lack of cases of stress-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy is that there is some overlap<br />

between these cases and the cases of foot-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed PCSA to be described in chapter 4.<br />

Some cases that we might want to describe as being stress-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed may have ended<br />

up in chapter 4 since they could also be viewed as being foot-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed. The lack of<br />

cases of stress-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy may therefore be due in part to the (somewhat<br />

artificial) divisi<strong>on</strong> between the stress-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy described in this chapter<br />

and the foot-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy to be described in chapter 4.<br />

However, this does not explain the lack of cases of t<strong>on</strong>e-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy,<br />

which remains puzzling. Only two examples of t<strong>on</strong>e-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed PCSA were revealed by<br />

the survey, despite the fact that over half of the world’s languages have t<strong>on</strong>e and a<br />

significant number of these languages must exhibit some t<strong>on</strong>al ph<strong>on</strong>ology. I will leave<br />

this problem for future c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

This secti<strong>on</strong> is organized as follows. I begin in §3.1.1 with a general discussi<strong>on</strong> of<br />

the expected and attested types of stress- and t<strong>on</strong>e-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed PCSA. In secti<strong>on</strong> §3.1.1.1,<br />

I present examples of stress-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by stress. In §3.1.1.2, I<br />

discuss examples of stem allomorphy (t<strong>on</strong>e- and stress-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed). In §3.1.1.3, I present<br />

an example of t<strong>on</strong>e-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed PCSA. In §3.1.1.4, I discuss an example of stress-<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy that appears not to be optimizing. I c<strong>on</strong>clude in §3.1.2 with a<br />

summary of these examples before moving to the analysis in §3.2.<br />

112


3.1.1 Examples<br />

3.1.1.1 Stress effects<br />

Many languages exhibit stress assignment rules/c<strong>on</strong>straints that seem to maximize<br />

alternating patterns of stressed and unstressed syllables in a word. C<strong>on</strong>straints such as<br />

CLASH and LAPSE have been devised to account for the apparent universal dispreferences<br />

for sequences of two stressed or two unstressed syllables, respectively (see e.g. Prince<br />

1983, Selkirk 1984). In ph<strong>on</strong>ology, violati<strong>on</strong>s of CLASH and LAPSE are most comm<strong>on</strong>ly<br />

repaired via stress shift, so that the underlying stress pattern (if any) of a morpheme or<br />

the stress pattern assigned to it in citati<strong>on</strong> form is changed in certain c<strong>on</strong>texts to optimize<br />

the overall stress pattern of the word. In PCSA, we might imagine that highly-ranked<br />

CLASH or LAPSE could cause an inherently stressless affix allomorph to be selected when<br />

it occurs next to a stressed stem syllable, or vice versa. Of course, in order for us to know<br />

that a given example involved suppletive allomorphy rather than purely ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

allomorphy, the affix allomorphs in questi<strong>on</strong> would have to differ in more than just their<br />

stress pattern; i.e., they would probably also need to be different in their segmental<br />

makeup. Three such examples are attested in the survey, to be discussed below.<br />

Aside from alternating stress patterns, another stress-related c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong> is the<br />

noti<strong>on</strong> of the optimal stress-bearing syllable. In many languages, stress is ‘attracted’ to<br />

certain syllable types, usually heavy syllables. In some cases, it has been claimed that<br />

stress can also be attracted to syllables having certain vowels, not <strong>on</strong>ly in terms of their<br />

length, but in some cases their quality (though this may relate to durati<strong>on</strong> if high vowels<br />

are inherently shorter than low vowels). In this secti<strong>on</strong>, I discuss <strong>on</strong>e case where it has<br />

113


een claimed that PCSA results in stress occurring <strong>on</strong> syllables c<strong>on</strong>taining a vowel that is<br />

an optimal bearer of stress.<br />

An example of PCSA resulting in an alternating stress pattern is found in Dutch<br />

(Booij 1997), where the plural is marked by -s or -en, depending <strong>on</strong> whether the final<br />

syllable of the base word is unstressed or stressed, respectively. Examples are given<br />

below (Booij 1997: 272-273; stem-final doubled c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants are orthographic <strong>on</strong>ly).<br />

(1) a. dam ‘dam’ dámm-en ‘dams’<br />

kanón ‘gun’ kanónn-en ‘guns’<br />

kanáal ‘channel’ kanáal-en ‘channels’<br />

lèdikánt ‘bed’ lèdikánt-en ‘beds’<br />

ólifànt ‘elephant’ ólifànt-en ‘elephants’<br />

b. kán<strong>on</strong> ‘can<strong>on</strong>’ kán<strong>on</strong>-s ‘can<strong>on</strong>s’<br />

bézəm ‘sweep’ bézəm-s ‘sweeps’<br />

tóga ‘gown’ tóga-s ‘gowns’<br />

proféssor ‘professor’ proféssor-s ‘professors’<br />

If the -en suffix is inherently unstressed, then using it with the stems in (1)b would have<br />

resulted in a sequence of unstressed syllables. It could therefore be said, in P >> M terms,<br />

that the allomorphy is driven by LAPSE. Of course, an alternative way to avoid a LAPSE<br />

violati<strong>on</strong> if -en were used with unstressed-final stems would be to stress the syllable<br />

c<strong>on</strong>taining the -en suffix. However, this would require us to posit a m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic foot at<br />

the end of the word; the allomorphy can therefore be said to optimize foot structure as<br />

well (or, to help avoid the creati<strong>on</strong> of subminimal feet). 1<br />

This Dutch example is interesting for another reas<strong>on</strong>, namely that it appears to be<br />

sensitive to derived ph<strong>on</strong>ological informati<strong>on</strong> since stress when predictable is usually<br />

1<br />

For this reas<strong>on</strong>, the Dutch example also fits into the category of examples discussed in<br />

chapter 4 (§4.1.1.1) in which allomorphy appears to be motivated by foot structure. I<br />

have discussed the example here instead of in chapter 4 since Booij (1997) characterizes<br />

it as being driven by stress.<br />

114


assumed to be assigned by the grammar rather than being lexically specified. Sensitivity<br />

to derived properties is predicted for PCSA both by the P >> M model and by any<br />

approach such as Lexical Ph<strong>on</strong>ology (Kiparsky 1982a, Mohanan 1986) where<br />

morphological processes apply cyclically and where ph<strong>on</strong>ological and morphological<br />

processes are ‘interleaved’ in grammar. However, it is not entirely clear that Dutch<br />

provides an example of sensitivity to derived properties, because stress is not entirely<br />

predictable, as acknowledged by Booij and Lieber (1993: 41) in their treatment of the<br />

Dutch adjectival suffix (to be discussed in §3.1.1.4). Assuming that stress normally falls<br />

<strong>on</strong> the penultimate syllable, the stems in (1)a would need to be lexically specified as<br />

having final stress. Thus, if we claim that -en occurs with final-stressed stems and -s<br />

occurs ‘elsewhere’, then we do not have to refer to any derived properties. On the other<br />

hand, if -s is c<strong>on</strong>sidered to be the more specific allomorph, then its distributi<strong>on</strong> would<br />

need to refer to a derived property, namely the default penultimate stress that is assumed<br />

to be assigned by a general rule of the language. The problem is that it is not entirely<br />

clear which is the more specific allomorph and which is the ‘elsewhere’ allomorph here.<br />

Another possible case of reference to a derived property is found in Spanish,<br />

where the feminine definite article has two allomorphs whose distributi<strong>on</strong> is stress-<br />

sensitive (Kikuchi 2001). The most comm<strong>on</strong>ly used allomorph is la, but the form el<br />

occurs before stems that begin with a stressed /a/. Some examples involving a-initial<br />

stems are shown below (Kikuchi 2001: 50). Note that all of these nouns have feminine<br />

gender.<br />

(2) a. la alméja ‘the clam’ la anguíla ‘the eel’<br />

la aréna ‘the arena’ la amíga ‘the friend’<br />

b. el álma ‘the soul’ el águila ‘the eagle’<br />

el área ‘the area’ el áma ‘the mistress’<br />

115


Kikuchi argues that this pattern is driven by positi<strong>on</strong>al faithfulness (Beckman 1998).<br />

When la occurs before an unstressed /a/, the /a/ vowels of the article and stem coalesce<br />

into a single [a]. Kikuchi claims that el is used when the stem-initial /a/ is stressed in<br />

order to avoid coalescence of a stressed vowel with another vowel. Thus, the initial<br />

stressed /a/ is ‘protected’ by the use of el.<br />

An interesting aspect of this pattern is that the article that is used can change with<br />

the additi<strong>on</strong> of certain affixes to the stem if this causes its stress to shift. Some examples<br />

are shown below (Kikuchi 2001: 50, except where noted).<br />

(3) el água ‘the water’ la aguáda ‘the water supply’<br />

el árma ‘the weap<strong>on</strong>’ la armadúra ‘the weap<strong>on</strong>ry’ (Kikuchi 2000)<br />

If the examples in (3) are indeed productively suffixed forms, then this c<strong>on</strong>stitutes<br />

an example of PCSA that makes reference to a derived ph<strong>on</strong>ological property. The<br />

determinati<strong>on</strong> of which allomorph to use for the definite article must be carried out after<br />

the attachment of affixes in (3). These affixes trigger a shift of the stem stress <strong>on</strong>e<br />

syllable to the right, so that the initial /a/ is no l<strong>on</strong>ger stressed. Then, when the definite<br />

article is added, the more specific (el) allomorph ‘checks’ the stem for a stressed initial<br />

/a/. Due to the stress shift triggered by affixati<strong>on</strong>, aguáda and armadúra do not satisfy<br />

this c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>, so el is not used; the more general allomorph la is used instead. Thus, the<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs refers to a stress pattern that was not present in the underlying<br />

form of the stem.<br />

Although this seems <strong>on</strong> its surface to be a good example of PCSA that refers to a<br />

derived property, there is a problem with the example, which is that in some cases a stress<br />

shift does not result in a change to the form of the definite article as expected. Kikuchi<br />

116


(2000) points out that diminutive forms whose stems have initial stressed /a/ take the el<br />

article even though their stress shifts, as in the examples below. 2<br />

(4) el áma ‘the mistress’ el amíta ‘the mistress (dim.)’<br />

el álma ‘the soul’ el almíta ‘the soul (dim.)’<br />

Furthermore, el is also used with compounds, which have stress <strong>on</strong> the rightmost element,<br />

when the leftmost element has initial stressed [a] in its citati<strong>on</strong> form.<br />

(5) el água ‘the water’ el aguafuérte ‘etching’ el aguamála ‘jellyfish’<br />

The fact that el occurs unexpectedly in these examples suggests that the definite<br />

article is sensitive to the stress pattern of the stem rather than the word. This is somewhat<br />

puzzling since the morphological bracketing should be such that the definite article<br />

(which is a clitic) occurs outside the stem+affixes, as follows: [article [[stem]-suffix]].<br />

There are two possible soluti<strong>on</strong>s to this puzzle. The first is to assume that stress is<br />

assigned at the stem level and that stress shift in compounds and affixed forms occurs not<br />

immediately after compounding or affixati<strong>on</strong> has applied, but rather at the level of the<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological word, i.e. after cliticizati<strong>on</strong>. This would allow the clitic to refer to the stress<br />

pattern of the stem before stress shift takes place. A sec<strong>on</strong>d possibility is that there is a<br />

mismatch between the morphological and ph<strong>on</strong>ological bracketing of words with the<br />

definite article, so that the article and the word-initial stem form a ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>stituent to the exclusi<strong>on</strong> of what follows (i.e., a suffix or the sec<strong>on</strong>d member of a<br />

compound). In either case, we have a way around the problem in the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

approach to PCSA, but this example is difficult in the P >> M model because the<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> that determines the allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong> is rendered opaque by stress shift.<br />

2 Much of Kikuchi (2000) is duplicated in Kikuchi (2001), but the diminutive and<br />

compound forms discussed here appear <strong>on</strong>ly in Kikuchi (2000).<br />

117


Because OT (and, in particular, the P >> M model) is surface-oriented, the P >> M model<br />

predicts that we should not find examples of PCSA whose c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s are rendered<br />

opaque by ‘later’ ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes. Some other examples of this type were seen in<br />

chapter 2 as well and were argued to provide evidence in support of the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

approach to PCSA.<br />

An example of a different type of stress-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy is found in<br />

Shipibo (Panoan, Peru; Elías-Ulloa 2004). This case seems to involve the noti<strong>on</strong> of<br />

optimal stress-bearing syllables or vowels. In Shipibo, the suffix meaning ‘again’ takes<br />

the form -ribi when the sec<strong>on</strong>d syllable of the suffix is an even-numbered syllable<br />

(counting from left to right) and -riba when the sec<strong>on</strong>d syllable of the suffix is in an odd-<br />

numbered syllable. Some examples are provided below (Elías-Ulloa 2004: 2-3; examples<br />

are originally from Lauriault 1948 except where noted).<br />

(6) y<strong>on</strong>o-ribi-kɨ ka-ma-ribi-kɨ<br />

command-Again-Past go-Caus-Again-Past<br />

‘commanded again’ ‘went again’<br />

pi-riba-kɨ yomɨtso-riba-kɨ<br />

eat-Again-Past steal-Again-Past<br />

‘ate again’ ‘stole again’<br />

ka-yama-riba-kɨ<br />

go-Neg-Again-Past<br />

‘do not go again’ (from Elías-Ulloa field notes)<br />

Elías-Ulloa relates this to the stress pattern of the language, which stresses the sec<strong>on</strong>d<br />

syllable if it is closed, or otherwise the first syllable. He accounts for the -ribi ~ -riba<br />

allomorphy using the c<strong>on</strong>straint rankings *i/Head >> *a/Head and *a/N<strong>on</strong>Head >><br />

*i/N<strong>on</strong>Head. These c<strong>on</strong>straints are claimed to account for why -riba allomorph occurs<br />

when its sec<strong>on</strong>d syllable will be stressed, while -ribi occurs when its sec<strong>on</strong>d syllable will<br />

118


not be stressed: [a] is more s<strong>on</strong>orous than [i] and is therefore a better bearer of stress than<br />

[i]. While it seems desirable to relate the allomorphy to the stress system, Elías-Ulloa<br />

does not c<strong>on</strong>sider the possibility that /-ribi/ surfaces as -riba when the sec<strong>on</strong>d syllable is<br />

stressed. This would require a rule, specific to the ‘again’ suffix, changing i to a in a<br />

stressed syllable. Though this rule would be item-specific, it would still be a ph<strong>on</strong>etically<br />

motivated rule, using Elías-Ulloa’s argument that [a] is a better stress-bearer than [i].<br />

Thus, we cannot be sure that this is a case of PCSA. N<strong>on</strong>etheless, it does seem to be an<br />

example of allomorphy that results in stress occurring <strong>on</strong> a more ‘stressable’ syllable than<br />

it would if there were no allomorphy.<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong> we have seen three examples of stress-related allomorphy. One<br />

example, from Dutch, involved PCSA that seemed to maximize an alternating stress<br />

pattern while preventing the creati<strong>on</strong> of m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic feet. Another example, the case of<br />

the Spanish feminine definite article, involved the preferential retenti<strong>on</strong> of a stressed<br />

vowel in surface forms. The third example, from Shipibo, appeared to ensure that stress<br />

occurred <strong>on</strong> syllables c<strong>on</strong>taining /a/, which is c<strong>on</strong>sidered to be a good stress-bearing<br />

vowel since it is highly s<strong>on</strong>orous. Thus, we have seen three different ways in which<br />

PCSA can be argued to be driven by ph<strong>on</strong>ological optimizati<strong>on</strong>. This is c<strong>on</strong>sistent with<br />

the P >> M model, though note that it is also c<strong>on</strong>sistent with the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

approach (as will be dem<strong>on</strong>strated in §3.2).<br />

3.1.1.2 Stem allomorphy<br />

In the preceding secti<strong>on</strong>, we saw examples in which the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs<br />

of an affix or clitic was determined by stress. So far, we have not discussed any<br />

119


examples in which a stem exhibits PCSA; even in chapter 2, where 74 cases of<br />

segmentally c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed PCSA were discussed, we did not find any examples of stem<br />

allomorphy. This is a striking result. It raises the questi<strong>on</strong> of why there are not more<br />

examples, and also why the attested examples are not segmentally c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed but rather<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by more ‘global’ or suprasegmental factors such as stress and t<strong>on</strong>e. The P >><br />

M model of PCSA does not answer these questi<strong>on</strong>s.<br />

The subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach, <strong>on</strong> the other hand, allows us to account for this<br />

cross-linguistic pattern as follows. First, since we are assuming that words are built ‘from<br />

the inside out,’ we predict that allomorphy in a root should never be sensitive to<br />

properties of an affix. As will be seen, this predicti<strong>on</strong> can be maintained based <strong>on</strong> the<br />

present survey. We furthermore predict that allomorphy in the ‘stem of affixati<strong>on</strong>’ should<br />

also never be sensitive to properties of any affix, with the following excepti<strong>on</strong>: if what<br />

appears to be the stem is morphologically complex, then in some cases the material that<br />

occurs next to the root could possibly be an infix, in which case its distributi<strong>on</strong> could be<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed based <strong>on</strong> some property of an affix that attaches ‘before’ the infix but ends<br />

up farther away from the root in terms of surface linear order. Since this is a very specific<br />

and complex scenario, we expect that it should not occur very often, and therefore that<br />

examples of this type should be rare. It is also crucial that in such cases, the root should<br />

be extractable from the ‘pseudo-stem’ that is formed by the additi<strong>on</strong> of the infix; if all of<br />

the root’s segments are not c<strong>on</strong>tained in this pseudo-stem, then we must c<strong>on</strong>clude that we<br />

are dealing with root allomorphy rather than stem allomorphy; this then would c<strong>on</strong>tradict<br />

a predicti<strong>on</strong> of the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> model as presented here. The subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

approach severely restricts the possibility of affix-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed stem allomorphy, but note<br />

120


that other types of ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing <strong>on</strong> stems may still be permitted if the<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> is imposed from outside of the word. The model that I am using<br />

here is <strong>on</strong>ly meant to account for morphological processes and does not make predicti<strong>on</strong>s<br />

for or set limitati<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> ph<strong>on</strong>ological interacti<strong>on</strong>s above the level of the word.<br />

While P >> M predicts that stem allomorphy c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

properties of affixes should be perfectly acceptable, the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach<br />

severely restricts the instances in which stem allomorphy can occur, as discussed above.<br />

N<strong>on</strong>etheless, some types of stem allomorphy are still allowed and able to be captured in<br />

the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach, and in fact, as menti<strong>on</strong>ed above, some such cases are<br />

attested. In this chapter, I discuss two cases of PCSA involving stem allomorphy: <strong>on</strong>e<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by stress, and the other c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by t<strong>on</strong>e.<br />

An example of stress-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed stem allomorphy occurs in Italian (Hall 1948).<br />

In Italian, some stems have allomorphs ending in /isk/ that occur <strong>on</strong>ly in morphological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>texts where the word stress falls <strong>on</strong> the root-final syllable, namely, in the present and<br />

subjunctive 1sg, 2sg, 3sg, and 3pl and in the 2sg imperative (Hall 1948: 25, 27). One<br />

such root is fin- ‘finish’; some examples are shown below (Hall 1948: 214).<br />

(7) Present<br />

finísk-o ‘I finish’ fin-iámo ‘we finish’<br />

finíšš-i ‘you (sg.) finish’ fin-íte ‘you (pl.) finish’<br />

finíšš-e ‘s/he finishes’ finísk-ɔno ‘they finish’<br />

Subjunctive<br />

finísk-a ‘that I finish’ fin-iámo ‘that we finish’<br />

finísk-a ‘that you (sg.) finish’ fin-iáte ‘that you (pl.) finish’<br />

finísk-a ‘that s/he finish’ finísk-ano ‘that they finish’<br />

Imperative<br />

fin-iámo ‘let’s finish’<br />

finíšš-i ‘(you (sg.)) finish!’ fin-íte ‘(you (pl.)) finish!’<br />

121


Other roots of this type include aǧ- ‘act’ (Hall 1948: 43), argu- ‘argue’ (1948: 44), dilu-<br />

‘add water’ (1948: 45), mɛńt- ‘lie’ (1948: 45), diminu- ‘diminish’ (1948: 52), and<br />

amm<strong>on</strong>- ‘adm<strong>on</strong>ish’ (1948: 61). There appears not to be any semantic or ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

generalizati<strong>on</strong> regarding which roots pattern with this class. A possible motivati<strong>on</strong> for<br />

this pattern of allomorphy is stress clash avoidance. If we assume that /isk/ is inherently<br />

stressed, then its occurrence next to an inherently stressed suffix would create a stress<br />

clash, so /isk/ is avoided in that c<strong>on</strong>text.<br />

This example is particularly interesting and important because it is the first case<br />

of apparent stem allomorphy that we have seen. As noted above, no examples were<br />

discussed in chapter 2, which described cases of segmentally c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy.<br />

The subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach allows us to explain the relative rarity of stem<br />

allomorphy, but it also requires us to assume that /isk/ here is an infix. This may provoke<br />

some skepticism, but in modern analyses of Italian stem allomorphy (e.g., DiFabio 1990,<br />

Schwarze 1999), -isc is c<strong>on</strong>sidered to be an affix or ‘stem extensi<strong>on</strong>’ (Schwarze 1999).<br />

Therefore, it is already assumed that stems c<strong>on</strong>taining -isc do not exhibit root<br />

allomorphy, but rather the presence or absence of -isc is determined by the stress pattern<br />

of the word. And, in fact, DiFabio (1990) analyzes -isc- as an infix. 3 Assuming that -isc-<br />

3<br />

The fact that separate stems fin- and finisc- co-existed at an earlier stage in the history<br />

of Italian does not preclude an infixati<strong>on</strong> analysis, since speakers could have created the<br />

infix -isc- <strong>on</strong> the basis of the existence of other such pairs of verbs in the language.<br />

However, if each of the two separate stems previously was able to occur in all of the<br />

morphological/ph<strong>on</strong>ological envir<strong>on</strong>ments in (7), then we are faced with the questi<strong>on</strong> of<br />

how the stem allomorphs came to be distributed in the modern language (after the stems<br />

collapsed into a single suppletive paradigm) in just such a way so as to avoid stress clash.<br />

One possibility is that forms of each stem with every possible inflecti<strong>on</strong>al suffix coexisted<br />

at some stage, and as the separate stems merged, perhaps via the creati<strong>on</strong> of the -<br />

isc- infix, the forms without -isc- preferentially survived in the stressed suffix<br />

envir<strong>on</strong>ment because they had a more harm<strong>on</strong>ic rhythmic pattern than those with -isc-<br />

122


is an infix explains how it can be sensitive to a property of the stem that is determined by<br />

affixes that occur later in the word (in terms of their linear order), without posing any<br />

problem for the ‘inside-out’ directi<strong>on</strong> of word formati<strong>on</strong> in the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

approach advocated here. This move may seem to be a clever trick designed to uphold the<br />

predicti<strong>on</strong> that affixes cannot c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> stem allomorphy. However, as discussed earlier,<br />

the lack of cases of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed stem allomorphy is striking given the<br />

number of cases involving affix allomorphy. Furthermore, it is not the case that any<br />

possible putative case of stem allomorphy could be explained away. The infixati<strong>on</strong><br />

account is possible for Italian because isc is present in all of the extended stems, but<br />

imagine a language in which some stems had an etymologically unrelated allomorph with<br />

an extra syllable that was used in a particular stress c<strong>on</strong>text. For example, if complet- (lit.<br />

‘complete’) were used instead of finisc- where it occurs in the paradigm of fin-, it would<br />

be impossible to claim that the allomorphy resulted from the additi<strong>on</strong> of a stem extensi<strong>on</strong>,<br />

and we would have to c<strong>on</strong>clude that this was a counterexample to our model. No such<br />

cases were revealed by the present survey.<br />

Another case of stem allomorphy is found in Zahao (Chin, Burma; Osburne<br />

1975). According to Yip (2004), Zahao exhibits suppletive allomorphy in verb stems that<br />

involves t<strong>on</strong>al alternati<strong>on</strong>s. In particular, verbs in Zahao have two stems, a ‘primary’ stem<br />

(this would be true whether -isc- had inherent stress or not; for example, the modern form<br />

fin-íte ‘you (pl.) finish’ has an alternating stress pattern, whereas its hypothetical<br />

competitors finísk-íte and finisk-íte do not). Note, however, that this historical scenario<br />

does not require that speakers ever utilized a ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint in determining when<br />

fin- vs. fin-isc- would be used. In the P >> M model, P c<strong>on</strong>straints are used to determine<br />

which affixes will be allowed to combine with which stems, not to choose between<br />

multiple pre-existing semantically equivalent words. Perhaps the choice between words<br />

already existing in a language is more a c<strong>on</strong>scious stylistic decisi<strong>on</strong> than <strong>on</strong>e that is<br />

driven by c<strong>on</strong>straints or rules of grammar.<br />

123


and a ‘sec<strong>on</strong>dary’ stem. The primary stem is used in main clauses, while sec<strong>on</strong>dary stems<br />

are used in subordinate clauses. Though this can be stated in syntactic terms, there is<br />

some interacti<strong>on</strong> with focus, and Yip suggests that the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing is prosodic. Some<br />

examples of primary-sec<strong>on</strong>dary stem pairs are shown below (following Yip 2004, t<strong>on</strong>es<br />

are given next to the stem; stems with no t<strong>on</strong>e are underlyingly t<strong>on</strong>eless).<br />

(8) Primary stem Sec<strong>on</strong>dary stem Gloss<br />

hmaan L hmaan L ‘be correct’<br />

hreen L hren H ‘lock up, close’<br />

laam LH laam L ‘dance’<br />

hmaan L hmaan L ‘be correct’<br />

ŋaan H ŋaan L ‘write’<br />

ree LH reet H ‘insert’<br />

khur L khurɁ ‘shiver’<br />

cat H caɁ ‘cut off’<br />

Yip points out that in each pair, the sec<strong>on</strong>dary stem is equally or less ‘marked’<br />

than the primary stem in terms of its laryngeal specificati<strong>on</strong> (t<strong>on</strong>e or final glottal stop): if<br />

the primary stem has a c<strong>on</strong>tour t<strong>on</strong>e, then the sec<strong>on</strong>dary stem has a level t<strong>on</strong>e; if the<br />

primary stem has a level t<strong>on</strong>e, then the sec<strong>on</strong>dary stem has either a level t<strong>on</strong>e or a final<br />

glottal stop, which is c<strong>on</strong>sidered to be less marked than a level t<strong>on</strong>e. Yip proposes a<br />

harm<strong>on</strong>ic scale Ɂ > H,L > LH, where the glottal stop is most harm<strong>on</strong>ic and least marked,<br />

the H and L t<strong>on</strong>es are somewhat less harm<strong>on</strong>ic and more marked (but equivalent to each<br />

other <strong>on</strong> the scale), and LH is the least harm<strong>on</strong>ic and the most marked. With respect to<br />

the primary stem, a sec<strong>on</strong>dary stem can either stay at the same level <strong>on</strong> the scale or move<br />

up by <strong>on</strong>e degree (but not two). As seen in the examples above, in some cases there is no<br />

change between the primary and sec<strong>on</strong>dary stem. In Yip’s analysis, the allomorphy is<br />

driven by several different factors, including: first, the existence in the lexic<strong>on</strong> of<br />

124


multiple underlying forms for stems as well as a c<strong>on</strong>straint MAXPARADIGM that requires<br />

every underlying stem form to be realized in some envir<strong>on</strong>ment; sec<strong>on</strong>d, a c<strong>on</strong>straint<br />

requiring that every stem must have a laryngeal specificati<strong>on</strong>; third, c<strong>on</strong>joined MAXH and<br />

MAXL c<strong>on</strong>straints that prevent the sec<strong>on</strong>dary stem from differing from the primary stem<br />

by more than <strong>on</strong>e degree <strong>on</strong> the harm<strong>on</strong>ic scale given above; and finally, a c<strong>on</strong>straint<br />

prohibiting c<strong>on</strong>tour t<strong>on</strong>es in a sec<strong>on</strong>dary stem. In a P >> M terms, all of these c<strong>on</strong>straints<br />

would outrank UNIFORMEXPONENCE, which is the morphological cosntraint that requires<br />

morphemes to be realized c<strong>on</strong>sistently regardless of the envir<strong>on</strong>ment in which they occur.<br />

Note, though, that the existence of this example of stem allomorphy does not<br />

c<strong>on</strong>tradict any of the predicti<strong>on</strong>s made by the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> model as discussed<br />

above, and therefore this need not be taken as evidence in favor of the P >> M model<br />

simply because it can be analyzed in those terms. As noted above, stem allomorphy that<br />

is not c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by an affix does not c<strong>on</strong>stitute a counterexample to the<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach that I am using, especially given that in this particular case,<br />

as acknowledged by Yip (2004), the distributi<strong>on</strong> of stem allomorphs may reduce to<br />

syntactic c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing, which is outside the scope of what is covered by either model of<br />

PCSA being c<strong>on</strong>trasted here.<br />

In summary, in this secti<strong>on</strong> we have seen two examples of stem allomorphy, <strong>on</strong>e<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by stress and <strong>on</strong>e c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by syntax and/or prosodic factors and<br />

involving t<strong>on</strong>al alternati<strong>on</strong>s. As has been discussed, the small number of examples is<br />

problematic for the most basic form of the P >> M model, which does not take into<br />

account morphological c<strong>on</strong>stituency, since in principle this means that stems can exhibit<br />

PCSA just as easily as affixes, which seems not to be the case. On the other hand, as<br />

125


discussed above, the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach allows us to explain why stem PCSA is<br />

relatively rare, while still not ruling out the examples that are attested in the present<br />

survey.<br />

3.1.1.3 T<strong>on</strong>e effects<br />

In additi<strong>on</strong> to the Zahao example described above, <strong>on</strong>e other example of PCSA<br />

involving t<strong>on</strong>e was found in this survey. The fact that <strong>on</strong>ly two examples of t<strong>on</strong>e-related<br />

PCSA were found is somewhat surprising given the fact that ph<strong>on</strong>ological t<strong>on</strong>e rules are<br />

so comm<strong>on</strong> in the world’s languages. We might have expected to find a number of<br />

examples of PCSA resulting in the same surface patterns that result from these t<strong>on</strong>e rules:<br />

t<strong>on</strong>e spread, dissimilati<strong>on</strong> of adjacent H t<strong>on</strong>es, and t<strong>on</strong>al plateauing, to name a few. The<br />

OT c<strong>on</strong>straints CLASH and LAPSE, originally formulated to account for stress patterns, are<br />

now also used for t<strong>on</strong>e (as advocated by Zoll 2002), so we might expect these c<strong>on</strong>straints<br />

to be am<strong>on</strong>g those that could be ranked above a morphological c<strong>on</strong>straint (in a P >> M<br />

analysis), resulting in PCSA. No such examples are found. Other c<strong>on</strong>straints that have<br />

been used for t<strong>on</strong>e include the OBLIGATORY CONTOUR PRINCIPLE (OCP; Leben 1973,<br />

McCarthy 1986) for dissimilati<strong>on</strong> and *H to capture the idea that a high t<strong>on</strong>e is ‘marked’,<br />

especially in languages with an underlying H vs. Ø t<strong>on</strong>e c<strong>on</strong>trast. In the P >> M<br />

approach, we would expect that these c<strong>on</strong>straints could play a role in PCSA as well.<br />

The P >> M also predicts the existence of some n<strong>on</strong>-local t<strong>on</strong>e effects. For<br />

example, a c<strong>on</strong>joined c<strong>on</strong>straint *H&*H ranked over UNIFORMEXPONENCE could result<br />

in l<strong>on</strong>g-distance t<strong>on</strong>al dissimilati<strong>on</strong> such that a H-t<strong>on</strong>ed affix allomorph could fail to be<br />

selected if there is a H t<strong>on</strong>e anywhere in the stem. The subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach that I<br />

126


take here, which includes a requirement that affixes must be adjacent to the ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

elements for which they subcategorize, predicts that any such effect should be purely<br />

local, so that the triggering H t<strong>on</strong>e would have to be at the edge of the stem (or, at the<br />

edge of the stem <strong>on</strong> the t<strong>on</strong>al tier). This difference in predicti<strong>on</strong>s turns out to be<br />

somewhat of a moot point since no cases of PCSA resulting in t<strong>on</strong>e dissimilati<strong>on</strong> of any<br />

kind are found. However, the fact that the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach is more restrictive<br />

regarding types of t<strong>on</strong>e dissimilati<strong>on</strong> is a point in its favor given the lack of any cases at<br />

all. The possibility of c<strong>on</strong>straint c<strong>on</strong>juncti<strong>on</strong> vastly increases the number and type of<br />

possible phenomena predicted by P >> M, and c<strong>on</strong>trary to any argument that c<strong>on</strong>straint<br />

c<strong>on</strong>juncti<strong>on</strong> is not an accepted mechanism in modern mainstream OT, Yip’s (2004)<br />

analysis of Zahao discussed above dem<strong>on</strong>strates that c<strong>on</strong>straint c<strong>on</strong>juncti<strong>on</strong> is still very<br />

much in use in modern OT analyses.<br />

One example of t<strong>on</strong>e-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed PCSA is attested in the survey, though it does<br />

not fit into any of the predicted types described above. The example is found in the<br />

Yucunany dialect of Mixtepec Mixtec (Otomanguean, Mexico; Paster and Beam de<br />

Azc<strong>on</strong>a 2005). This language exhibits PCSA in the first pers<strong>on</strong> singular clitic (subject or<br />

possessor). The 1sg is marked by a floating low t<strong>on</strong>e that associates to the end of the verb<br />

or noun phrase, except in those cases where the final t<strong>on</strong>e of the verb or noun phrase is<br />

low, in which case the first pers<strong>on</strong> singular is marked by the yù allomorph. Examples M-<br />

or H-final stems taking the floating L t<strong>on</strong>e allomorph are shown below (examples are<br />

from my field notes).<br />

127


(9) nàmá ‘soap’ nàmáà ‘my soap’<br />

kwíìí ‘narrow/thin’ kwíìíì ‘I am narrow/thin’<br />

vílú ‘cat’ vílúù ‘my cat’<br />

tìinà ncháá ‘blue dog’ tìinà nchááà ‘my blue dog’<br />

tzàáku ‘corral’ tzàákuù ‘my corral’<br />

yùúti ‘sand’ yùútiì ‘my sand’<br />

sì’i ‘leg’ sì’iì ‘my leg’<br />

kwà’a ‘man’s sister’ kwà’aà ‘my sister’<br />

As seen in the examples below, the yù allomorph occurs following a L t<strong>on</strong>e.<br />

(10) sòkò ‘shoulder’ sòkò yù ‘my shoulder’<br />

tutù ‘paper’ tutù yù ‘my paper’<br />

chá’à ‘short’ chá’à yù ‘I am short’<br />

ve’e nchá’ì ‘black house’ ve’e nchá’ì yù ‘my black house’<br />

This case likely involves suppleti<strong>on</strong> since the two different forms of the 1sg are not<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ologically similar enough to warrant relating them to a single underlying form. Even<br />

if they were, we would want the underlying form to resemble the ‘elsewhere’ allomorph<br />

(the floating L that occurs after H- and M-final roots) rather than the allomorph that<br />

occurs in the more specific envir<strong>on</strong>ment (the yù form that occurs with L-final roots), and<br />

yet this would require us to posit inserti<strong>on</strong> of [yu] following a L-t<strong>on</strong>ed root. This seems<br />

implausible. I c<strong>on</strong>clude that this example involves genuine suppletive allomorphy,<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by the final t<strong>on</strong>e of the root.<br />

This pattern, where the floating L t<strong>on</strong>e allomorph occurs in all envir<strong>on</strong>ments<br />

except where preceded by a L t<strong>on</strong>e, serves to maintain a distincti<strong>on</strong> between 1sg and<br />

unmarked forms. Without the yù allomorph, 1sg forms would be homoph<strong>on</strong>ous with the<br />

unmarked forms of verbs and noun phrases with final L t<strong>on</strong>e. One possible way of<br />

modeling this is to use a ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint against homoph<strong>on</strong>y am<strong>on</strong>g forms in a<br />

128


paradigm. However, we can explain the apparent homoph<strong>on</strong>y avoidance without positing<br />

a c<strong>on</strong>straint that generates it. In a different dialect of Mixtepec Mixtec described by Pike<br />

and Ibach (1978), yù is a 1sg polite marker, while the floating low marks the informal<br />

1sg. This is most likely the c<strong>on</strong>servative dialect since it would be difficult to develop the<br />

semantically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy from the ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>. Furthermore, the<br />

Yucunany dialect does exhibit an informal vs. polite distincti<strong>on</strong> in the 2sg and 3sg,<br />

suggesting that it had such a distincti<strong>on</strong> in the 1sg at an earlier stage.<br />

The tables below show the proposed stages in the development of the modern<br />

pattern of allomorphy in the Yucunany dialect. (11)a shows the original stage, where the<br />

two 1sg markers are distributed based <strong>on</strong> the informal vs. polite distincti<strong>on</strong>. This pattern<br />

is retained in the modern dialect described by Pike and Ibach (1978). (11)b shows a<br />

proposed intermediate stage in the Yucunany dialect, where the semantic distincti<strong>on</strong><br />

between informal and polite in the 1sg has been lost, and both forms of the 1sg marker<br />

still exist in free variati<strong>on</strong>. At this stage, each type of root has two possible 1sg forms, but<br />

L-final stems have <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>on</strong>e form that is not homoph<strong>on</strong>ous with the root. In some<br />

c<strong>on</strong>texts where a L-final root is marked with a redundant final L t<strong>on</strong>e, the intended 1sg<br />

form may be mistaken for a plain form if the 1sg meaning is not of critical relevance in<br />

the discourse. Therefore, assuming that the two allomorphs are used by speakers with<br />

equal frequency, the majority of underlyingly L-final stems that are understood by the<br />

listener to be 1sg forms will have the yù allomorph rather than the floating L t<strong>on</strong>e. Since<br />

it is used more frequently than the floating L t<strong>on</strong>e, the yù allomorph ultimately ‘wins<br />

out’, becoming the <strong>on</strong>ly 1sg marker to be used with L-final roots, as shown in (11)c. At<br />

this stage, <strong>on</strong>e possible development is for the 1sg of M- and H-final roots to be marked<br />

129


<strong>on</strong>ly by yù by analogy with L-final roots. Instead, in the modern dialect, the M- and H-<br />

final roots c<strong>on</strong>verge <strong>on</strong> the floating L t<strong>on</strong>e as the marker of 1sg, as seen in (11)d. One<br />

explanati<strong>on</strong> for this is that speakers picked up the discrepancy between the existence of<br />

the L-final 1sg forms for M- and H-final roots <strong>on</strong> the <strong>on</strong>e hand, and the lack of L-final<br />

1sg forms for L-final roots <strong>on</strong> the other hand. This could have led to the generalizati<strong>on</strong><br />

that yù is used with L-final roots while the floating L t<strong>on</strong>e is used with M- and H-final<br />

roots.<br />

(11) a. Mixtepec Mixtec<br />

Root type Plain form 1sg informal 1sg polite<br />

final L final L final L =yù<br />

final M final M final L =yù<br />

final H final H final L =yù<br />

b. Early Yucunany Mixtepec Mixtec<br />

Root type Plain form 1sg<br />

final L final L final L ~ =yù<br />

final M final M final L ~ =yù<br />

final H final H final L ~ =yù<br />

c. Intermediate Yucunany Mixtepec Mixtec<br />

Root type Plain form 1sg<br />

final L final L =yù<br />

final M final M final L ~ =yù<br />

final H final H final L ~ =yù<br />

d. Modern Yucunany Mixtepec Mixtec<br />

Root type Plain form 1sg<br />

final L final L =yù<br />

final M final M final L<br />

final H final H final L<br />

Thus, the pattern of t<strong>on</strong>e-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy emerged in Yucunany<br />

Mixtepec Mixtec without necessarily being driven by homoph<strong>on</strong>y avoidance. We are<br />

therefore free to analyze the pattern in a way that captures the generalizati<strong>on</strong> without<br />

necessarily encoding the anti-homoph<strong>on</strong>y c<strong>on</strong>cept in our analysis. A subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

130


analysis is thus well-suited to this example, as will be dem<strong>on</strong>strated in §3.2.<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong>, we have discussed <strong>on</strong>e example of t<strong>on</strong>e-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed PCSA.<br />

Including the Zahao example discussed in the preceding secti<strong>on</strong>, there were two t<strong>on</strong>e-<br />

related examples of PCSA found in this survey.<br />

3.1.1.4 N<strong>on</strong>-optimizati<strong>on</strong><br />

In additi<strong>on</strong> to the examples described above, which can each be viewed as<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ologically optimizing in some way, the survey also revealed two examples of stress-<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy where the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs does not appear to optimize<br />

the overall ph<strong>on</strong>ological pattern of the word. By now, such cases will not be surprising<br />

since a number of examples were discussed in chapter 2. However, it should be pointed<br />

out <strong>on</strong>ce again that examples of this kind are problematic for the P >> M model, which<br />

reduces PCSA to resulting from regular ph<strong>on</strong>ological well-formedness c<strong>on</strong>straints. The<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach, <strong>on</strong> the other hand, predicts and accounts straightforwardly<br />

for n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing PCSA.<br />

One example of apparent n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing PCSA that relates to stress is found in<br />

Woleaian (Trukic, Micr<strong>on</strong>esia; Sohn 1975, Sohn and Tawerilmang 1976). According to<br />

Kennedy (2002), the ‘denotative’ marker (which c<strong>on</strong>verts intransitive verbs from<br />

transitive verbs) has two allomorphs. It can either appear as a suffixed reduplicant 4<br />

4<br />

The characterizati<strong>on</strong> of this pattern as suffixing (rather than infixing before the stemfinal<br />

foot) is Kennedy’s. Kennedy does not seem to entertain the infixing analysis,<br />

focusing instead <strong>on</strong> the choice between prefixing vs. suffixing reduplicati<strong>on</strong>: ‘Note that<br />

the order of stem and affix is not immediately certain for forms like fatifeti and many<br />

others, in which a complete bivocalic stem is reduplicated. I treat these forms as suffixed<br />

to be uniform with trivocalic denotatives in this group [which] are clearly suffixed, as in<br />

131


c<strong>on</strong>sisting of the final two syllables of the stem, or as geminati<strong>on</strong> of the initial<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant. 5 Examples are shown below (Kennedy 2002: 4). 6<br />

(12) a. feragi ‘spread’ fferagi ‘to be spread’<br />

ŋüsü-ri ‘snort it’ ŋŋüsü ‘to snort’<br />

pilegü-w ‘bundle it’ ppilegü ‘to be bundled’<br />

sawee-y ‘go al<strong>on</strong>g side of it’ ssawe ‘to go al<strong>on</strong>g side of’<br />

tabee-y ‘follow it’ ttabe ‘to follow’<br />

b. βugo-si ‘tie it’ βugo-βugo ‘to tie’<br />

faŋošo ‘current’ faŋošo-ŋošo ‘to have a little current’<br />

file-ti ‘stir it’ file-file ‘to stir’<br />

masowe ‘hard’ masowe-sowe ‘to be str<strong>on</strong>g’<br />

perase ‘to splash’ perase-rase ‘to scatter’<br />

In Kennedy’s analysis, the locati<strong>on</strong> of the denotative affix (prefix or suffix) is lexically<br />

determined. Then, based <strong>on</strong> its positi<strong>on</strong> the shape of the allomorph is determined by<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints, such that prefixes c<strong>on</strong>sist of geminati<strong>on</strong> of the initial c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant,<br />

while suffixes c<strong>on</strong>sist of a reduplicati<strong>on</strong> of the final two syllables of the stem. In order to<br />

get the shape of the allomorphs, Kennedy first assumes that stems that take the suffixing<br />

form are lexically specified as having a ‘flag’, whose surface correlate is stress, and<br />

which is required to be anchored at the left edge of the word. In effect, this means that the<br />

leftmost syllable of the stem will be the first stressed syllable in the word if the stem has a<br />

flag. By using c<strong>on</strong>straints such as LAPSE and ALLFEETRIGHT, this analysis ensures that<br />

perase-rase.’ (2002: 4). Sohn (1975) does not say explicitly whether reduplicati<strong>on</strong> is<br />

infixing or suffixing, and the examples do not include morpheme breaks.<br />

5<br />

Though <strong>on</strong>e may be tempted to suggest that initial geminati<strong>on</strong> and reduplicati<strong>on</strong> are two<br />

different morphological processes, Sohn implies (1975: 132) that they are the same in<br />

stating that ‘transitive stem minus thematic element + reduplicati<strong>on</strong> equals neutral verb.<br />

(Here reduplicati<strong>on</strong> in neutral verbs includes that of a whole-stem, a part, and c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antdoubling)’<br />

(emphasis mine).<br />

6<br />

According to Sohn (1975: 132-133), these are not the <strong>on</strong>ly two ways to create an<br />

intransitive verb. For example, some verbs undergo truncati<strong>on</strong> and/or vowel changes<br />

(e.g., petangi ‘land <strong>on</strong> it’ → pat ‘to land’, fangiuli ‘wake him up’ → fang ‘to wake up’).<br />

Others appear to undergo prefixing reduplicati<strong>on</strong> (e.g., torofi ‘catch it’ → tottor ‘to<br />

catch’, telati ‘free it’ → tettal ‘to free’).<br />

132


the suffix allomorph can <strong>on</strong>ly be a two syllable reduplicant. Similarly, the c<strong>on</strong>straints<br />

ALLFEETRIGHT and *SEGMENT (similar to *STRUC) cause the prefix always to surface as<br />

initial geminati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

Thus, in an indirect way, the shape of the denotative affix in Woleaian is<br />

determined by stress. This example does not fit neatly into any particular category of<br />

PCSA, nor is it of a type predicted by the P >> M model: even though the OT analysis is<br />

perfectly compatible with the P >> M approach, the ‘flag’ and the c<strong>on</strong>straint that aligns it<br />

to the left edge of the word is stipulative and language-specific, so even though it can be<br />

analyzed using ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints in OT, it is not exactly ‘optimizing’ in the way<br />

that prop<strong>on</strong>ents of the P >> M model view PCSA to be. It could <strong>on</strong>ly be argued to be<br />

optimizing in a very language-specific sense.<br />

Another example of stress-related PCSA that does not appear to be<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ologically optimizing is found in Dutch. In Dutch, two suffixes that are comm<strong>on</strong>ly<br />

used to derive adjectives from nouns are -isch /is/ and -ief /iv/ (Booij and Lieber 1993).<br />

For nouns ending in ie /i/, the distributi<strong>on</strong> of the adjectival suffix allomorphs is<br />

determined by the stress pattern of the stem, as follows: -isch is used if the stem has final<br />

stress, while -ief is used if the stem-final syllable is unstressed. 7 Examples are shown<br />

7<br />

It is possible that the different patterning of forms in (13)a vs. (13)b is based in some<br />

way <strong>on</strong> the origin of the stems rather <strong>on</strong> their stress pattern, since those in (a) have a<br />

Greek origin while those in (b) have a Latin origin. This generalizati<strong>on</strong> is not<br />

c<strong>on</strong>tradicted am<strong>on</strong>g the nouns in ie provided by Booij and Lieber (1993), though as will<br />

be seen in (14), there are other, n<strong>on</strong>-ie nouns taking -isch that are not of Greek origin, e.g.<br />

álgebra (from Arabic). In fact, additi<strong>on</strong>al forms found in Booij (2001: 128) uphold the<br />

alternative generalizati<strong>on</strong>: agressief ‘aggressive’, dem<strong>on</strong>stratief ‘dem<strong>on</strong>strative’, imitatief<br />

‘imitating’, and suppletief ‘suppletive’ are based <strong>on</strong> stems of Latin origin, as is<br />

c<strong>on</strong>servatief ‘c<strong>on</strong>servative’ (Booij 2001: 106); filosofisch ‘philosophical’ (Booij 2001:<br />

108) is of Greek origin. Thus, the trigger of allomorphy could actually be a diacritic<br />

indicating the perceived origin of the stem, rather than its stress pattern. Already Booij<br />

133


elow (Booij and Lieber 1993: 25). 8<br />

(13) a. sociologíe ‘sociology’ sociolog-isch ‘sociological’<br />

blasfemíe ‘blasphemy’ blasfem-isch ‘blasphemous’<br />

allergíe ‘allergy’ allerg-isch ‘allergic’<br />

b. prevéntie ‘preventi<strong>on</strong>’ prevent-ief ‘preventive’<br />

c<strong>on</strong>strúctie ‘c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>’ c<strong>on</strong>struct-ief ‘c<strong>on</strong>structive’<br />

integrátie ‘integrati<strong>on</strong>’ integrat-ief ‘integrating’<br />

Here, there is no indicati<strong>on</strong> that the pattern of allomorphy is optimizing, since both<br />

allomorphs have the shape /iC/ and therefore would not affect the number of syllables for<br />

the creati<strong>on</strong> of stress feet. The allomorphy therefore appears to be n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing, unlike<br />

the Dutch plural example described earlier.<br />

Also unlike the plural, this pattern seems crucially to refer to a derived<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological property. Recall that the distributi<strong>on</strong> of plural suffixes was able to be stated<br />

in such a way that we did not have to refer to any derived properties, since the stress in<br />

<strong>on</strong>e class of words had to be lexically specified. In this case, however, it is more difficult<br />

to avoid reference to a derived property. As discussed by Booij and Lieber (1993: 25,41),<br />

the -ief suffix must be the more specific allomorph because it <strong>on</strong>ly occurs productively<br />

(2001: 76) has proposed a feature [-native] to mark n<strong>on</strong>-native stems, since these are the<br />

<strong>on</strong>ly stems to which n<strong>on</strong>-native suffixes can attach (Booij 2001: 75), and also features<br />

[+French] and [+Germanic] ((2001: 104). Perhaps other features could be used to<br />

distinguish the Latin and Greek vocabulary. Under such an analysis, distrubuti<strong>on</strong> of -isch<br />

vs. -ief would not be an example of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy. Thanks to<br />

Andrew Garrett for pointing out this alternative generalizati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

8 Booij and Lieber (1993) do not mark stress <strong>on</strong> the derived forms. Based <strong>on</strong> Booij (2001:<br />

114), it may be inferred that forms with the -isch suffix assign stress to the last stressable<br />

syllable before the suffix, but this is a generalizati<strong>on</strong> referring to the ‘native’ suffix -isch,<br />

while the -isch that attaches to n<strong>on</strong>-native stems is listed separately (Booij 2001: 76) as a<br />

n<strong>on</strong>-native suffix. Therefore, Booij may be assuming there are two -isch suffixes (though<br />

it is not clear how <strong>on</strong>e would distinguish them). Stress is marked <strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong>e form with -ief:<br />

cònservatíef ‘c<strong>on</strong>servative’ (Booij 2001: 106), suggesting that -ief gets the main stress in<br />

words where it occurs, but there are not enough examples to dem<strong>on</strong>strate that this<br />

generalizati<strong>on</strong> holds for all forms with -ief.<br />

134


with stems ending in ie, whereas -isch also occurs with other types of stems, as in the<br />

examples below (Booij and Lieber 1993: 25).<br />

(14) proféet ‘prophet’ profet-isch ‘prophetical’<br />

álgebra ‘algebra’ algebra-ïsch ‘algebraic’<br />

organisátor ‘organizer’ organisator-isch ‘organizati<strong>on</strong>al’<br />

Therefore, as Booij and Lieber argue, -ief must be the allomorph that imposes a<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological requirement <strong>on</strong> stems, and since this is the allomorph that occurs with stems<br />

having the predictable (penultimate) stress pattern, this means that the distributi<strong>on</strong> of -ief<br />

refers to a derived ph<strong>on</strong>ological property. As menti<strong>on</strong>ed earlier, the existence of such<br />

examples is predicted both by P >> M and by the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach. Although<br />

the fact that this type of pattern is attested does not help us to choose between the<br />

competing ways of modeling PCSA, it is n<strong>on</strong>etheless important to document the fact that<br />

this type of example does in fact exist.<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong> we have seen two examples of apparently n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing stress-<br />

related PCSA. These cases are significant in that they fail to uphold the predicti<strong>on</strong> of the<br />

P >> M model that PCSA is ph<strong>on</strong>ologically optimizing, unless we extend the noti<strong>on</strong> of<br />

‘optimizing’ to such a degree that it is virtually meaningless. Another important point<br />

was made by the Dutch example, which is that stress-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed PCSA can involve<br />

reference to derived ph<strong>on</strong>ological properties.<br />

3.1.2 Summary<br />

In §3.1, we have seen eight examples of PCSA involving stress or t<strong>on</strong>e. In some<br />

cases, in particular in the n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing examples discussed in §3.1.1.4, the results of<br />

the survey c<strong>on</strong>tradicted a claim of the P >> M approach, namely that PCSA is<br />

135


ph<strong>on</strong>ological optimizati<strong>on</strong>. The failure of this claim to be upheld in the survey data is by<br />

now a recurrent theme, since this was also dem<strong>on</strong>strated in chapter 2. In general, then, it<br />

can be said that although not very many examples of t<strong>on</strong>e- or stress-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed PCSA<br />

were attested in the survey (for the possible reas<strong>on</strong>s discussed earlier), those examples<br />

that are attested tend to favor the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach. In the following secti<strong>on</strong>, I<br />

dem<strong>on</strong>strate how this approach applies to some of the examples described above.<br />

3.2 Analysis<br />

T<strong>on</strong>e- and stress-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy are easily modeled using the<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach as described and implemented in chapter 2. I will reiterate the<br />

basics of this approach here; for a fuller descripti<strong>on</strong>, see chapters 1 and 2.<br />

Subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> is a mechanism in which an affix is prespecified with<br />

properties that are required to be present in any stem to which it will attach. These<br />

properties may be morphological, lexical, or otherwise; crucially, they may also be<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological. Subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approaches have been advanced by Lieber 1980,<br />

Kiparsky 1982b, Selkirk 1982, Orgun 1996, and Yu 2003, am<strong>on</strong>g others. The basic<br />

approach here is the same; the <strong>on</strong>e stipulati<strong>on</strong> that seems to be necessary (though see<br />

chapter 2 for more discussi<strong>on</strong>) is that an affix must be adjacent to the ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

element that it subcategorizes for. This requirement is covered by the Generalized<br />

Determinant Focus Adjacency C<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> (GDFAC), which was proposed by Inkelas<br />

1990 building <strong>on</strong> a proposal of Poser (1985). The GDFAC is given below.<br />

(15) Generalized Determinant Focus Adjacency C<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>: Each ph<strong>on</strong>ologically<br />

c<strong>on</strong>strained element must be adjacent to each c<strong>on</strong>straining element.<br />

136


With this in mind, let us move to a dem<strong>on</strong>strati<strong>on</strong> of how the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

approach works for cases of t<strong>on</strong>e- and stress-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed PCSA. T<strong>on</strong>e-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed<br />

allomorphy is modeled in the same way as feature-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy discussed in<br />

chapter 2, except that the features that are subcategorized for are <strong>on</strong> the t<strong>on</strong>al tier rather<br />

than being features bel<strong>on</strong>ging to particular segments. Below I give subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

frames for each of the two 1sg allomorphs in Mixtepec Mixtec, accounting for their<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong>.<br />

(16) Mixtepec Mixtec 1sg c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> A<br />

[[ L#] stem yù 1sg clitic ] 1sg word<br />

Mixtepec Mixtec 1sg c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> B (‘elsewhere’)<br />

[[ ] stem L 1sg clitic ] 1sg word<br />

An alternative approach would encode homoph<strong>on</strong>y avoidance directly into the synchr<strong>on</strong>ic<br />

account of the allomorphy via an OT c<strong>on</strong>straint that penalizes any word that is<br />

homoph<strong>on</strong>ous with another word in the same paradigm, such as Crosswhite’s (1999)<br />

ANTI-IDENT, shown below.<br />

(17) ANTI-IDENT: For two forms, S1 and S2, where S1 ≠ S2, ∃α, α∈S1, such that<br />

α ≠ ℜ(α).<br />

One could account for the allomorphy by ranking ANTI-IDENT (a ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint)<br />

ahead of the morphological c<strong>on</strong>straint that requires morphological categories to be<br />

expressed uniformly <strong>on</strong> all stems. This would be an example of the P >> M ranking<br />

schema (McCarthy and Prince 1993a,b) discussed earlier. Such an alternative analysis<br />

would be problematic because, as shown above, it is possible to explain the apparent<br />

homoph<strong>on</strong>y avoidance effect based <strong>on</strong> its historical development. Therefore, the P >> M<br />

analysis provides an unnecessary and c<strong>on</strong>tradictory explanati<strong>on</strong>. The subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

approach, <strong>on</strong> the other hand, does not include a synchr<strong>on</strong>ic explanati<strong>on</strong> for the pattern,<br />

137


and therefore it accounts for the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs without duplicating or<br />

c<strong>on</strong>tradicting the historical explanati<strong>on</strong> for the pattern.<br />

Stress-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy under this approach amounts to<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> for a stressed syllable, as I will dem<strong>on</strong>strate here for the Dutch<br />

example. A different opti<strong>on</strong> would be to view this as subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> for a foot, so that<br />

Dutch plural allomorphy would fall under the category of foot-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive<br />

allomorphy, to be described in chapter 4. I have rejected this opti<strong>on</strong> because the Dutch<br />

plural suffixes seem to be sensitive not <strong>on</strong>ly to the presence of a stem-final foot, but<br />

specifically to the stress pattern within the foot. In comparing kanón ‘gun’ with kán<strong>on</strong><br />

‘can<strong>on</strong>’, I am assuming that each word is exhaustively parsed into a single, disyllabic<br />

foot, and that the difference is that kanón excepti<strong>on</strong>ally has an iambic rather than a<br />

trochaic foot structure. Given this, it is not the alignment of the foot that differentiates the<br />

two words, but rather which syllable of the foot is stressed.<br />

I give subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> frames below showing the distributi<strong>on</strong> of -en vs. -s.<br />

(18) Dutch plural c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> A<br />

[[ σ́ #] stem en pl suffix ] pl word<br />

Dutch plural c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> B (‘elsewhere’)<br />

[[ ] stem s pl suffix ] pl word<br />

In this analysis, -s is the ‘elsewhere’ allomorph. This proposal is corroborated by the fact<br />

that loanwords are inflected with -s rather than -en, though the choice of a default<br />

allomorph is not uncomplicated (see van Wijk 2002 for discussi<strong>on</strong>).<br />

This is how the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach handles t<strong>on</strong>e- and stress-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed<br />

allomorphy. As was dem<strong>on</strong>strated, the approach straightforwardly captures the patterns<br />

of allomorphy described in this chapter. Although the P >> M model is also capable of<br />

138


modeling the same patterns, the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach has an advantage in that, as<br />

has been pointed out throughout this chapter as well as chapter 2, the predicti<strong>on</strong>s of the<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach seem to fit better with the survey results being presented here<br />

than do the predicti<strong>on</strong>s of the P >> M approach.<br />

3.3 C<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong><br />

In this chapter, I have presented examples of suppletive allomorphy c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed<br />

by t<strong>on</strong>e or stress. It was noted that there are fewer such examples than we may have<br />

expected. Some reas<strong>on</strong>s for this were discussed, including the fact that some cases<br />

potentially falling into the stress-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed category may overlap with the cases to be<br />

described in chapter 4, thereby artificially reducing the number of cases of stress-<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed PCSA. Still, the lack of cases of t<strong>on</strong>e-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed PCSA is surprising since<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological phenomena involving t<strong>on</strong>al alternati<strong>on</strong>s are quite comm<strong>on</strong> cross-<br />

linguistically; this remains an unresolved issue.<br />

The examples in this chapter were dem<strong>on</strong>strated to be straightforwardly<br />

analyzable using the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach outlined in chapter 2. For the example of<br />

t<strong>on</strong>e-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy in Mixtepec Mixtec, it was argued that a subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

analysis is superior to an OT account based <strong>on</strong> homoph<strong>on</strong>y avoidance because the<br />

explanati<strong>on</strong> provided by the OT account is made unnecessary by the historical<br />

explanati<strong>on</strong> outlined above. In the following chapter, I discuss examples of allomorphy<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by elements of the prosodic hierarchy and dem<strong>on</strong>strate that the<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach is easily and fruitfully extended to those cases as well.<br />

139


Chapter 4: Prosodically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy<br />

Probably the best-known cases of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive<br />

allomorphy (PCSA) are those that are prosodically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed. Kager (1996) devotes an<br />

article to the topic of syllable-counting allomorphy (SCA), which he claims can actually<br />

be reduced to foot-parsing (though, as will be seen in this chapter, not all cases of<br />

syllable-counting allomorphy can be handled in this way). In this chapter, I c<strong>on</strong>sider<br />

cases of prosodically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy as follows. First, in §4.1, I<br />

present results of a cross-linguistic survey of the phenomen<strong>on</strong>. In §4.2, I discuss the<br />

historical development of a set of related examples in Pama-Nyungan languages, showing<br />

how a diachr<strong>on</strong>ic analysis of the phenomen<strong>on</strong> clears the way for a straightforward and<br />

unified approach to prosodically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy that is c<strong>on</strong>sistent<br />

with the analysis of PCSA presented in chapters 2 and 3. In §4.3, I review the synchr<strong>on</strong>ic<br />

analysis of PCSA and dem<strong>on</strong>strate how it accounts for the prosodically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed<br />

examples presented in this chapter, c<strong>on</strong>trasting it with the Output Optimizati<strong>on</strong> approach<br />

espoused by, e.g., Kager (1996). The chapter is c<strong>on</strong>cluded in §4.4.<br />

4.1 Survey results<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong>, I present examples of prosodically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive<br />

allomorphy revealed by a cross-linguistic survey. I define ‘prosodically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed’ to<br />

refer to allomorphy that is sensitive to the presence of an element of the prosodic<br />

hierarchy, namely, a mora, syllable, or foot. The survey revealed 137 total cases of PCSA<br />

140


in 67 different languages, listed in the Appendix. Of these cases, 59 cases from 39<br />

different languages involve prosodic c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing and will be discussed in this chapter. 1<br />

Under the P >> M approach, the same ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints are resp<strong>on</strong>sible for<br />

both regular ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes and PCSA. Therefore, we expect that the same<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints that drive foot parsing should also be manifested in PCSA with<br />

approximately the same frequency cross-linguistically. For example, c<strong>on</strong>straints such as<br />

TROCHAIC (requiring feet to have a stressed-unstressed pattern), FOOTBINARITY<br />

(requiring feet to have exactly two moras or two syllables), and PARSESYLL (requiring<br />

every syllable to be part of a foot) are expected to drive PCSA in a c<strong>on</strong>siderable number<br />

of languages since they are comm<strong>on</strong>ly invoked in analyses of foot parsing not involving<br />

suppletive allomorphy. The effects of these c<strong>on</strong>straints could be manifested in PCSA in a<br />

variety of ways. For example, in some language where suppletive allomorphs of an affix<br />

differ in whether they are inherently stressed or not, TROCHAIC could cause the unstressed<br />

allomorph to be used next to a stressed stem syllable and the stressed allomorph to be<br />

used next to an unstressed stem syllable. FOOTBINARITY combined with PARSESYLL<br />

could cause affixes with an odd mora/syllable count to occur with stems with an odd<br />

mora/syllable count (and likewise for affixes and stems with an even mora/syllable count)<br />

in order to ensure that words have an even mora count, allowing every syllable to be<br />

parsed into a binary foot.<br />

As we will see, some of these effects are exhibited in <strong>on</strong>e or more languages,<br />

c<strong>on</strong>firming a predicti<strong>on</strong> of the P >> M approach and suggesting that it is <strong>on</strong> the right<br />

1 Note that the sum of the number of examples discussed in each chapter is greater than<br />

the total number of examples found in the survey; this is because a few of the examples<br />

are discussed in more than <strong>on</strong>e chapter.<br />

141


track in accounting for prosodically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed PCSA. For example, as will be<br />

discussed, we do find cases where PCSA results in words with an even syllable or mora<br />

count. This was the impetus for Kager’s (1996) claim that ‘syllable-counting allomorphy’<br />

reduces to optimal foot parsing. However, a perhaps surprising result of this survey is the<br />

finding that not all examples of PCSA c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by syllable or mora count involve<br />

some complementary relati<strong>on</strong> between the stress pattern or the number of moras in the<br />

stem and in the affix. As will be seen in §4.1.1.3, there are examples in which suppletive<br />

allomorphs are distributed according to the syllable or mora count of the stem but where<br />

each allomorph c<strong>on</strong>tributes the same number of moras to the word. Thus, foot parsing<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straints al<strong>on</strong>e will not be able to handle all of the cases to be discussed here. In some<br />

cases, it must be stipulated that a certain allomorph occurs <strong>on</strong>ly with stems having a<br />

certain number of moras, syllables, or feet. This issue will be discussed again in §4.3.<br />

This secti<strong>on</strong> is organized as follows. First, I present the attested examples in<br />

§4.1.1. In §4.1.1.1, I discuss examples in which the distributi<strong>on</strong> of suppletive allomorphs<br />

relates to foot parsing. In §4.1.1.2, I discuss examples that relate to word minimality. In<br />

§4.1.1.3, I discuss examples where the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs seems to be arbitrary or<br />

n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing, in that there is no clear relati<strong>on</strong>ship between the shape of the allomorphs<br />

and their distributi<strong>on</strong>. The examples are summarized in §4.1.2.<br />

4.1.1 Examples<br />

The examples to be presented in this secti<strong>on</strong> exhibit essentially the same<br />

properties as those presented in chapters 2 and 3. Some major generalizati<strong>on</strong>s that will<br />

emerge here, each of which has already been discussed in the preceding two chapters, are<br />

142


the following. First, the generalizati<strong>on</strong> that c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing applies from the ‘inside-out’ is<br />

maintained here. PCSA in affixes is triggered by elements that are closer to the root, and<br />

not by elements that are farther away; we also find no instances of affix-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed stem<br />

allomorphy here.<br />

Sec<strong>on</strong>d, we find here (as in chapters 2 and 3) some examples of opaque<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing, where the element that c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s the occurrence of a particular allomorph<br />

is lost or changed in the surface form. This supports the claim that PCSA is sensitive to<br />

input elements, not surface elements.<br />

A third generalizati<strong>on</strong> made in chapters 2 and 3 is that PCSA is c<strong>on</strong>strained by<br />

locality, so that c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> PCSA always occur at the edge of the stem at which the<br />

affix attaches. Most of the examples in this chapter do not bear <strong>on</strong> this particular<br />

generalizati<strong>on</strong>, since they involve c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing by general properties of the stem (such as<br />

syllable count) that cannot be said to occur at <strong>on</strong>e edge or the other. However, there is at<br />

least <strong>on</strong>e type of example that could c<strong>on</strong>tradict the locality generalizati<strong>on</strong> if it were<br />

attested. This would be a case in which allomorphy is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by the weight of a<br />

particular syllable in the stem, but the affix undergoing allomorphy is at the opposite<br />

edge, and the weight generalizati<strong>on</strong> cannot be characterized in any more general way that<br />

would refer, e.g., to the overall mora count of the word. 2 This type of example would<br />

c<strong>on</strong>tradict the generalizati<strong>on</strong>, but no such cases are attested.<br />

A final generalizati<strong>on</strong> that has been made in previous chapters is that PCSA is not<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ologically optimizing. In those chapters, numerous examples were presented in<br />

2 For example, imagine a case in which PCSA in a suffix is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by whether the<br />

stem-initial syllable is light or heavy, and it does not matter how many moras or syllables<br />

intervene between the initial syllable and the right edge.<br />

143


which allomorphy did not seem to follow from any well-known or well-motivated<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint. It was argued that even though many examples do appear <strong>on</strong><br />

their surface to be optimizing, the existence of the n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing examples is sufficient<br />

to c<strong>on</strong>tradict the predicti<strong>on</strong>s made by the P >> M model of PCSA because it is not able to<br />

handle n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing cases without recourse to ad hoc, stipulative c<strong>on</strong>straints that<br />

violate the spirit of the model. In this chapter, it seems that a higher percentage of the<br />

examples are optimizing than in chapters 2 and 3. For this reas<strong>on</strong>, in §4.2 I explore the<br />

possibility of accounting for the optimizati<strong>on</strong> via a historical explanati<strong>on</strong>, thereby freeing<br />

the synchr<strong>on</strong>ic model from having to account for it.<br />

I have given an overview of some generalizati<strong>on</strong>s that will emerge in the data<br />

presented in this chapter; I move now to discuss the examples. I begin in §4.1.1.1 with<br />

examples of PCSA that relate to foot parsing.<br />

4.1.1.1 Foot parsing<br />

This survey revealed a number of cases in which the outcome of PCSA can be<br />

viewed as maximizing the number of syllables that are parsed into feet. One could claim<br />

that PARSESYLL is the c<strong>on</strong>straint resp<strong>on</strong>sible for these effects. However, this <strong>on</strong>ly works<br />

when PARSESYLL is combined with some other c<strong>on</strong>straint such as FOOTBINARITY, since<br />

if a foot can c<strong>on</strong>sist of any number of syllables or moras, then the shape of an allomorph<br />

will have no bearing <strong>on</strong> whether or not all of the syllables in a word can be parsed into<br />

feet. In this secti<strong>on</strong>, I discuss several examples where such an analysis is possible; the<br />

ordering of examples is roughly by c<strong>on</strong>tinent or geographical regi<strong>on</strong>.<br />

144


Am<strong>on</strong>g the languages surveyed, Latin provides the clearest examples of this type<br />

of PCSA. Mester (1994) discusses three cases of allomorphy in Latin, which he argues to<br />

result from the drive to parse all syllables into feet that are exactly bimoraic. The first of<br />

these involves the ‘theme vowel’, which has two allomorphs, -ī- and -ĭ-. This is a vowel<br />

that occurs in the so-called io-verbs and is sometimes referred to as the ‘stem vowel’ but<br />

is explicitly assumed here to be a distinct morpheme from the root. According to Mester<br />

(1994: 24), the form of the theme vowel is predictable ‘to a large extent’ based <strong>on</strong> the<br />

shape of the root: -ĭ- occurs when preceded by a single light syllable (as in capĭmus<br />

‘catch’), while -ī- occurs when preceded by a heavy syllable or two light syllables (as in<br />

audīmus ‘hear’ and aperīmus ‘open’, respectively). Mester does not make a case for why<br />

this allomorphy must be assumed to be suppletive, except to say that ‘[g]iven its lexically<br />

restricted nature, there is no motivati<strong>on</strong> for positing a general ph<strong>on</strong>ological rule’ (1994:<br />

26). Thus, Mester’s implicit criteri<strong>on</strong> for whether or not a particular instance of<br />

allomorphy is suppletive seems to be that rule-derived allomorphy can <strong>on</strong>ly result from<br />

general ph<strong>on</strong>ological rules. C<strong>on</strong>sidering how ph<strong>on</strong>ologically similar the two allomorphs<br />

are in this particular example, the Latin theme vowel alternati<strong>on</strong> could be c<strong>on</strong>sidered to<br />

be rule-derived rather than suppletive. However, I discuss this example here since, even if<br />

the theme vowel alternati<strong>on</strong> is not suppletive, Mester discusses two other cases from<br />

Latin that are unambiguously suppletive and are argued to follow from the same<br />

principles as the theme vowel alternati<strong>on</strong>. Furthermore, as was discussed in chapter 2,<br />

given that the P >> M model accounts for suppletive and n<strong>on</strong>-suppletive allomorphy in<br />

the same way, it is not absolutely crucial that we exclude all n<strong>on</strong>-suppletive examples<br />

from the survey.<br />

145


The proposed explanati<strong>on</strong> for the theme vowel alternati<strong>on</strong> is that it serves to avoid<br />

the ‘trapping’ c<strong>on</strong>figurati<strong>on</strong> where a light syllable is located between a well-formed<br />

bimoraic foot and either the beginning or end of the word, or another well-formed<br />

bimoraic foot. Such c<strong>on</strong>figurati<strong>on</strong>s ‘trap’ the light syllable and prevent it from being<br />

parsed into a well-formed foot. In the envir<strong>on</strong>ments in which the -ī- theme vowel occurs<br />

(after a heavy syllable or two light syllables), the root can be parsed into a single<br />

bimoraic foot. If the light syllable (m<strong>on</strong>omoraic) theme vowel -ĭ- occurred after such a<br />

root, it would not be parsable into a bimoraic foot, and would therefore be trapped. In<br />

these envir<strong>on</strong>ments, the -ī- theme vowel occurs instead, and since it c<strong>on</strong>tributes a heavy<br />

syllable, this theme vowel can be parsed into its own bimoraic foot, with the result that all<br />

syllables of the word are parsed into well-formed feet.<br />

Another Latin example described by Mester that is more likely to be suppletive<br />

involves suffixes that form abstract nouns (1994: 43), with the shapes -ia and -iēs.<br />

According to Mester, many roots can take either allomorph (for example, māter-ia and<br />

māter-iēs ‘matter’ apparently occur in free variati<strong>on</strong>). However, some roots can <strong>on</strong>ly take<br />

<strong>on</strong>e or the other, and there is a prosodic principle behind their selecti<strong>on</strong>. The –iēs<br />

allomorph is avoided after heavy syllables (Mester 1994: 43), which Mester attributes to<br />

their inherent trapping c<strong>on</strong>figurati<strong>on</strong>: if -iēs were added to a root ending in a heavy<br />

syllable, the coda of the root would syllabify with the /i/ of the suffix, forming a light<br />

syllable, which would then be trapped between two heavy syllables since the ēs of the<br />

suffix would form a sec<strong>on</strong>d heavy syllable. In this situati<strong>on</strong>, -ia is used instead (as in<br />

grāt-ia ‘grace’), avoiding the trapping c<strong>on</strong>figurati<strong>on</strong> since the entire suffix is parsed into a<br />

bimoraic foot.<br />

146


A third and final example from Latin discussed by Mester involves the perfect<br />

stem of the sec<strong>on</strong>d (ē) c<strong>on</strong>jugati<strong>on</strong> (1994: 44). According to Mester, the generalizati<strong>on</strong> is<br />

that perfect stems take the u-perfect form except in exactly those cases where the use of<br />

the u-perfect would result in a trapping c<strong>on</strong>figurati<strong>on</strong>. The u-perfect c<strong>on</strong>sists of a verb<br />

root followed by -ŭ-, as in m<strong>on</strong>-ŭ-ī ‘warn (1sg perfect)’. This u-perfect is the predominant<br />

way to form a perfect stem, but there are two other ways of forming a perfect stem. The<br />

first is the s-perfect (Mester 1994: 45), which adds -s to the root, as in auk-s-ī ‘enlarge<br />

(1sg perfect)’. The sec<strong>on</strong>d is through reduplicati<strong>on</strong>, which Mester describes as an archaic<br />

formati<strong>on</strong>; an example is spop<strong>on</strong>dī ‘vow’ (


ases select -cita/-cito, while stems with three or more syllables select -ita/-ito. Examples<br />

are shown below (Harris 1979: 291).<br />

(1) madre-cita *madr-ita dinosaur-ito *dinosaurie-cito<br />

saurie-cito *saur-ito comadr-ita *comadre-cita<br />

There are several interesting points to be made regarding this example. First, note that the<br />

two affix allomorphs themselves both would appear to c<strong>on</strong>tribute two syllables to the<br />

stem, but the initial vowel of the -ita/-ito suffix triggers deleti<strong>on</strong> of the stem-final vowel,<br />

resulting in a net increase of <strong>on</strong>e syllable to the word, as compared to two syllables when<br />

-cita/-cito is used. Thus, the apparent complementarity between the stem and suffix is not<br />

a property of the suffix itself, but is rather the result of a ph<strong>on</strong>ological rule that is<br />

triggered by <strong>on</strong>e suffix allomorph but not the other. This type of ‘indirect’ optimizati<strong>on</strong> is<br />

predicted by P >> M since hiatus resoluti<strong>on</strong> and allomorph selecti<strong>on</strong> are manifested<br />

simultaneously and can therefore freely interact.<br />

Note also, however, that not all words are optimized by this distributi<strong>on</strong> of<br />

allomorphs. In these dialects of Spanish, stems with four syllables take the -ita/-ito form<br />

according to Harris; this would result in words having an odd syllable count (five<br />

syllables). Thus, the pattern cannot be claimed to be optimal for every stem in the<br />

language. In a P >> M analysis, <strong>on</strong>e would have to find some way to force four-syllable<br />

stems to take -ita/-ito even though this would be ph<strong>on</strong>ologically less optimal than using<br />

the -cita/-cito form. In a subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> analysis, this would be unproblematic since<br />

the -ita/-ito suffixes can subcategorize for a disyllabic stem with -cita/-cito as the<br />

‘elsewhere’ allomorphs.<br />

148


A final point to be made regarding the Spanish example is that, as pointed out by<br />

Harris, there are some surface counterexamples to the pattern, in which trisyllabic stems<br />

are treated as disyllabic for the purposes of diminutive allomorphy. These examples<br />

apparently all begin with es, so Harris explains them by proposing that diminutive<br />

allomorph selecti<strong>on</strong> occurs prior to the epenthesis of initial e before s in these words<br />

(Harris 1979: 291). This type of interacti<strong>on</strong> with a ph<strong>on</strong>ological process is not predicted<br />

to occur under P >> M, since allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong> is supposed to be determined<br />

simultaneously with the applicati<strong>on</strong> of ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes (and using the same<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints). The fact that a ph<strong>on</strong>ological epenthesis rule renders the PCSA<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing opaque in this set of examples c<strong>on</strong>stitutes an argument against the P >> M<br />

approach. 3<br />

Another example where PCSA produces words with an even syllable count is<br />

found in Saami (Lappic, Norway; Dolbey 1997). In this language, several pers<strong>on</strong> marking<br />

suffixes have allomorphy determined by the syllable count of the stem (Dolbey 1997).<br />

Some examples are shown below (Dolbey 1997: 103, 105).<br />

(2) jearra- ‘to ask’ veahkehea- ‘to help’ ‘even’ ‘odd’<br />

1du je:r.re.-Ø veah.ke.he:-t.ne Ø ~ -tne<br />

2du jear.ra.-beaht.ti veah.ke.hea-hp.pi -beahtti ~ -hppi<br />

2pl jear.ra.-beh.tet veah.ke.he:-h.pet -behtet ~ -hpet<br />

3pl pret je:r.re.-Ø veah.ke.he:-d.je Ø ~ -dje<br />

passive je:r.ro.-juv.vo veah.ke.hu-v.vo -juvvo ~ -vvo<br />

In every case, stems with an even syllable count take suffix allomorphs<br />

c<strong>on</strong>tributing an even number of syllables (including zero), while stems with an odd<br />

syllable count take allomorphs c<strong>on</strong>tributing an odd number of syllables. The result, as<br />

pointed out by Dolbey, is to avoid unfooted syllables. An interesting point made by<br />

3 Several other examples of opaque c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing were discussed in chapter 2 (§2.1.2.6).<br />

149


Dolbey regarding this example is that it provides str<strong>on</strong>g evidence for cyclic, rather than<br />

global, evaluati<strong>on</strong> of stems in terms of even syllable count. This is seen where two of the<br />

suffixes listed above are combined with a root having an even syllable count, such as in<br />

the example je:r.ro-juv.vo-beaht.ti ‘ask-Passive-2du’. In such cases, the whole word<br />

would also have an even syllable count even if the m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic allomorph of each suffix<br />

were used, as in *je:r.ru-v.vo-hp.pi. It is not enough for the whole word to have an even<br />

syllable count, because the even syllable count requirement is evaluated at each level of<br />

morphological c<strong>on</strong>stituency. Since the stem of affixati<strong>on</strong> for the 2du suffix in the form<br />

*je:r.ru-v.vo-hp.pi is the ungrammatical (trisyllabic) stem *je:r.ru-v.vo-, the whole word<br />

is ungrammatical even when the additi<strong>on</strong> of the m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic passive suffix allomorph<br />

would correct the syllable count problem for the purposes of global evaluati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

Thus, interestingly, although Saami does c<strong>on</strong>firm the predicti<strong>on</strong> of P >> M that<br />

PCSA should result in words with an even syllable count, it also provides an argument<br />

against the simplest and most comm<strong>on</strong> implementati<strong>on</strong> of P >> M. Generally, P >> M<br />

analyses do not refer to morphological c<strong>on</strong>stituency, but rather show the stem and all<br />

affixes present in the input, implying that they have equal status and therefore equal<br />

potential to trigger or undergo a change in the output. The Saami example dem<strong>on</strong>strates<br />

that this type of model is too simplistic; in an OT analysis, the grammar needs to be able<br />

to evaluate well-formedness each time an affix is added to the stem.<br />

Another case that may involve foot parsing c<strong>on</strong>straints is found in Finnish, though<br />

the analysis is not as straightforward as in the Saami example discussed above. The<br />

Finnish illative has three allomorphs: -Vn, -hVn, and -seen (Karlss<strong>on</strong> 1999: 112-113). The<br />

-seen allomorph occurs after polysyllabic stems ending in a l<strong>on</strong>g vowel. The -hVn<br />

150


allomorph occurs after m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic stems and after plural stems where the root ends in a<br />

vowel (yielding a Vi sequence at the end of the root after the additi<strong>on</strong> of the -i plural<br />

suffix). The -Vn allomorph occurs with other stems. In each of the two allomorphs<br />

c<strong>on</strong>taining ‘V’, this vowel surfaces with the same quality as the immediately preceding<br />

vowel. The distributi<strong>on</strong> of the three allomorphs is illustrated in the examples below<br />

(Karlss<strong>on</strong> 1999: 112-113).<br />

(3) talo-<strong>on</strong> ‘into the house’ koulu-un ‘to school’<br />

kaupunki-in ‘to the town’ lehte-en ‘into the newspaper’<br />

kunta-an ‘into the commune’ korkea-an ‘into the high’<br />

maa-han ‘into the country’ tie-hen ‘to the road’<br />

työ-hön ‘to work’ suu-hun ‘into the mouth’<br />

pullo-i-hin ‘into the bottles’ kalo-i-hin ‘into the fish (pl.)’<br />

vapaa-seen ‘into the free’ harmaa-seen ‘into the grey’<br />

perhee-seen ‘into the family’ tietee-seen ‘into science’<br />

taivaa-seen ‘to heaven/into the sky’ rikkaa-seen ‘into the rich’<br />

The use of the -hVn allomorph with m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic stems produces words with two<br />

syllables, and its use after plural stems prevents VVV sequences from arising. Perhaps<br />

the distributi<strong>on</strong> of -hVn vs. -Vn can be analyzed in terms of a requirement that a foot have<br />

two syllables and a c<strong>on</strong>straint against VVV; in fact, <strong>on</strong>e could write rules deriving <strong>on</strong>e<br />

allomorph from the other, so that the relati<strong>on</strong>ship between these two allomorphs is not<br />

necessarily suppletive. The distributi<strong>on</strong> of -seen, however, does not follow from these<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straints. Perhaps there is also a separate c<strong>on</strong>straint requiring a foot to have at least two<br />

moras, so that with a stem such as vapaa, if the stem has to be parsed into a single<br />

disyllabic foot, then the suffix form is -seen, which can form its own bimoraic foot. Thus,<br />

the Finnish example may involve c<strong>on</strong>straints <strong>on</strong> foot structure, but the overall pattern of<br />

allomorphy in the illative suffixes is complicated and would require several separate<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straints in a P >> M analysis.<br />

151


Three examples of syllable count-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy are found in Est<strong>on</strong>ian<br />

(Finno-Lappic, Est<strong>on</strong>ia; Mürk 1997). These examples are discussed by Kager (1996) in<br />

support of his argument that syllable-counting allomorphy is driven by foot-parsing<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straints. In Est<strong>on</strong>ian, the genitive plural takes the form -te after stems with two or four<br />

syllables, and -tte with three syllables; the partitive plural takes the form -sit after stems<br />

with two or four syllables, and -it (or by a vowel mutati<strong>on</strong>) after stems with three<br />

syllables (Kager 1996: 157). The partitive singular is -Ø or -t after ‘even-numbered’<br />

stems (with the -t allomorph occurring <strong>on</strong>ly after m<strong>on</strong>osyllables) and -tt after ‘odd-<br />

numbered’ stems (Kager 1996: 168). Examples given below with page numbers in<br />

parentheses are from Mürk 1997; the remaining examples are from Kager 1996: 157,<br />

168.<br />

(4) Genitive plural Partitive plural Partitive singular Gloss<br />

maa:-te (74) ma-it (74) maa:-t ‘land’<br />

aas:ta-tte (149) aas:ta-it (149) aas:ta-tt ‘year’<br />

häda-te (77) häda-sit (77) häda-Ø (77) ‘trouble’<br />

paraja-tte paraja-it paraja-tt ‘suitable’<br />

raamattu-tte raamaattu-it raamattu-tt ‘book’<br />

atmirali-te atmirali-sit atmirali-Ø ‘admiral’<br />

telef<strong>on</strong>i-te telef<strong>on</strong>i-sit telef<strong>on</strong>i-Ø ‘teleph<strong>on</strong>e’<br />

Kager’s analysis is that ‘even-numbered’ stems are those that can be exhaustively<br />

parsed into disyllabic feet, while ‘odd-numbered’ stems cannot be exhaustively parsed<br />

into disyllabic feet (1996: 158). The suffix forms selected by even-numbered stems do<br />

not end up being parsed into feet. The suffix forms selected by odd-numbered stems, <strong>on</strong><br />

the other hand, are parsed into a foot al<strong>on</strong>g with the final syllable of the stem. The fact<br />

that in these cases the suffix allomorph c<strong>on</strong>tributes a coda c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant to the stem-final<br />

syllable, making that syllable heavy, follows from the preference for disyllabic trochaic<br />

152


feet. Thus, Kager claims that this is not actually a case of syllable counting, but of foot<br />

parsing.<br />

Kager makes the str<strong>on</strong>ger claim that syllable count-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy in<br />

general reduces to foot parsing optimizati<strong>on</strong>. We will see that this claim does not hold up<br />

for all cases since, as will be dem<strong>on</strong>strated in §4.1.1.3, there are several cases of<br />

allomorphy based <strong>on</strong> syllable count where the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs is arbitrary<br />

rather than optimizing. N<strong>on</strong>etheless, the Est<strong>on</strong>ian examples do appear to involve a<br />

‘c<strong>on</strong>spiracy’ that optimizes foot parsing. However, note that in each of the sets of<br />

allomorphs discussed by Kager (partitive singular, partitive plural, and genitive plural),<br />

the two allomorphs are very similar to each other ph<strong>on</strong>etically. This suggests that we<br />

might view these as examples of rule-derived rather than suppletive allomorphy (though<br />

the rules needed to produce the allomorphy would probably have to be specific to each<br />

morpheme).<br />

In Turkana (Nilotic, Kenya; Dimmendaal 1983), we find an example in which the<br />

apparent complementarity between the size of the stem and the size of an affix cannot be<br />

attributed to the regular applicati<strong>on</strong> of ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes to a single underlying affix<br />

form. According to Dimmendaal (2000), Turkana exhibits syllable count-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed<br />

suppletive allomorphy in the affix used to form abstract nouns. As shown in the examples<br />

below (Dimmendaal 2000: 166), roots of shape CVC take the -ɪ̀sɪ́ allomorph ((5)a), while<br />

roots of shape CiVjCiVjC take the -ù allomorph ((5)b), and other roots are partially<br />

reduplicated ((5)c).<br />

153


(5) a. á-rɛ́ŋ-ɪ̀sɪ́ ‘redness’ (-rɛ́ŋ ‘be red’)<br />

á-jɔ́k-ɪ̀sɪ́ ‘kindness’ (-jɔ́k ‘be kind, good’)<br />

b. á-gógóŋ-ù ‘strength’ (-gógóŋ ‘be str<strong>on</strong>g’)<br />

á-bábár-ù ‘saltiness’ (-bábár ‘be salty’)<br />

c. á-cʊ́kʊ́l-ʊ́l ‘depth’ (-cʊ́kʊ́l ‘be deep’)<br />

á-ŋáráb-áb ‘roughness’ (-ŋáráb ‘be rough’)<br />

Dimmendaal’s (2000) characterizati<strong>on</strong> of the distributi<strong>on</strong> implies that the allomorphy<br />

may result from a four-syllable requirement for abstract nouns. However, the distributi<strong>on</strong><br />

is actually more complicated than represented here, as indicated by Dimmendaal (1983).<br />

In additi<strong>on</strong> to the types menti<strong>on</strong>ed above, there are other root types for which the<br />

selecti<strong>on</strong> of the abstract noun suffix is not predictable from the factors outlined above.<br />

For example, in additi<strong>on</strong> to CVC roots, roots with ‘an epipatetic high fr<strong>on</strong>t vowel’ take<br />

the -ɪ̀sɪ́ allomorph (Dimmendaal 1983: 270), while roots with ‘an epipatetic vowel /o/ or<br />

/a/’ (1983: 271) take the -ù allomorph, as do stems c<strong>on</strong>taining a habitual extensi<strong>on</strong>. Thus,<br />

some morphological and/or stem class c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing must be involved here in additi<strong>on</strong> to<br />

the ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing; though we do not have examples of all of these different<br />

types of stems, it seems that not every nominalized form ends up with four syllables.<br />

Still, it seems that there is a str<strong>on</strong>g tendency for nominalized forms to have four syllables,<br />

suggesting that a c<strong>on</strong>straint enforcing this would not be implausible. One could view this<br />

as being foot-based, since a four-syllable word is easily parsed into two disyllabic feet; it<br />

could also fall into the category of minimality-related c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing since it seems that<br />

there is a preference for a specific number of syllables in nominalized words.<br />

In some examples found in the survey, both the shape and the placement of the<br />

allomorphs are relevant to syllable count and foot parsing. For example, in Nancowry<br />

154


(M<strong>on</strong>-Khmer, Nicobar Islands; Radhakrishnan 1981), 4 the causative is marked by either a<br />

prefix or an infix, depending <strong>on</strong> whether the stem is m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic or disyllabic,<br />

respectively (Radhakrishnan 1980: 54). When the stem is m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic, the causative is<br />

marked by a ha- prefix, as in the examples below.<br />

(6) ha-káh ‘to cause to know’ ha-míh ‘to cause to rain’<br />

ha-míɁ ‘to cause to be soaked’ ha-suáh ‘to cause to burn’<br />

When the stem is disyllabic, the causative is marked by an -um- infix, which ‘overwrites’<br />

the rhyme of the stem-initial syllable, as in the examples below.<br />

(7) p-um-Ɂɯ̃ y ‘to cause to have a bad smell’ paɁɯ̃ y ‘bad smell’<br />

p-um-rẽ ‘to cause something to be flat’ pirẽ ‘flat’<br />

p-um-lóɁ ‘to cause some<strong>on</strong>e to lose s.t.’ palóɁ ‘lose’<br />

The result of this allomorphy appears to be that causative forms always have two<br />

syllables. As with the Turkana example above, the result of the allomorphy could be<br />

analyzed in terms of both foot parsing (since causative forms end up with two syllables,<br />

which presumably form a single foot) and minimality c<strong>on</strong>straints.<br />

Radhakrishnan (1980: 55) discusses some interesting ‘double causative’<br />

examples, which are formed by prefixing ha- and infixing -um-. The double causative can<br />

<strong>on</strong>ly apply to m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic roots. Examples are shown below (Radhakrishnan 1980: 55). 5<br />

4 Recent discussi<strong>on</strong>s of Nancowry ph<strong>on</strong>ology can be found in Steriade 1988, Alderete et<br />

al 1999, Hendricks 1999, and Inkelas and Zoll (2005: 223-224); these deal primarily with<br />

reduplicati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

5 The meaning of the double causative is not clear since the examples are given out of<br />

c<strong>on</strong>text, but based <strong>on</strong> the glosses, it does not necessarily involve the introducti<strong>on</strong> of two<br />

new causative agents as might be expected.<br />

155


(8) ha-káh h-um-káh ‘to cause to know’<br />

ha-míh h-um-míh ‘to cause to rain’<br />

ha-Ɂuáh h-um-Ɂuáh ‘to cause to cough’<br />

ha-sɯ́ l h-um-sɯ́ l ‘to frighten’<br />

On the surface, these examples might appear to provide an argument in favor of using a<br />

foot parsing or minimality/maximality c<strong>on</strong>straint to analyze the Nancowry causatives,<br />

since the combinati<strong>on</strong> of two causatives still always results in a disyllabic word.<br />

However, the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach also provides a straightforward explanati<strong>on</strong> for<br />

the fact that <strong>on</strong>e instance of each causative allomorph is used in the double causative<br />

c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>. If the ha- allomorph subcategorizes for a m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic stem, then this<br />

allomorph will apply first to the root; then, when a sec<strong>on</strong>d causative is applied to the<br />

(now disyllabic) stem, the -um- allomorph will be used since ha- can <strong>on</strong>ly attach to a<br />

m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic stem. Thus, the double causative does not provide an argument in favor of<br />

<strong>on</strong>e analysis or the other. However, it does c<strong>on</strong>stitute an example in which allomorph<br />

selecti<strong>on</strong> is sensitive to a ph<strong>on</strong>ological property c<strong>on</strong>tributed by another affix (in this case,<br />

a different allomorph marking the same morphological category), since the use of -um- in<br />

the double causative is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by the extra syllable c<strong>on</strong>tributed by ha-. Other<br />

examples involving this type of interacti<strong>on</strong> between affixes have already been discussed<br />

(for example, the Saami examples discussed earlier in this secti<strong>on</strong>, and the Turkish<br />

‘stacked’ causatives discussed in chapter 2), but this is worth pointing out n<strong>on</strong>etheless.<br />

One example that has been claimed to relate to foot parsing is found in<br />

Martuthunira (Pama-Nyungan, Australia; Dench 1995), where the ‘full laden’ suffix takes<br />

the form -warlaya following trimoraic and larger stems, and -warla following bimoraic<br />

stems (Dench 1995: 65). Dench claims that this pattern is ‘based <strong>on</strong> a preference for an<br />

156


even pattern of stressed-unstressed syllables in the word’ (1995: 65). 6 Some examples are<br />

shown below (from Dench 1995: 94, except where noted).<br />

(9) jinyji-warla ‘fat, plump, obese’ marrari-warlaya (no English given)<br />

fat-FULL word-FULL (Dench 1995: 38)<br />

ngungku-warla ‘str<strong>on</strong>g’ kunkuwarra-warlaya ‘full to<br />

weight-FULL h<strong>on</strong>ey-FULL bursting with<br />

h<strong>on</strong>ey’<br />

Dench appears to claim that the -warla form occurs with bimoraic roots so that the<br />

resulting form will have an even number of moras, which can be parsed into exactly two<br />

feet. However, since the -warlaya allomorph occurs with stems with an even mora count<br />

of more than three moras (as in kunkuwarra-warlaya), Dench’s explanati<strong>on</strong> does not<br />

extend to all cases since the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs does not always result in an even-<br />

numbered syllable count. Therefore, the allomorphy seems not to refer to feet, but<br />

specifically to mora count, and in general it cannot be c<strong>on</strong>sidered to optimize footing.<br />

Furthermore, note that this pattern cannot be analyzed in terms of either minimality or<br />

maximality, since the pattern here is the exact opposite of the type of complementarity<br />

that we have seen in some previous examples: the smaller suffix attaches to the smallest<br />

stems, while the larger suffix attaches to larger stems. This example lends itself to a<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach, since we can easily characterize the -warla suffix as<br />

subcategorizing for a stem with two moras (or, to avoid allowing the grammar to ‘count’,<br />

6 Since Dench’s claim refers specifically to stress patterns, it might have made sense to<br />

discuss this example al<strong>on</strong>g with the other stress-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed examples in chapter 3.<br />

However, the noti<strong>on</strong> of alternating stress does relate directly to foot parsing, and<br />

furthermore, I argue against Dench’s explanati<strong>on</strong> here. Therefore, I have opted to include<br />

the example in this secti<strong>on</strong> al<strong>on</strong>g with other similar examples where allomorph<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong> is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by syllable/mora count.<br />

157


we could assume that the bimoraic stem is parsed into a foot before the additi<strong>on</strong> of the<br />

suffix, so that the suffix attaches to a stem c<strong>on</strong>sisting of a single foot).<br />

A final example of apparent foot-based allomorphy is found in Shipibo (Panoan,<br />

Peru; Elías-Ulloa 2004) . In Shipibo, the ergative suffix has two allomorphs, -n and -nin<br />

(Elías-Ulloa 2004: 1). The -n allomorph occurs when the noun stem has an even syllable<br />

count, while the -nin allomorph occurs with noun stems with an odd syllable count. Some<br />

examples are shown below (Elías-Ulloa 2004: 3).<br />

(10) bakɨ-n ‘child-ERG’ atapa-nin ‘hen-ERG’<br />

The distributi<strong>on</strong> of ergative allomorphs results in words with an even syllable count, as in<br />

the Saami case discussed earlier in this secti<strong>on</strong>. Thus, this is another example that could<br />

be analyzed in terms of foot parsing, since the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs results in a<br />

c<strong>on</strong>figurati<strong>on</strong> of syllables that is optimal for foot formati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong>, we have seen several examples of allomorphy c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by<br />

syllable or mora count (17 examples from nine different languages) whose net result is<br />

that every syllable can be parsed into a binary foot. This is an important finding since it is<br />

the first type of allomorphy that we have seen so far in which a predicti<strong>on</strong> of the P >> M<br />

model is borne out in a significant way. Since this is <strong>on</strong>e of the more well-known types of<br />

PCSA, it should not be surprising that such cases exist. In fact, we might have expected<br />

to find more examples, since the effects of foot parsing c<strong>on</strong>straints are evident in the<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological systems of so many of the world’s languages. However, <strong>on</strong>e point should be<br />

kept in mind, which is that although the P >> M model predicts and explains examples of<br />

this type, the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach is also able to account for these examples. The<br />

difference is that in a subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> analysis, we would not have a built-in<br />

158


explanati<strong>on</strong> for the apparent drive towards exhaustive parsing into binary feet; the foot-<br />

parsing effect would be (from a synchr<strong>on</strong>ic perspective) coincidental. This missed<br />

generalizati<strong>on</strong> might seem to be a serious disadvantage of the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

approach. However, as will become clear when we discuss the n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing examples<br />

in §4.1.1.3, there is a good reas<strong>on</strong> to avoid using foot-parsing c<strong>on</strong>straints to analyze<br />

syllable-counting allomorphy: many examples of syllable-counting allomorphy seem to<br />

be arbitrary and make no difference to foot parsing, and yet in terms of their behavior and<br />

the factors that c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong>, they look exactly like the examples seen<br />

in this secti<strong>on</strong>. The P >> M model fares poorly when we attempt a unified account of all<br />

syllable-counting allomorphy. 7 This issue will be taken up in §4.3.<br />

4.1.1.2 Minimality<br />

Another set of c<strong>on</strong>straints expected to play a role in prosodically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed<br />

PCSA is minimality c<strong>on</strong>straints. These c<strong>on</strong>straints stipulate that a word must have some<br />

minimum number of moras, syllables, or feet in order to be a well-formed word.<br />

An example of allomorphy that could be analyzed as resulting from a minimality<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straint is found in Spanish, where the nominalizing suffixes -ez and -eza are<br />

distributed according to the syllable count of the stem. As seen in the examples below,<br />

the form -ez is used when the citati<strong>on</strong> form of the corresp<strong>on</strong>ding adjective has three or<br />

7 It has been suggested (Booij 1998) that the P >> M approach could be used for the<br />

optimizing type of PCSA, while another mechanism could be used to handle the n<strong>on</strong>optimizing<br />

types. I argue against this approach in §4.3 and again in §6.4 <strong>on</strong> the grounds<br />

that it is unsatisfying to the linguist looking for a unified soluti<strong>on</strong> to the problem of<br />

syllable-counting allomorphy, and also that it is scientifically unsound.<br />

159


more syllables, while the suffix -eza is used when the adjective has <strong>on</strong>e or two syllables<br />

(Aranovich et al 2005).<br />

(11) rigido rigid-ez ‘rigid’<br />

estupido estupid-ez ‘stupid’<br />

vil vil-eza ‘vile’<br />

franco franqu-eza ‘truthful’<br />

gentil gentil-eza ‘gentle’<br />

real real-eza ‘royal, regal’<br />

One generalizati<strong>on</strong> is that nominalized forms have no fewer than three syllables (e.g.,<br />

*vil-ez is unacceptable). Thus, in a P >> M account, the distrubuti<strong>on</strong> of -eza could be<br />

attributed in part to a minimality c<strong>on</strong>straint (3 syllable minimum for nominalized words)<br />

if we assume that -ez is the default or ‘elsewhere’ allomorph. However, this would not<br />

explain why disyllabic c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems such as gentil take -eza instead of -ez. The<br />

problem for a P >> M account is that the number of input stem syllables is obscured by<br />

the deleti<strong>on</strong> of the stem-final vowel that is triggered by the additi<strong>on</strong> of the vowel-initial<br />

suffix. 8 In a subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> analysis, we can state that the -ez suffix subcategorizes for<br />

a stem with at least three syllables, while -eza is the ‘elsewhere’ allomorph. 9 Thus,<br />

although we can still say that minimality may be playing a role here, the surface patterns<br />

cannot all be explained in this way, and the example does not lend itself to a standard,<br />

surface-based P >> M analysis involving minimality.<br />

In Qafar (Cushitic, Ethiopia; Parker and Hayward 1985, Hayward 1998), the<br />

indefinite genitive suffix exhibits PCSA that may be driven in part by word minimality<br />

8<br />

Aranovich et al (2005) argue that the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs is driven by a c<strong>on</strong>straint<br />

<strong>on</strong> inputs (stem + suffix) requiring them to c<strong>on</strong>sist of two binary feet. A problem with<br />

this type of approach is that it requires the ph<strong>on</strong>ology to build feet out of the stem and<br />

suffix prior to the evaluati<strong>on</strong> of the input by the ph<strong>on</strong>ology, which should logically take<br />

place before any ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes (such as foot formati<strong>on</strong>) apply to the input.<br />

9<br />

Alternatively, -eza could subcategorize for stems of <strong>on</strong>e or two syllables, with -ez as the<br />

elsewhere allomorph.<br />

160


c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s. As seen in the examples below (Hayward 1998: 630), am<strong>on</strong>g masculine<br />

stems, 10 those that are m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic and c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final take the -ti suffix ((12)a). Those<br />

that are polysyllabic and c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final undergo no segmental changes, though stems<br />

that bear lexical accent are de-accented in the indefinite genitive ((12)b). Those that are<br />

polysyllabic and vowel-final undergo de-accentuati<strong>on</strong> and have their final vowel replaced<br />

by [i] ((12)c).<br />

(12) a. /ħan/ ‘milk’ ħan-tí dala ‘(a) milk gourd’<br />

b. /áʕan/ ‘frog’ aʕán iba ‘(a) frog’s leg(s)’<br />

/danan/ ‘d<strong>on</strong>key’ danán iba ‘(a) d<strong>on</strong>key’s leg(s)’<br />

c. /kúta/ ‘dog’ kut-í ɖagor ‘(a) dog’s fur’<br />

One result of the allomorphy seen here is that no possessor noun has fewer than two<br />

syllables. This could account for why m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic possessor stems take the -ti suffix<br />

instead of -Ø. However, this still does not explain why polysyllabic vowel-final stems<br />

behave differently from their c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final counterparts in taking -i rather than -Ø,<br />

since they would still be disyllabic without the -i suffix. This aspect of the allomorphy<br />

does not follow from minimality. A possible way of accounting for the distributi<strong>on</strong> of -i<br />

vs. -Ø is to propose a two-syllable maximality c<strong>on</strong>straint as well, so that possessor nouns<br />

must have both a minimum and a maximum of two syllables. Suppose that the c<strong>on</strong>straint<br />

MORPHEXPR (Rose 2000a) requires every morphological category to be marked by some<br />

affix, and suppose that the stress shift that applies to the forms in (12)b and (12)c is<br />

sec<strong>on</strong>dary and does not count as an expressi<strong>on</strong> of the category. Then, the distributi<strong>on</strong> of -i<br />

vs. -Ø can be explained because while -i can fuse with a stem-final vowel, yielding<br />

10 Feminine nouns take a -C suffix, with the quality of the c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant determined by the<br />

initial c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant of the possessed stem that follows, unless this stem is vowel-initial, in<br />

which case the suffix c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant surfaces as [h] by default (Hayward 1998: 630).<br />

161


disyllabic words in (12)c, using -i with the c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems in (12)b would add a<br />

third syllable, which would violate the disyllabic maximality c<strong>on</strong>straint.<br />

An important point to note regarding this example is that it requires us to posit<br />

both a minimality and a maximality c<strong>on</strong>straint, plus MORPHEXPR, to account for the<br />

single fact that all possessor nouns have exactly two syllables. Thus, in a P >> M<br />

analysis, the drive towards disyllabic words here is the combined effect of multiple<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straints; this is not a very straightforward way of getting at the syllable count<br />

generalizati<strong>on</strong>. 11<br />

One example that has been argued to result from word maximality is found in<br />

Miya (Chadic, Nigeria). According to Schuh (1998), the maximal native verb is<br />

trimoraic, accounting for the fact that trimoraic roots do not undergo reduplicati<strong>on</strong> in the<br />

pluracti<strong>on</strong>al form as other roots do. As shown below, roots with the shape /Ca/ undergo<br />

reduplicati<strong>on</strong>, surfacing as CəCa ((13)a). Roots with the shapes /C1əC2(ə)/ and /C1əC2a/<br />

also undergo reduplicati<strong>on</strong>, surfacing as C1aC1əC2a ((13)b). Roots of the shape /C1aC2/<br />

undergo vowel lengthening, surfacing as C1aaC2a ((13)c). However, roots with the form<br />

/C1VC2(ə)C3(ə)/ undergo a vowel change but no reduplicati<strong>on</strong> or vowel lengthening,<br />

surfacing as C1aC2(ə)C3a ((13)d). Examples are from Schuh 1998: 175-176.<br />

11 Note also that we cannot use foot parsing c<strong>on</strong>straints to account for the pattern, since<br />

there do exist trisyllabic stems in the language which, according to Hayward’s (1998)<br />

generalizati<strong>on</strong>, pattern with disyllabic stems, rather than with m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic stems as<br />

would be the case if foot parsing c<strong>on</strong>straints were resp<strong>on</strong>sible.<br />

162


(13) a. za ‘enter’ à zə-za-ya sáy ‘he entered’<br />

pa ‘collect’ à pə-pa sáy ‘he collected’<br />

b. tsər ‘stop’ à tsa-tsə́r-a-yà sáy ‘he stopped’<br />

pər ‘cut’ à pa-pə́r-à sáy ‘he cut’<br />

zəna ‘spread to dry’ à za-zən-a sáy ‘he spread to dry’<br />

c. tlakə ‘scrape’ à tláak-à sáy ‘he scraped’<br />

dzar ‘disperse’ sə̀bə dzaar-a-ya sáy ‘the people dispersed’<br />

d. tsəryə ‘step <strong>on</strong>’ à tsary-á say ‘he stepped <strong>on</strong>’<br />

kərmə ‘scoop up’ à karm-a sáy ‘he scooped up’<br />

Schuh’s explanati<strong>on</strong> for the failure of the roots in ((13)d) to reduplicate is compelling but<br />

does not explain why the C1aC2 roots also do not reduplicate. If the generalizati<strong>on</strong> is that<br />

the pluracti<strong>on</strong>al involves reduplicati<strong>on</strong> except in the case that the three-mora restricti<strong>on</strong><br />

prevents reduplicati<strong>on</strong> from applying, then we cannot account for the behavior of C1aC2<br />

roots. One possible c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> is that the form of the pluracti<strong>on</strong>al for C1aC2 and<br />

C1VC2(ə)C3(ə) is lexically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed (despite the fact that the generalizati<strong>on</strong> is stated in<br />

terms of the ph<strong>on</strong>ological shape of the roots), while the allomorphy that distinguishes CV<br />

roots from CVC/CVCV roots (excluding those with a lexically specified pluracti<strong>on</strong>al<br />

form) is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by mora count and may relate, at least historically, to Schuh’s<br />

proposed trimoraic c<strong>on</strong>straint <strong>on</strong> verbs.<br />

New Zealand Maori (Polynesian, New Zealand; Biggs 1961) provides another<br />

example of stem-affix complementarity that could be driven by word minimality. In New<br />

Zealand Maori, the form of the inceptive prefix is kaa- before m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic stems and<br />

disyllabic stems where both syllables are short (i.e., before bimoraic stems), and ka-<br />

elsewhere. Examples of the kaa- allomorph are shown below (Biggs 1961: 29); Biggs<br />

does not provide examples with ka-.<br />

(14) kaa-pái ‘becomes good’ kaa-ríro ‘is carried away’<br />

163


This distributi<strong>on</strong> can be restated as referring to mora count: bimoraic stems take kaa-,<br />

while larger stems take ka-. A possible way of accounting for this would be to posit a<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straint requiring inceptive forms to have a minimum of four moras. Note, however,<br />

that we can use such a c<strong>on</strong>straint in an OT analysis of the allomorphy without P >> M,<br />

since the allomorphs are not necessarily in a suppletive relati<strong>on</strong>ship. Since they are so<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>etically similar to each other, these allomorphs could be related to a single<br />

underlying prefix, /ka-/, whose vowel undergoes lengthening when it occurs before a<br />

stem with two moras. Therefore, this example may result from minimality, but it is not an<br />

ideal candidate for a P >> M analysis. 12<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong>, we have seen five examples in which allomorphy appears to be<br />

driven by word minimality or maximality. However, some of these examples do not<br />

necessarily involve suppletive allomorphy, and as was discussed, some cannot easily be<br />

accounted for using the P >> M model. In §4.1.1.3, I discuss several more examples that<br />

defy analysis using P >> M since they involve allomorphy that is not optimizing with<br />

respect to any well-known P c<strong>on</strong>straints.<br />

12 Note also that the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs cannot be analyzed in terms of foot<br />

parsing. This is because there do exist stems in the language that are polysyllabic and<br />

have an initial l<strong>on</strong>g vowel. Some examples (from Harlow 1996, with page numbers in<br />

parentheses) include we:ra ‘whale’ (13), te:pu ‘table’ (19), pu:hi ‘shoot’ (47), wa:hi<br />

‘place’ (49), ta:ne ‘man’ (51), and ma:ku: ‘wet’ (18). According to Biggs’ (1961)<br />

generalizati<strong>on</strong>, stems with these shapes (CV:CV(:)) take the ka- prefix; this is<br />

problematic for foot parsing since the single light syllable c<strong>on</strong>tributed by ka- is prevented<br />

from being parsed into a well-formed foot when the stem-initial syllable is heavy.<br />

164


4.1.1.3 N<strong>on</strong>-optimizati<strong>on</strong><br />

In the preceding secti<strong>on</strong>s, we have seen examples in which the distributi<strong>on</strong> of<br />

allomorphs appears to have some motivati<strong>on</strong> based <strong>on</strong> foot parsing or word<br />

minimality/maximality. In this secti<strong>on</strong>, we will c<strong>on</strong>sider some examples of PCSA in<br />

which the motivati<strong>on</strong> for allomorphy is unclear, suggesting that the distributi<strong>on</strong> of<br />

allomorphs is arbitrary rather than optimizing. This is not to say that <strong>on</strong>e could never<br />

come up with some possible motivati<strong>on</strong> for any of these examples. However, unlike some<br />

of the examples presented above in §§4.1.1.1-2, there is no immediately obvious<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint that can be identified as driving the allomorphy.<br />

One example of PCSA in which the motivati<strong>on</strong> for allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong> is<br />

unclear is found in Turkana (Dimmendaal 1983). In Turkana, plural is marked <strong>on</strong> nouns<br />

by a prefix ŋa- or ŋI- and <strong>on</strong>e of three suffix allomorphs, -a, -In, or -I. 13 As seen in the<br />

examples below (Dimmendaal 1983: 226, Dimmendaal 2000: 44, 235), the -a allomorph<br />

occurs with stems of shape CV(C)VC ((15)a), the -In allomorph occurs with stems of<br />

shape CV(C)V ((15)b), and the -I allomorph occurs with stems of shape C(C)VC ((15)c).<br />

(15) a. ŋa-kìɲàŋ-a ‘crocodiles’ ŋa-ŋàjɛ̀p-a ‘t<strong>on</strong>gues’<br />

ŋa-ŋàsɛ̀p-a ‘placentas’ ŋɪ-kààl-a ‘camels’<br />

b. ŋa-kwap-ɪnˋ ‘lands’ ŋi-rot-inˋ ‘roads’<br />

ŋa-rʊk-ɪn ‘humps’ ŋa-kʊŋ-ɪn ‘knees’<br />

c. ŋi-wɔrʊ-ɪˋ ‘cloths’ ŋi-suro-iˋ ‘dik-diks’<br />

ŋa-pɔɔ-ɪˋ ‘hares’<br />

If coda c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants are moraic, then the use of -In with m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic stems could be seen<br />

as the result of a requirement that plural forms have a minimum of four moras. However,<br />

13 I is a high, fr<strong>on</strong>t vowel whose value for ±ATR is determined by the stem vowels.<br />

165


this still does not explain the distributi<strong>on</strong> of -a vs. -I. This could have something to do<br />

with sequences of vowels that are permitted to be adjacent to each other; perhaps [a] is<br />

dispreferred after another vowel, so -i is used in that envir<strong>on</strong>ment instead. We can<br />

therefore possibly explain the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs in these examples using<br />

comm<strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>straint types, but such an explanati<strong>on</strong> would be c<strong>on</strong>tingent <strong>on</strong> some<br />

unsubstantiated assumpti<strong>on</strong>s.<br />

Another example in which allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong> is not obviously optimizing is<br />

found in Kimatuumbi (Odden 1996). As was also discussed in chapter 2, the perfective in<br />

Kimatuumbi has four allomorphs: -i̹te, -i̹i̹le, -i̹i̹ye, and the infix -i̹-. The allomorphs are<br />

distributed as follows (Odden 1996: 51-53). M<strong>on</strong>osyllabic verbs (of shape (C)VC or<br />

(C)VVC), as well as stems whose final vowel is l<strong>on</strong>g, take -i̹te. Examples are shown<br />

below (Odden 1996: 51).<br />

(16) ni̹-chól-i̹te ‘draw’ ni̹-tí̹n-i̹te ‘chop’<br />

ni̹-bálaang-i̹te ‘count’ ni̹-chéleew-i̹te ‘be late’<br />

Polysyllabic stems (except those with a final l<strong>on</strong>g vowel) take the -i̹- infix, which is<br />

inserted into the stem-final syllable, as in the examples below (Odden 1996: 51). These<br />

forms also select the final vowel e rather than a.<br />

(17) ni̹-áandi̹-i̹-ke ‘write’ ni̹-béli̹-i̹-ke ‘bear’<br />

ni̹-chíili̹-i̹-ye ‘be late’ ni̹-sábi̹-i̹-te ‘beat’<br />

As was discussed in chapter 2, glide-final roots take -i̹i̹le, while stems ending in yaan or<br />

waan take -i̹i̹ye (Odden 1996: 53).<br />

The distributi<strong>on</strong> could be c<strong>on</strong>strued as resulting from a requirement that<br />

perfective forms, including their prefixes, have four syllables. However, the four-syllable<br />

166


generalizati<strong>on</strong> does not apply in all cases, since disyllabic stems whose final vowel is<br />

l<strong>on</strong>g take -i̹te, thereby ending up with five syllables. Also, all roots ending in yaan or<br />

waan take the -i̹i̹ye suffix, resulting in words with more than four syllables. Furthermore,<br />

if the four-syllable requirement were invoked to explain the use of -i̹te with m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic<br />

stems, then we would also have to explain why this allomorph is used after stems with a<br />

final l<strong>on</strong>g vowel. Therefore, much of the pattern seen here cannot be attributed to a<br />

minimality c<strong>on</strong>straint, and appears to be arbitrary.<br />

In Nancowry (Radhakrishnan 1980), there is another example of syllable count-<br />

based PCSA in which the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs appears to be arbitrary. In<br />

Nancowry, there the instrumental is marked by either -an- or -in-. M<strong>on</strong>osyllabic stems<br />

select -an-, while disyllabic stems (including those built from a m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic root plus<br />

causative prefix) select -in-, which overwrites the rime of the initial syllable<br />

(Radhakrishnan 1980: 60-63). Some examples are shown below (Radhakrishnan 1980:<br />

61, 62-63).<br />

(18) káp ‘to bite’ k,an,áp ‘tooth’<br />

tián ‘to file’ t,an,ián ‘a file’<br />

léʔ ‘to catch’ l,an,éʔ ‘an object to catch with’<br />

rɯ́ k ‘to arrive’ r,an,ɯ́ k ‘a vehicle’<br />

kaʔáp ‘to close’ k,in,ʔáp ‘a trap’<br />

tikóʔ ‘to prick’ t,in,kóʔ ‘pin, needle’<br />

sahuáŋ ‘cool’ s,in,huáŋ ‘something that cools’<br />

ha-kiãk ‘to inflate’ h,in,kiãk ‘a pump’<br />

In this example, there appears to be no functi<strong>on</strong>al motivati<strong>on</strong> for the distributi<strong>on</strong> of the<br />

allomorphs. As with the causative examples given above in §4.1.1.1, instrumental forms<br />

appear always to have two syllables, so <strong>on</strong>e might argue that the distributi<strong>on</strong> of<br />

allomorphs is ‘optimizing’ with respect to syllable count. However, <strong>on</strong>ce we distinguish<br />

167


etween affix shape and affix placement, the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs seems arbitrary<br />

as in many other examples described in this secti<strong>on</strong>. The -in- allomorph overwrites the<br />

first vowel of a disyllabic stem, yielding a disyllabic word, while the -an- allomorph is<br />

inserted after the first c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant of a m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic stem without overwriting the vowel.<br />

However, the infixes themselves could just as easily pattern in the opposite way; their<br />

actual behavior is no more natural than if the -in- suffix were inserted after the first<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant of a m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic stem and the -an- suffix were to overwrite the first vowel of<br />

a disyllabic stem. Thus, the distributi<strong>on</strong> of the allomorphs in terms of their shape does not<br />

appear to be functi<strong>on</strong>ally motivated.<br />

Another example involving apparently arbitrary allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong> is found in<br />

Martuthunira, where there are two different forms of the collective suffix (Dench 1995:<br />

§6.1.5, §6.3.2) <strong>on</strong> ‘L-c<strong>on</strong>jugati<strong>on</strong>’ verbs that are distributed according to the size of the<br />

verb stem (1995: 38). Bimoraic stems take -yarri, while larger stems take -lwarri. Some<br />

examples are provided below (Dench 1995: 38).<br />

(19) karta-yarri stab-COLL thuulwa-lwarri pull out-COLL<br />

thani-yarri hit-COLL kartatha-lwarri chop-COLL<br />

This is an interesting case because not <strong>on</strong>ly is there not a complementary relati<strong>on</strong>ship<br />

between the size of the stem and affix, but if anything, the situati<strong>on</strong> is the exact reverse:<br />

larger stems take the larger allomorph. 14 There does not seem to be any way to predict<br />

the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs based <strong>on</strong> their shape.<br />

14 Of course, if coda c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants are not moraic, then the noti<strong>on</strong> of the ‘larger’ allomorph<br />

is not very significant (it would simply refer to the allomorph with more segments).<br />

However, it is worth pointing out this generalizati<strong>on</strong>, because it underscores the fact that<br />

this example does not show the kind of complementarity between the stem and affix that<br />

was seen in some examples in §§4.1.1.1-2.<br />

168


Another interesting example of syllable count-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy in which<br />

the allomorphs c<strong>on</strong>tribute the same number of syllables to the stem is found in Kashaya<br />

(Oswalt 1960, Buckley 1994). As discussed in chapter 2, the durative in Kashaya exhibits<br />

PCSA c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed both by syllable count and by the stem-final c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant. According to<br />

Buckley (1994: 328-329), the allomorphs are distributed as follows. The first split<br />

(described in chapter 2) is between c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant- and vowel-final stems. Am<strong>on</strong>g vowel-<br />

final stems, there is another split based <strong>on</strong> syllable count: m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic stems take -cin’,<br />

while polysyllabic stems take -men’. Finally, in general, c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems take -an. 15<br />

Examples of vowel-final roots exhibiting syllable count-based allomorphy are provided<br />

below (Oswalt 1960: 212-213). 16<br />

(20) sime-sime-ciˑd-u ‘to keep <strong>on</strong> sprinkling’<br />

buwi-ciˑd-u ‘to keep <strong>on</strong> stringing’<br />

duk’ilci-meˑd-u ‘<strong>on</strong>e to keep pointing <strong>on</strong>ce’<br />

mohqa-méˑd-u ‘<strong>on</strong>e to drive’<br />

The stems characterized as m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic appear in these examples to have more than <strong>on</strong>e<br />

syllable; this leads Oswalt to characterize the distributi<strong>on</strong> of durative allomorphs<br />

somewhat differently from Buckley (Oswalt states that -cin’ is used ‘after a vowel...<br />

when that preceding vowel is in the sec<strong>on</strong>d syllable of the verb’ (Oswalt 1960: 212),<br />

while -men’ ‘...is used after a vowel... when that preceding vowel is in the third or later<br />

syllable of the word’ (Oswalt 1960: 212). However, vowel epenthesis may be argued to<br />

apply to stems <strong>on</strong>ly after the attachment of -cin’, so that the stem for attachment of this<br />

allomorph is actually m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic as characterized by Buckely. This is an important<br />

15<br />

Am<strong>on</strong>g c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems, there also exists an elaborate subpattern of allomorphy,<br />

discussed in chapter 2, which seems to reduce to morphological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing.<br />

16<br />

Note that what Buckley refers to as -cin’ is generally transcribed as [ciˑd], while<br />

Buckley’s -men’ is transcribed as [meˑd].<br />

169


point, because if -cin’ attaches to m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic stems which later gain an extra syllable<br />

through epenthesis, then the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> for the attachment of -cin’ is rendered opaque.<br />

This then is another example of the type of opaque c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing of PCSA that would be<br />

difficult to capture in a P >> M analysis; other examples of this type include the Spanish<br />

example discussed in §4.1.1.1, and several examples discussed in chapter 2 (§2.1.2.6).<br />

Zuni (isolate, New Mexico; Newman 1965) exhibits another example of possibly<br />

arbitrary PCSA. The form of the singular suffix that attaches to nouns in Zuni depends in<br />

part up<strong>on</strong> the number of syllables in the stem, as follows (Newman 1965: 23-24). Nouns<br />

of class 2 (which are all m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic) take the suffix -mmeʔ ((21)a). Nouns of class 3<br />

(which are all polysyllabic) take -ʔe ((21)b). Am<strong>on</strong>g class 1 nouns, the distributi<strong>on</strong> of<br />

allomorphs depends <strong>on</strong> syllable count. Those with <strong>on</strong>e syllable take -ʔleʔ ((21)c). Those<br />

with two syllables take the allomorph -nne ((21)d). Examples are shown below (Newman<br />

1965: 24).<br />

(21) a. kʔe-mmeʔ ‘stalk’<br />

b. sap-ʔe ‘box of dishes’ (< sapa)<br />

c. ɬi-ʔleʔ ‘sinew’<br />

d. homa-nne ‘juniper leaf’<br />

Though part of the distributi<strong>on</strong> refers to lexical classes, the allomorphy within class 1 is<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological since it is determined by syllable count. However, note that the distributi<strong>on</strong><br />

of allomorphs does not affect the surface syllable count. Each suffix allomorph<br />

c<strong>on</strong>tributes exactly <strong>on</strong>e syllable to the word, so their distributi<strong>on</strong> does not complement<br />

the syllable count of the stem. It is possible that the generalizati<strong>on</strong> could have to do with<br />

mora count instead, since in the examples seen above, both of the class 1 singular forms<br />

may have four moras, if it is assumed that coda c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants c<strong>on</strong>tribute a mora. However,<br />

170


not all singular nouns fit this pattern (e.g., the example sap-ʔe in (21)b has <strong>on</strong>ly three<br />

moras).<br />

Another apparently n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing example of PCSA is found in Tzeltal (Mayan,<br />

Mexico). According to Walsh Dickey (1999), perfective suffix allomorphs in Tzeltal are<br />

selected based <strong>on</strong> syllable count, but the shape of the affixes themselves does not seem to<br />

relate to syllable count: the variants are -oh (occurring with m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic stems) and -ɛh<br />

(occurring with polysyllabic stems). Examples of the -oh variant are provided below<br />

(Walsh Dickey 1999: 328-329).<br />

(22) s-mah-oh ‘he has hit something’ j-il-oh ‘he has seen something’<br />

s-pas-oh ‘he has made something’ s-kut͡ʃ-oh ‘she has carried it’<br />

s-nut͡s-oh ‘he has chased something’ j-al-oh ‘he has told something’<br />

s-tsak-oh ‘he has taken something’ s-jom-oh ‘he has gathered it’<br />

s-nɛt’-oh ‘he has squashed something’<br />

When the root is polysyllabic, the perfective suffix is -Eh, as shown below (Walsh<br />

Dickey 1999: 328).<br />

(23) s-majlij-ɛh ‘he has waited for some<strong>on</strong>e’ s-mak’lin-ɛh ‘he has fed some<strong>on</strong>e’<br />

s-maklij-ɛh ‘he has listened to something’ s-tikun-ɛh ‘he has sent something’<br />

The -ɛh variant is also used with a m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic root when another suffix intervenes,<br />

resulting in a polysyllabic stem, as shown in the examples below (Walsh Dickey 1999:<br />

329, no interlinear glosses provided).<br />

(24) s-hol-intaj-ɛh ‘he has thought about it’<br />

h-pak’-antaj-ɛh ‘I have patched it’<br />

s-kut͡ʃ-laj-ɛh ‘she was carrying it repeatedly’<br />

This c<strong>on</strong>stitutes another example in which the shape of the allomorphs does not relate to<br />

the ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> their distributi<strong>on</strong>.<br />

171


A final example of apparently n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing PCSA is found in Axininca Campa<br />

(Arawakan, Peru; Payne 1981). In Axininca Campa, there is a genitive suffix that takes<br />

<strong>on</strong>e of two forms, -ni or -ti, depending <strong>on</strong> whether the stem (not including the pers<strong>on</strong><br />

marking prefix) has two vocalic moras or more than two, respectively. Examples are<br />

shown below (Payne 1981: 244-246).<br />

(25) no-sari-ni ‘my macaw’ a-t<strong>on</strong>iro-ti ‘our palm (aquaje)’<br />

p-ana-ni ‘your black dye’ pi-wiiri-ti ‘your bat’<br />

o-çaa-ni ‘her anteater’ o-itairiki-ti ‘her wild pig’<br />

i-yimi-ni ‘his squash’ n-aawana-ti ‘my mahogany’<br />

Once again, there does not appear to be any motivati<strong>on</strong> for the distributi<strong>on</strong> of the two<br />

allomorphs; the distributi<strong>on</strong> seems to be arbitrary.<br />

The examples in this secti<strong>on</strong> are of interest because, unlike the more well-known<br />

examples in the literature, these examples do not seem to involve ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

optimizati<strong>on</strong>, at least not in any obvious way. Even if some motivati<strong>on</strong> were proposed for<br />

some of the examples seen in this secti<strong>on</strong>, the existence of several examples in which<br />

stem syllable count determines allomorphs that c<strong>on</strong>tribute the same number of syllables<br />

to the word is sufficient to dem<strong>on</strong>strate that, c<strong>on</strong>trary to Kager (1996), syllable-counting<br />

allomorphy does not always reduce to foot parsing c<strong>on</strong>straints.<br />

4.1.2 Summary<br />

We have discussed numerous examples in which the distributi<strong>on</strong> of suppletive<br />

allomorphs is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by syllable or mora count. Some of them appeared to be driven<br />

by foot parsing (§4.1.1.1), and others by word minimality or maximality (§4.1.1.2); some<br />

did not appear to optimize words in any readily apparent way (§4.1.1.3). One<br />

generalizati<strong>on</strong> that holds for all three of these example types is that every example<br />

172


discussed in this chapter involves affix allomorphy, rather than allomorphy in stems or<br />

clitics. This follows from a model of morphology in which words are built from the<br />

inside out; it does not follow from the simplest versi<strong>on</strong> of the P >> M model, in which<br />

unordered stems and affixes appear together in the input with no bracketing or other<br />

indicati<strong>on</strong> of the structure of the word.<br />

As has been discussed throughout this secti<strong>on</strong>, some of the examples seen here<br />

have other characteristics that suggest that the P >> M model is not the best way to<br />

handle them. For instance, some of the examples discussed above involve opaque<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing, in which the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> for the attachment of an affix is rendered opaque by<br />

a ph<strong>on</strong>ological process. This shows that PCSA is not necessarily a process that optimizes<br />

surface forms, and it suggests that the selecti<strong>on</strong> of suppletive allomorphs occurs before<br />

the applicati<strong>on</strong> of regular ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes. 17 Also, in several examples,<br />

particularly the examples of minimality/maximality-related allomorphy discussed in<br />

§4.1.1.2, we can <strong>on</strong>ly capture the ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s using language-specific<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straints. Thus, the patterns are <strong>on</strong>ly ‘optimizing’ if we define optimizati<strong>on</strong> to mean<br />

that some c<strong>on</strong>straint can be written to account for them. For example, in the Miya<br />

example discussed in §4.1.1.2, the differential applicati<strong>on</strong> of reduplicati<strong>on</strong> and vowel<br />

lengthening to stems with different mora counts was claimed to result from a c<strong>on</strong>straint<br />

requiring verbs to have no more than three moras. However, PCSA driven by such a<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straint can <strong>on</strong>ly be ‘optimizing’ in a language that prefers verbs to have no more than<br />

three moras; there is nothing inherently optimal about trimoraic verbs. Thus, although it<br />

17 In using the word ‘before’ here, I mean that ph<strong>on</strong>ological rules/processes apply to<br />

whatever is the outcome of allomorph selecti<strong>on</strong>; this does not have to be understood as a<br />

serially ordered sequence of events.<br />

173


is possible to provide a P >> M analysis for the examples in this chapter, many of the<br />

analyses would involve stipulative language-specific c<strong>on</strong>straints.<br />

I have argued against using the P >> M model to account for these examples, and<br />

yet, as has been acknowledged throughout this chapter, there are many examples of<br />

prosodically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy that truly do seem to optimize words in<br />

some way, particularly in the cases relating to foot structure discussed in §4.1.1.1. Since<br />

the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach does not incorporate the noti<strong>on</strong> of optimizati<strong>on</strong>, there is<br />

some sense in which the burden is <strong>on</strong> advocates of subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> to explain why these<br />

examples appear to optimize words; to say that this is a coincidence would be<br />

unsatisfying. Explaining the apparent optimizati<strong>on</strong> in prosodically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed PCSA is<br />

therefore somewhat of a challenge for the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach. In the following<br />

secti<strong>on</strong>, I resp<strong>on</strong>d to this challenge by providing a historical explanati<strong>on</strong> for a set of<br />

related examples of PCSA from the Pama-Nyungan languages of Australia. I will<br />

dem<strong>on</strong>strate that, despite the fact that several of the examples appear to be ph<strong>on</strong>ologically<br />

optimizing, many are not, and all have a comm<strong>on</strong> historical source involving individual<br />

and independently motivated changes not driven by prosodic optimizati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

4.2 Historical development of prosodically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy: The<br />

case of Pama-Nyungan ergative suffix allomorphy<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong> I examine the historical origins of the syllable- or mora-counting<br />

allomorphy exhibited by the ergative suffix in many Pama-Nyungan (henceforth PN)<br />

languages, which will be described here. This is an important case study because it can<br />

help shed light <strong>on</strong> an important questi<strong>on</strong> raised by the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach to<br />

PCSA. One potential objecti<strong>on</strong> to the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach is that it does not<br />

174


explain why many cases of PCSA, perhaps more than expected to occur by chance, seem<br />

to be ph<strong>on</strong>ologically optimizing. For example, as has been seen in this chapter, many<br />

cases of syllable- and mora-counting allomorphy pattern in such a way that the<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs results in words with an even syllable/mora count, which<br />

facilitates exhaustive parsing into binary feet. The subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach can easily<br />

capture these patterns, but does not explain the apparent foot-parsing optimizati<strong>on</strong> that<br />

seems to drive them.<br />

One may therefore wish to argue that although subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> is needed to<br />

handle the apparently arbitrary (n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing) cases of PCSA, an output optimizati<strong>on</strong><br />

approach should still be used for the apparently optimizing cases so as not to lose any<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological generalizati<strong>on</strong>s (such as the foot-parsing optimizati<strong>on</strong> menti<strong>on</strong>ed above).<br />

However, the lack of explanatory power is not problematic for subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> if there<br />

is an external explanati<strong>on</strong> for the apparent optimizati<strong>on</strong>. For example, if we can explain a<br />

case of apparent optimizing PCSA diachr<strong>on</strong>ically, then there is no need to incorporate<br />

this into the synchr<strong>on</strong>ic model of PCSA at the expense of a unitary account of the<br />

phenomen<strong>on</strong>. In this secti<strong>on</strong> I discuss the origins of PN ergative allomorphy, arguing that<br />

the apparent optimizing pattern exhibited in the ergative allomorphy in some modern PN<br />

languages arose by accident and not for the purpose of ph<strong>on</strong>ological optimizati<strong>on</strong>. 18<br />

18 I do not claim here that there is no bias in language acquisiti<strong>on</strong> towards finding patterns<br />

that are optimizing; this may be the case. However, as I will show, n<strong>on</strong>e of the specific<br />

changes that led to the modern patterns of PN ergative allomorphy were necessarily<br />

optimizing. As will be seen, in some modern languages, the result of these accumulated<br />

changes has the appearance of being optimizing; in other languages, however, the result<br />

of these changes looks arbitrary.<br />

175


4.2.1 Examples<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong>, I describe some examples of ergative and/or locative allomorphy<br />

in several PN languages. I include the locative suffixes here because in many languages,<br />

they pattern just like the ergative (in most instances, the <strong>on</strong>ly difference is that the<br />

locative suffixes have the vowel a where the ergative suffixes have u). 19 A fuller list of<br />

examples is provided by Sands 1996 (for ergative <strong>on</strong>ly); here I focus <strong>on</strong> a smaller set of<br />

languages that exemplify the range of patterns found throughout the c<strong>on</strong>tinent. I have<br />

attempted to balance the survey by providing broad geographical coverage of the Pama-<br />

Nyungan area; below I give a map showing the locati<strong>on</strong>s of the languages to be discussed<br />

in this secti<strong>on</strong>.<br />

19 In fact, it may be the case that in at least some of the languages to be discussed here,<br />

the initial c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant(s) of the ergative and locative suffixes is actually a stem ending, and<br />

that the suffixes themselves c<strong>on</strong>sist <strong>on</strong>ly of vowels. This would mean that in some<br />

languages, the apparent parallel allomorphy between ergative and locative reduces to a<br />

single pattern of allomorphy in the stem ending that co-occurs with the ergative and<br />

locative suffixes. The resoluti<strong>on</strong> of this issue is not crucial to my analysis.<br />

176


Figure 1: Map showing locati<strong>on</strong> of examples of ergative allomorphy<br />

Map outline © 2006 Comm<strong>on</strong>wealth of Australia (Geoscience Australia).<br />

Used with permissi<strong>on</strong>.<br />

Below I present a number of examples of ergative and locative allomorphy in languages<br />

represented <strong>on</strong> the map. The examples are organized according to the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> that<br />

determines the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs. I begin with examples c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by syllable<br />

count. For readers not wishing to read through descripti<strong>on</strong>s of all of the examples, I<br />

provide tables summarizing the patterns of ergative and locative allomorphy; these tables<br />

are given at the end of all of the descripti<strong>on</strong>s.<br />

One example of syllable count-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppleti<strong>on</strong> that looks <strong>on</strong> its surface to<br />

be driven by a minimality c<strong>on</strong>straint (but probably is not) is the ergative marker in<br />

177


Dyirbal (Dix<strong>on</strong> 1972). In Dyirbal, the ergative case is marked by -ŋgu or -gu, as shown<br />

below.<br />

(26) yara-ŋgu ‘man-ERG’ yamani-gu ‘rainbow-ERG’<br />

The ph<strong>on</strong>ological generalizati<strong>on</strong> is that -ŋgu occurs with disyllabic stems, while -gu<br />

occurs with larger stems. According to McCarthy and Prince (1990), although it has been<br />

proposed that this (and similar phenomena in other Australian languages) be analyzed as<br />

fulfilling a requirement that the ergative c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> has four moras, such an analysis is<br />

problematic because c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants generally are not mora-bearing in Pama-Nyungan<br />

languages. 20 Thus, this putative example of allomorph selecti<strong>on</strong> based <strong>on</strong> minimality<br />

probably does not go through. This is a simple case of arbitrary suppletive allomorphy<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by a ph<strong>on</strong>ological factor (syllable count) not related to the shape of the<br />

allomorphs.<br />

Another syllable count-related example is found in Kaititj (Koch 1980), where the<br />

ergative/ instrumental/ locative suffix has three surface realizati<strong>on</strong>s (probably relating to<br />

two underlying forms). The -ŋ form occurs <strong>on</strong>ly after disyllabic stems, while the -l form<br />

is selected after stems with three or more syllables (and excepti<strong>on</strong>ally after a few specific<br />

disyllabic stems) (Koch 1980: 265-266). In additi<strong>on</strong> to this split, the -l suffix also has two<br />

realizati<strong>on</strong>s: [ɭ] following an apical c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant and [l] elsewhere (Koch note 9). I assume<br />

that these latter allomorphs corresp<strong>on</strong>d to a single underlying form, /-l/. The distributi<strong>on</strong><br />

of the ergative/instrumental/locative forms is shown below (N, M = prestopped apical<br />

and labial nasals, respectively; examples are from Koch 1980: 264-266).<br />

20 This is made explicit in analyses of, e.g., Yindjibarndi (Wordick 1982).<br />

178


(27) aki-ŋ ‘head-ERG’ ilt y i-ŋ ‘hand-ERG’<br />

aNmi-ŋ ‘red ochre-ERG’ aynpi-ŋ ‘pouch-ERG’<br />

aliki-l ‘dog-ERG’ aʈuyi-l ‘man-ERG’<br />

aɣirki-l ‘sun-ERG’ awiyawi-l-amiɳ ‘dead pers<strong>on</strong> (pl.)-ERG’<br />

aɣiri-ɭ ‘kangaroo-ERG’ ɭuNpiri-ɭ ‘forehead-ERG’<br />

at̪iri-ɭ ‘two-ERG’ aMu-ŋi-t̪iri-ɭ ‘snake-ERG’<br />

The -N and -l allomorphs could be related to a single underlying form by using some<br />

arbitrary rule referring to the number of syllables in the root, but this seems undesirable.<br />

Such a rule would not be motivated by any principle of the language or by any functi<strong>on</strong>al<br />

c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s. Furthermore, the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing envir<strong>on</strong>ment has no relati<strong>on</strong> to the shape of<br />

the allomorphs. Therefore, this example appears to be n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing in nature.<br />

Diyari (Austin 1981) marks ergative case with the suffixes -ndu, -li, and -yali. The<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong> of the allomorphs is determined both semantically and ph<strong>on</strong>ologically (based<br />

<strong>on</strong> syllable count and the stem-final segment) as follows (Austin 1981: 48-49). Female<br />

pers<strong>on</strong>al names take -ndu. Male pers<strong>on</strong>al names, n<strong>on</strong>-singular comm<strong>on</strong> nouns with final u<br />

becoming [a], and singular comm<strong>on</strong> nouns with final u or i becoming [a] take -li.<br />

Singular comm<strong>on</strong> nouns with two, four, or five syllables with final u or i take -yali, and<br />

singular comm<strong>on</strong> nouns with three syllables with final u or i can take either -yali or -li.<br />

Examples are shown below (Austin 1981: 49).<br />

(28) t̹iɽimiri -ndu ‘(woman’s name)-ERG’<br />

waŋamiri-li ‘(man’s name)-ERG’<br />

t̪aɽiwuɭa-li ‘youth.DUAL-ERG’<br />

t̪aɽiwaɽa-li ‘youth.PL-ERG’<br />

kanku-yali ‘boy-ERG’<br />

wadukat̪i-yali ‘emu-ERG’<br />

yapakaɲt̹in̪t̪u-yali ‘fear-EXCESS-PROP-ERG’<br />

kan̪ina-li ~ kan̪ini-yali ‘mother’s mother-ERG’<br />

A number of examples also refer to mora count rather than syllable count. For<br />

example, in Warlpiri (Nash 1986), the ergative is marked by -ngku after bimoraic stems,<br />

179


and by -rlu after l<strong>on</strong>ger stems. Examples are shown below (page numbers from Nash<br />

1986 are given next to each example).<br />

(29) ngurrpa-ngku ‘unknowing-ERG’ (34) nguurrpa-rlu ‘throat-ERG’ (34)<br />

ngapa-ngku ‘water-ERG’ (41) nyanungu-rlu ‘he-ERG’ (235)<br />

ngarrka-ngku ‘man-ERG’ (234) Jakamarra-rlu ‘(name)-ERG’ (217)<br />

kurdu-ngku ‘child-ERG’ (227) kurdu-jarra-rlu ‘child-DUAL-ERG’ (231)<br />

The locative in Warlpiri exhibits the same pattern as the ergative, except that the<br />

locative suffixes have a where the ergative suffixes have u. Examples are shown below<br />

(page numbers from Nash 1986 are shown next to each example).<br />

(30) ngulya-ngka ‘hole-LOC’ (30) karti-ngka ‘cards-LOC’ (203)<br />

karru-ngka ‘creek-LOC’ (203) pirli-ngka ‘rock-LOC’ (176)<br />

yali-rla ‘that-LOC’ (176) turaki-rla ‘vehicle-LOC’ (145)<br />

Yalikarangu-rla ‘(placename)-LOC’ (132)<br />

manangkarra-rla ‘spinifex plain-LOC’ (102)<br />

In Nhanda (Blevins 2001), ergative and instrumental suffix allomorphy is<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by the minimal vs. n<strong>on</strong>-mininal word stem distincti<strong>on</strong>, again in terms of<br />

moras (Blevins 2001: 48, 50). Ergative is marked by -(ng)gu with bimoraic stems and -lu<br />

with l<strong>on</strong>ger stems, as shown below (ng is deleted following a homorganic NC cluster<br />

(Blevins 2001: 48-49)).<br />

(31) nyarlu-nggu ‘woman-ERG’ nguutu-lu ‘horse-ERG’<br />

uthu-nggu ‘dog-ERG’ arnmanu-lu ‘man-ERG’<br />

munda-gu ‘poor-ERG’ kurndi-waa-lu ‘club-COM-ERG’<br />

Instrumental exhibits the exact same allomorphs and pattern of allomorphy (Blevins<br />

2001: 50-51). Examples are shown below.<br />

(32) mara-nggu ‘hand-INST’ yadiwa-lu ‘axe-INST’<br />

wana-nggu ‘digging stick-INST’ yawarda-lu ‘kangaroo-INST’<br />

mambu-gu ‘b<strong>on</strong>e-INST’ arnmanu-lu ‘man-ERG’<br />

The locative in Nhanda is marked by -(ng)gu; there is no -lu allomorph (Blevins 2001:<br />

52).<br />

180


(33) malu-nggu ‘shade-LOC’ mambu-gu ‘b<strong>on</strong>e-LOC’<br />

uthudu-nggu ‘ground-LOC’ marnda-gu-tha ‘buttocks-LOC-1sgOBL’<br />

In some cases, allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong> refers both to mora count and to another<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological factor. For example, the locative suffix in Martuthunira (Dench 1995)<br />

exhibits allomorphy based <strong>on</strong> both the root-final segment and mora count. Bimoraic<br />

stems with a final vowel take the suffix -ngka, stems with three or more morae with a<br />

final vowel take -la, and there is further allomorphy am<strong>on</strong>g c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems<br />

depending <strong>on</strong> the c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant (Dench 1995: 64). The effector suffix has the same shape as<br />

the locative in all of these c<strong>on</strong>texts, except that in each case, the effector suffix has /u/<br />

rather than /a/. Some examples are provided below (Dench 1995: 38). This example is<br />

discussed further in chapter 2 because allomorph selecti<strong>on</strong> is sensitive to c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant<br />

features and the C/V distincti<strong>on</strong> in additi<strong>on</strong> to mora count.<br />

(34) nguu-ngka ‘face-LOC’ kaara-la ‘hip b<strong>on</strong>e-LOC’<br />

nharnu-ngka ‘sand-LOC’ malarnu-la ‘shade-LOC’<br />

muyi-ngku ‘dog-EFF’ muyira-lu ‘dingo-EFF’<br />

tharnta-ngku ‘euro-EFF’ mirntirimarta-lu ‘goanna-EFF’<br />

Since codas are not moraic, the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs has no effect <strong>on</strong> the number of<br />

moras in the surface forms.<br />

A similar example is found in Yindjibarndi (Wordick 1982), where the locative is<br />

marked <strong>on</strong> comm<strong>on</strong> nouns by -ŋka or -la (Wordick 1982: 56). The -ŋka allomorph occurs<br />

with m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic roots ending in a vowel and with disyllabic roots ending in a vowel if<br />

each syllable c<strong>on</strong>tains <strong>on</strong>ly a single short vowel. The -la allomorph occurs with roots<br />

having three or more morae and with c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final roots. Some examples are given<br />

below (examples are from Wordick 1982: 63-65 and have been adapted into ph<strong>on</strong>etic<br />

notati<strong>on</strong>).<br />

181


(35) parlu-ŋka ‘cliff-LOC’<br />

warkamu-la-ŋu ‘work-LOC-ABL’ maatha-la ‘boss-LOC’<br />

kuɲciri-la-mpa ‘<strong>on</strong>e-LOC-TOP’<br />

Coda c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants are not c<strong>on</strong>sidered to be moraic (Wordick 1982: 40), so although the<br />

allomorphy is based partly <strong>on</strong> mora count, the choice of the locative allomorph does not<br />

alter the mora count of the word: each c<strong>on</strong>tributes <strong>on</strong>e mora. In terms of mora count,<br />

then, the allomorphy does not c<strong>on</strong>tribute to well-formedness. However, the V/C sensitive<br />

aspect of the distributi<strong>on</strong> is optimizing with respect to syllable structure, since the<br />

selecti<strong>on</strong> of -la after c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final roots prevents the creati<strong>on</strong> of three-c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant<br />

clusters (which would occur if -ŋka were suffixed to a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final root, assuming that<br />

/ŋk/ is not a single segment but two separate segments). Three-c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant clusters do not<br />

exist in the language (Wordick 1982: 14).<br />

Yet another very similar example is found in Yingkarta (Dench 1998), where the<br />

ergative and locative markers exhibit allomorphy based <strong>on</strong> mora count and the final<br />

segment (Dench 1998: 15-16). Vowel final stems with two moras mark ergative with the<br />

suffix -ngku, and locative with -ngka. Vowel-final stems wtih three or more moras mark<br />

ergative with -lu and locative with -la. Stems with a final c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant take the ergative<br />

suffix -Su and locative -Sa (where S is a stop homorganic with the preceding c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant;<br />

ergative and locative examples with stem-final c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants are limited to apical nasals and<br />

laterals in Dench’s corpus, so it is not known which allomorph is selected by rr-final<br />

stems). Examples are shown below (Dench 1998: 19-21, except where noted).<br />

(36) Ergative<br />

ngampu-ngku ‘stick-ERG’ mayu-ngku ‘child-ERG’<br />

kutharra-lu ‘two-ERG’ partirri-lu ‘returning-ERG’<br />

majun-tu ‘turtle-ERG’<br />

182


Locative<br />

jurla-ngka ‘scrub-LOC’ kuru-ngka ‘eye-LOC’<br />

parrumpa-la ‘wattle-LOC’ paapa-la ‘guts-LOC’<br />

kurtan-ta ‘bag-LOC’<br />

(Dench 1998: 29)<br />

In several cases, the distributi<strong>on</strong> of ergative or locative allomorphs refers solely to<br />

the final segment of the stem, and in particular, to whether the stem is c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant- or<br />

vowel-final. For instance, as discussed in chapter 2, the ergative in Warrgamay (Dix<strong>on</strong><br />

1980: 266) is marked by the suffix -ŋgu after a vowel-final stem and by -du after a<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stem, as shown below.<br />

(37) ŋulmburu-ŋgu ‘woman-ERG’ wurrbi-ŋgu ‘big-ERG’<br />

wurrbi-bajun-du ‘very big-ERG’<br />

This distributi<strong>on</strong> results in avoidance of three-c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant clusters.<br />

A similar pattern is found in Yidiɲ (Dix<strong>on</strong> 1977). Ergative is marked by -ŋgu after<br />

a vowel-final stem, or -du after a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stem (d assimilates to a preceding stem-<br />

final nasal (Dix<strong>on</strong> 1977: 126)). Examples are given below (Dix<strong>on</strong> 1977: 126-127).<br />

(38) wagud̹a-ŋgu ‘man-ERG’<br />

warabal-du ‘flying squirrel-ERG’ d̹ud̹u:m-bu ‘father’s sister-ERG’<br />

The locative and allative allomorphs in Yidiɲ are selected based <strong>on</strong> whether the<br />

stem is c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final or vowel final (Dix<strong>on</strong> 1980: 296), though in this case (unlike in<br />

the ergative), the allomorphy cannot be claimed to optimize syllable structure in any way<br />

since both allomorphs have the shape -CV. Their distributi<strong>on</strong> is as follows: -la occurs<br />

after vowel-final stems; -da occurs after c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems (d assimilates to the place<br />

of a preceding stem-final nasal (Dix<strong>on</strong> 1977: 129)). Examples are shown below.<br />

183


(39) digarra-la gabud̹u-la<br />

‘beach-LOC’ (Dix<strong>on</strong> 1980: 296) ‘white clay-LOC’ (Dix<strong>on</strong> 1977: 128)<br />

ward̹a:n-da mud̹a:m-ba<br />

‘boat-LOC’ (Dix<strong>on</strong> 1977: 129) ‘mother-LOC’ (Dix<strong>on</strong> 1977: 129)<br />

Although these allomorphs are not related through a general rule of the language, <strong>on</strong>e<br />

might still assume that they corresp<strong>on</strong>d to a single underlying form, /-da/, and that /d/<br />

surfaces as [l] after a vowel due to a leniti<strong>on</strong> rule specific to the locative and allative<br />

suffixes. This example is therefore not necessarily suppletive, though the rule relating the<br />

allomorphs would apply <strong>on</strong>ly to the locative and allative.<br />

Another example of C/V-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy is found in Biri (Terrill 1998),<br />

where <strong>on</strong>ce again the ergative/instrumental and locative suffixes exhibit allomorphy<br />

determined by the final segment of the stem. Vowel-final stems select the ergative/<br />

locative form -ŋgu, while c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems select -du, as seen below (page numbers<br />

from Terrill 1998 are given next to each example).<br />

(40) gunhami-ŋgu ‘that-ERG’ (15) bunbun-du ‘pheasant-ERG’ (36)<br />

gayu-ŋgu ‘woman-ERG’ (15) dhagany-dyu ‘crocodile-ERG’ (35)<br />

mala-ŋgu ‘hand-INST’ (16) waŋgarany-dyu ‘all-ERG’ (50)<br />

balgu-ŋgu ‘axe-INST’ (16)<br />

The locative suffix in Biri shows the same pattern except that it has a where the<br />

ergative/instrumental has u, as shown below (Terrill 1998).<br />

(41) dhula-ŋga ‘tree-LOC’ (19) bidhal-da ‘Woodhouse Stati<strong>on</strong>-LOC’ (54)<br />

yamba-ŋga ‘camp-LOC’ (19) waŋal-da ‘boomerang-LOC’ (20)<br />

buri-ŋga ‘fire-LOC’ (19)<br />

ŋugunda-ŋga ‘night-LOC’ (19)<br />

In Nyangumarta (Sharp 2004: 117), ergative is marked by -ju with c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-<br />

final stems and by -lu with vowel-final stems.<br />

184


(42) partany-ju ‘child-ERG’ ngagu-lu ‘1sg-ERG’<br />

wangal-ju ‘wind-ERG’ mirtawa-lu ‘woman-ERG’<br />

Minyjun-ju ‘(name)-ERG’ pirirri-lu ‘man-ERG’<br />

parirr-ju ‘hand-ERG’ Yinyjana-lu ‘(name)-ERG’<br />

Locative is marked in Nyangumarta by -jV with c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems and -ngV<br />

with vowel-final stems, where the vowel of the suffix assimilates to the final vowel of the<br />

stem (Sharp 2004: 118).<br />

(43) parirr-ji ‘hand-LOC’<br />

tili-ngi ‘flame-LOC’ mirtawa-nga ‘woman-LOC’<br />

karru-ngu ‘creek-LOC’<br />

In Kuuku Yaʔu (Thomps<strong>on</strong> 1976), ergative and instrumental are marked by -lu<br />

with c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems, and by -Vlu or -ʔV with vowel-final stems, where V is a copy<br />

of the stem-final vowel (the two suffix variants for vowel-final stems vary freely) (1976:<br />

329). Examples are shown below (Thomps<strong>on</strong> 1976: 329-331).<br />

(44) John-lu ‘John-ERG’<br />

piipi-ilu ~ piipi-ʔi ‘father-ERG’ mukana-ʔa ‘big-ERG’<br />

yuku-ulu ~ yuku-ʔu ‘tree-ERG’<br />

In Ngiyambaa (D<strong>on</strong>alds<strong>on</strong> 1980), allomorphy is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed not <strong>on</strong>ly by whether<br />

the stem ends in a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant or a vowel, but also by more specific features of the stem-<br />

final segment. Ngiyambaa has three primary ergative/instrumental allomorphs, -gu, -u,<br />

and -DHu (DH is a laminal stop archiph<strong>on</strong>eme), though D<strong>on</strong>alds<strong>on</strong> (1980: 83) reduces<br />

these to two underlying forms, /-gu/ and /-DHu/. The -gu allomorph occurs with vowel-<br />

final stems (including stems ending in VN). The -u allomorph occurs with stems ending<br />

in l or r. The -DHu allomorph occurs with other c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems. Examples are<br />

shown below (D<strong>on</strong>alds<strong>on</strong> 1980: 82).<br />

185


(45) mura-gu ‘spear-ERG’ miri-gu ‘dog-ERG’<br />

dhuruŋ-gu ‘snake-ERG’ dhuli:ŋ-gu ‘sand goanna-ERG’<br />

gaɽul-u ‘st<strong>on</strong>e-ERG’ mugar-u ‘prickle-ERG’<br />

gamugin-du ‘mosquito-ERG’<br />

bura:-dhu ‘child-ERG’ ŋurunh-dhu ‘emu-ERG’<br />

( < bura:y-) ( < ŋuruyN-)<br />

D<strong>on</strong>alds<strong>on</strong> formulates a morphoph<strong>on</strong>ological rule (1980: 50) deleting dh of a case marker<br />

after l or r, which allows the -u allomorph to be derived from /-DHu/. The motivati<strong>on</strong> for<br />

making this a general rule of the language is that two other cases, locative and<br />

circumstantive, exhibit similar patterns. Locative forms are identical to ergative forms<br />

except that they have a instead of u, as seen below (D<strong>on</strong>alds<strong>on</strong> 1980: 82).<br />

(46) a. mura-ga ‘spear-LOC’ miri-ga ‘dog-LOC’<br />

dhuruŋ-ga ‘snake-LOC’ dhuli:ŋ-ga ‘sand goanna-LOC’<br />

b. gaɽul-a ‘st<strong>on</strong>e-ERG’ mugar-a ‘prickle-LOC’<br />

c. gamugin-da ‘mosquito-LOC’<br />

bura:-dha ‘child-LOC’ ŋurunh-dha ‘emu-LOC’<br />

( < bura:y-) ( < NuruyN-)<br />

An interesting point to be made regarding this example is that in the forms bura:-dhu and<br />

bura:-dha in (45)c and (46)c, respectively, the stem-final /y/ that c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s the use of the<br />

-DHu suffix is absent in the surface form. Thus, this is an example in which a c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong><br />

<strong>on</strong> the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs is rendered opaque by a ph<strong>on</strong>ological process.<br />

Muruwari (Oates 1988) has three basic ergative/instrumental allomorphs (Oates<br />

1988: 56). The -ngku allomorph occurs with vowel/‘semivowel’-final stems. The -u<br />

allomorph occurs with stems ending in l or r. Finally, -tu/-thu/-tju occurs with stems<br />

ending in other c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants (the place of articulati<strong>on</strong> of the cor<strong>on</strong>al is determined by the<br />

stem-final c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant). Examples are given below (Oates 1988: 56, 58). 21<br />

21 Bidjara (Breen 1976a) exhibits a pattern of allomorphy that is similar to Muruwari in<br />

the locative and in the ‘operative’, which marks agents and instruments and corresp<strong>on</strong>ds<br />

in shape to PN ergative. According to Breen (1976a: 339), the operative is marked by -ŋu<br />

186


(47) kuthara-ngku ‘child-ERG’ kamay(i)-ngku ‘yam-INST’<br />

kula-ngku ‘kangaroo-ERG’ kuliya-ngku ‘spear-INST’<br />

kuntarl-u ‘dog-ERG’ kurlur-u ‘widow-ERG’<br />

muwarn-tu ‘younger brother-ERG’ kaan-tu ‘snake-ERG’<br />

wilanh-thu ‘sp. of cloud-ERG’ mayinj-tju ‘man-ERG’<br />

Locative exhibits the same pattern, except that the vowel of the suffix is a rather than u.<br />

Examples of the locative are shown below (Oates 1988: 59-63).<br />

(48) thuri-ngka ‘sun-LOC’ nhuu-ngka ‘this-LOC’<br />

partala-ngka ‘tomorrow-LOC’ paru-ngka ‘down-LOC’<br />

kuntarl-a ‘dog-LOC’ thinkal-a ‘knee-LOC’<br />

nhurran-ta ‘that-LOC’ karan-ta ‘across-LOC’<br />

kirin-tja ‘husband-LOC’ yurrin-tja ‘night-LOC’<br />

A slightly more complicated pattern is found in DuuNidjawu (Kite and Wurm<br />

2004), where the ergative/instrumental is marked by <strong>on</strong>e of -ndu, -ru, or -yu when the<br />

stem has a final short vowel ((49) a), by -wu when the stem has a final l<strong>on</strong>g vowel<br />

((49)b), by -Du when the stem ends in a nasal ((49)c), and by -u when the stem has any<br />

other c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant as its final segment ((49)d). Examples below are from Kite and Wurm<br />

2004: 28-29 (ergative examples) and 31 (instrumental examples).<br />

(49) a. badja-ru ‘other.<strong>on</strong>e-ERG’ bala-ru ‘jewfish-ERG’<br />

bebere-yu ‘uncle-ERG’ djuŋa-ndu ‘vine-INSTR’<br />

b. mama:-wu ‘uncle-ERG’<br />

c. baran-du ‘boomerang-ERG’ ŋuwim-bu ‘sun-ERG’<br />

d. guraŋgur-u ‘spear-INSTR’ gurruy-u ‘rain-INSTR’<br />

The locative allomorphs in DuuNidjawu are identical to the ergative except that<br />

the locative suffixes have a where ergative has u (Kite and Wurm 2004: 32). Some<br />

examples are given below (Kite and Wurm 2004: 32).<br />

with vowel-final stems, -d̪u with final ny (which becomes n5), and -u with other<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems. The locative is marked by -ŋa with vowel-final stems, -d̪a with<br />

final ny (which becomes n̪), and -a with other c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems. No examples are<br />

provided.<br />

187


(50) doyi-ya ‘rock-LOC’<br />

djuŋa-nda ‘vine-LOC’<br />

bayer-djin-da ‘mountain-PL-LOC’<br />

guyum-ba ‘camp-LOC’<br />

The ergative in Dja:bugay (Hale 1976a) has five allomorphs distributed according<br />

to the stem-final segment (1976: 321). The form -ŋgu is used with vowel-final stems, -du<br />

is used with n-final stems, -ndu is used with l-final stems, -u is used with r-final stems,<br />

and -njdju is used with y-final stems (which then lose their final y). Stems with surface<br />

final m pattern with vowel-final stems. Examples are shown below (Hale 1976a: 321).<br />

(51) gura:-ŋgu ‘dog-ERG’ gurina-ŋgu ‘porcupine-ERG’<br />

guyuru-ŋgu ‘wind-ERG’<br />

bigumu-ŋgu ‘fingernail-ERG’ (< bigum)<br />

djulbin-du ‘tree-ERG’ yaraman-du ‘horse-ERG’<br />

njiwul-ndu ‘<strong>on</strong>e-ERG’ dayal-ndu ‘boy-ERG’<br />

dugir-u ‘live-ERG’<br />

bibu:-njdju ‘small-ERG’ (< bibu:y)<br />

djaru-njdju ‘bird-ERG’ (< djaruy)<br />

The instrumental and locative in Dja:bugay are marked by <strong>on</strong>e of three<br />

allomorphs (Hale 1976a: 322). Bimoraic vowel-final stems have their final vowel<br />

lengthened. Vowel-final stems with three or more moras take -la. C<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems<br />

have instrumental/locative suffixes that are identical to the ergative except that the vowel<br />

is a: -da is used with n-final stems, -nda is used with l-final stems, -a is used with r-final<br />

stems, and -njdja is used with y-final stems (which then lose their final y). As with the<br />

ergative, m-final stems pattern with vowel-final stems. Examples are shown below (Hale<br />

1976a: 322).<br />

188


(52) a. bulmba-: ‘country-LOC’ bana-: ‘water-LOC’<br />

b. djina:-la ‘foot-LOC’ djumburu-la ‘road-LOC’<br />

c. djulbin-da ‘tree-LOC’ burŋan-da ‘ground-LOC’<br />

d. baNgal-nda ‘big-LOC’ waNal-nda ‘boomerang-LOC’<br />

e. dugir-a ‘live-LOC’<br />

f. mula-njdja ‘hole-LOC’ (< mulay)<br />

gimu-njdja ‘Cairns-LOC’ (< gimuy)<br />

As in the Ngiyambaa example discussed earlier in this secti<strong>on</strong>, Dja:bugay exhibits some<br />

opaque c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing in words with a /y/-final stem. As seen in the examples seen above<br />

in ((51)e) and ((52)f), stems with final /y/ take the ergative and locative suffixes -njdju<br />

and -njdja, respectively, but the stem-final /y/ is lost in the surface form. In a surface-<br />

based account of allomorphy (such as in a P >> M account), we would predict that these<br />

stems should pattern with vowel-final stems in terms of ergative and locative suffix<br />

allomorph selecti<strong>on</strong>, but as seen in these examples, this is not the case.<br />

In Wangkumara (Breen 1976b), allomorphy is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by both ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

and morphological factors. In this language, the ergative (or ‘operative’) has four primary<br />

allomorphs (1976b: 336-337) distributed based <strong>on</strong> both morphological and ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s (syllable count as well as the stem-final segment). The suffix -ulu is used with<br />

all masculine singular nouns, -anrru is used with n<strong>on</strong>-masculine-singular nouns having<br />

two syllables or final i or u, -nrru is used with n<strong>on</strong>-masculine-singular nouns of more<br />

than two syllables ending in a, and -ŋu is used with dual nouns. Examples are shown<br />

below (Breen 1976b: 337).<br />

(53) t̪it̪i-ulu ‘dog-ERG’ kat̪ikat̪i-ulu ‘snake-ERG’<br />

kugad̪ari-anrru ‘wind-ERG’ muku-anrru ‘b<strong>on</strong>e-ERG’<br />

makurra-nrru ‘tree-ERG’ ŋamadya-nrru ‘mother-ERG’<br />

t̪it̪i-ula-ŋu ‘dog-DUAL-ERG’<br />

Locative is marked in Wangkumara by two allomorphs whose distributi<strong>on</strong> is<br />

morphologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed (Breen 1976b: 337). The suffix -ŋala is used with dual<br />

189


nouns, and -laŋa is used with all other nouns. Examples are given below (Breen 1976b:<br />

337-338).<br />

(54) mirrulu-ŋala ‘Naryilco-LOC’ naka-laŋa ‘water-LOC’<br />

kukad̪iula-ŋala ‘btwn. the two hills-LOC’ murrkadya-laŋa<br />

‘younger brother- LOC’<br />

In some cases, allomorphy is semantically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed. For example, in Kuku<br />

Yalanji (Patz 2002), the distributi<strong>on</strong> of ergative allomorphs is both semantically and<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed. The suffixes -nkV and -VnkV are used with ‘potent’ stems<br />

that are vowel- or c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final, respectively ((55)a-b) (Patz 2002: 46). With ‘neutral’<br />

stems, -bu is used after vowel-final stems ((55)c), -Vbu after r-final stems ((55)d), -njV<br />

after y-final stems ((55)e), and -dV elsewhere ((55)f).<br />

(55) a. ngurrku-ngku ‘mopoke-ERG’<br />

kaya-ngka ‘dog-ERG’<br />

kami-ngka ‘father’s father / mother’s mother-ERG’<br />

b. ngangkin-angka ‘porcupine-ERG’<br />

dingkar-angka ‘man-ERG’<br />

walkarr-angka ‘black goanna-ERG’<br />

dubuy-ungku ‘small brown kingfisher (messenger bird)-ERG’<br />

wabul-ungku ‘Torres Strait Pige<strong>on</strong>-ERG’<br />

c. jna-bu ‘foot-ERG’<br />

kulji-bu ‘st<strong>on</strong>e-ERG’<br />

juku-bu ‘tree-ERG’<br />

d. wungar-abu ‘sun-ERG’<br />

badur-ubu ‘fishing line-ERG’<br />

e. balbay-nja ‘light, lightning-ERG’<br />

diliy-nja ‘corkwood pine-ERG’<br />

junjuy-nja ‘something-ERG’<br />

f. jalun-du ‘sea-ERG’<br />

jalbany-da ‘taboo food-ERG’<br />

bayil-da ‘freshwater perch-ERG’<br />

balarr-da ‘scabies-ERG’<br />

The locative in Kuku Yalanji also exhibits both ph<strong>on</strong>ologically and semantically<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy (Patz 2002: 48). Locative is marked by -ndV and -VndV with<br />

190


potent stems that are vowel- or c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final, respectively ((56)a-b). Am<strong>on</strong>g neutral<br />

stems, vowel-final stems take -ngV ((56)c), r-final stems take -V ((56)d), y-final stems<br />

take -mbV ((56)e), and all other stems take -bV ((56)f).<br />

(56) a. ngiwa-nda ‘salt-water eel-ERG’<br />

bulki-nda ‘cattle-ERG’<br />

dunyu-ndu ‘husband-ERG’<br />

b. mukay-anda ‘mother’s older sister,/ younger sister’s child-ERG’<br />

mukirr-anda ‘freshwater oyster-ERG’<br />

wuyngkul-undu ‘spirit of dying pers<strong>on</strong>-ERG’<br />

kukur-undu ‘rat-ERG’<br />

c. ngara-nga ‘roots-ERG’<br />

ngarri-nga ‘leg-ERG’<br />

kiju-ngu ‘mud crab-ERG’<br />

d. bibar-a ‘shin-ERG’<br />

burrir-a ‘island-ERG’<br />

bujur-u ‘feather-ERG’<br />

e. buray-mba ‘spring (water)-ERG’<br />

dajaliy-mba ‘deep water-ERG’<br />

wakuy-mbu ‘upper arm-ERG’<br />

f. nyabil-ba ‘t<strong>on</strong>gue-ERG’<br />

dalkan-ba ‘casuarina pine-ERG’<br />

diburr-bu ‘egg’<br />

The locative suffix allomorphs in Kuuku Yaʔu (Thomps<strong>on</strong> 1976) are also<br />

semantically distributed. The allomorph -lu (which can reduce to -l) is used with a<br />

‘dem<strong>on</strong>strative reference’, while -ŋuna ~ -Vla are used elsewhere (-ŋuna also has surface<br />

variants -ŋun and -ŋu; -Vla can reduce to -Vl). Examples are given below (Thomps<strong>on</strong><br />

1976: 329-331).<br />

(57) dinghy-lu ‘dinghy-LOC’ airstrip-ŋun ‘airstrip-LOC’<br />

kat̪aa-lu ‘dead-LOC’ kulamu-ŋun ‘road-LOC’<br />

There also exist languages in which the ergative and locative do not exhibit any<br />

allomorphy. For example, in Warluwara (Breen 1976c), ergative is always marked by the<br />

suffix -gu, and locative is always marked by -ga (1976c: 331-332). Examples are given<br />

below (1976c: 332-333).<br />

191


(58) bumad̪a-gu ‘sun-ERG’ wada-ga ‘st<strong>on</strong>e-LOC’<br />

yaŋad̪a-ra-gu ‘see-SUBJ-ERG’ wuŋaramba-ga ‘Carandotta-LOC’<br />

Similarly, in Go<strong>on</strong>iyandi (McGregor 1990), the ergative is marked invariably by<br />

the suffix -ngga (McGregor 1990: 177-178). This suffix can have both an ergative and an<br />

instrumental functi<strong>on</strong>, though McGregor explicitly rejects splitting it into two separate<br />

suffixes. Examples are shown below with page numbers from McGregor 1990.<br />

(59) yoowarni-ngga ‘<strong>on</strong>e-ERG’ (178) gambayi-ngga ‘boy-ERG’ (506)<br />

ngirndaji-ngga ‘this-ERG’ (588) niyi-ngga ‘that-ERG’ (586)<br />

The tables below summarize the cases described above. Table 1 shows languages<br />

exhibiting ergative allomorphy, and Table 2 shows languages exhibiting locative<br />

allomorphy (as seen above, some languages have both and are therefore listed in both<br />

tables).<br />

192


Table 1: Examples of ergative allomorphy<br />

Language Form Envir<strong>on</strong>ment Form Envir<strong>on</strong>ment<br />

Bidjara -d̪u ny-final stem -u other C-final stem<br />

-ŋu V-final stem<br />

Biri -ngu V-final stem<br />

-du C-final stem<br />

Diyari -ndu female pers<strong>on</strong>al name -li male pers<strong>on</strong>al name,<br />

a-final noun<br />

-yali other comm<strong>on</strong><br />

noun<br />

Dja:bugay -ŋgu V-final stem -u r-final stem<br />

-du n-final stem<br />

-ndu l-final stem<br />

-njdju y-final stem<br />

Dyirbal -ŋgu disyllabic stem<br />

-gu trisyllabic+ stem<br />

Duuŋidjawu -ndu/-ru/-yu stem w/final short V -wu stem w/final l<strong>on</strong>g V<br />

-Du nasal-final stem -u stem w/other final C<br />

Go<strong>on</strong>iyandi -ŋgga all envir<strong>on</strong>ments<br />

Kaititj -ŋ disyllabic stem -l trisyllabic+ stem<br />

Kuku Yalanji -ŋkV potent referent<br />

-dV neutral referent<br />

Kuuku Yaʔu -Vlu/-/V V-final stem -lu C-final stem<br />

Muruwari -ngku V-final stem -u l- or r-final stem<br />

-tu stem w/other final C<br />

Ngiyambaa -DHu V-final stem -u l- or r-final stem<br />

-gu stem w/other final C<br />

Nhanda -(ng)gu bimoraic stem -lu stem with 3+ moras<br />

Nyangumarta -ju C-final stem -lu V-final stem<br />

Wangkumara -ŋu dual stem -ulu masc. singular stem<br />

-anrru n<strong>on</strong>-masc.-sg. w/2<br />

syllables or final<br />

i or u<br />

-nrru n<strong>on</strong>-masc.-sg. w/3+<br />

syllables and final a<br />

Warlpiri -ŋku noun stem with -rlu stem with 3+ moras<br />

2 moras or n<strong>on</strong>-noun stem<br />

Warluwara -gu all envir<strong>on</strong>ments<br />

Warrgamay -ŋgu V-final stem -du C-final stem<br />

Yidiɲ -ŋgu V-final stem -du C-final stem<br />

Yingkarta -ngku V-final stem w/2 moras -lu V-final stem w/3+<br />

-Su C-final stem moras<br />

193


Table 2: Examples of locative allomorphy<br />

Language Form Envir<strong>on</strong>ment Form Envir<strong>on</strong>ment<br />

Bidjara -d̪a ny-final stem -a other C-final stem<br />

-ŋa V-final stem<br />

Biri -nga V-final stem<br />

-da C-final stem<br />

Dja:bugay -: V-final stem w/2 moras -la V-final stem w/3+<br />

-da n-final stem moras or r-final<br />

-nda l-final stem stem<br />

-njdja y-final stem<br />

Duuŋidjawu -nda/-ra/-ya stemw/final l<strong>on</strong>g V -wa stem w/final l<strong>on</strong>g V<br />

-Da nasal-final stem -a stemw/other final C<br />

Kaititj -ŋ disyllabic stem -l trisyllabic+ stem<br />

Kuku Yalanji -ndV potent referent<br />

-ŋV neutral referent<br />

Kuuku Yaʔu -ŋunaʔ-Vla n<strong>on</strong>-dem<strong>on</strong>strative -lu dem<strong>on</strong>strative<br />

Martuthunira -ngka V-final stem with -la V-final stem with<br />

2 moras 3+ moras<br />

Muruwari -ngka V-final stem -a l- or r-final stem<br />

-ta stem w/other final C<br />

Ngiyambaa -DHa V-final stem -a l- or r-final stem<br />

-ga stem w/other final C<br />

Nhanda -(ng)gu all envir<strong>on</strong>ments<br />

Nyangumarta -ngV V-final stem<br />

-jV C-final stem<br />

Wangkumara -ŋala dual stem -laŋa any other stem<br />

Warlpiri -ŋka noun stem with -rla stem with 3+ moras<br />

2 moras or n<strong>on</strong>-noun stem<br />

Warluwara -ga all envir<strong>on</strong>ments<br />

Yidiɲ -da C-final stem -la V-final stem<br />

Yindjibarndi -ŋka V-final stem with -la C-final stem or stem<br />


Figure 2: Map showing distributi<strong>on</strong> of c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> ergative allomorphy<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>C<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> determining allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong><br />

syllable count semantic mora count lexical<br />

V- vs. C-final final segment feature no allomorphy other/multiple<br />

Map outline © 2006 Comm<strong>on</strong>wealth of Australia (Geoscience Australia).<br />

Used with permissi<strong>on</strong>.<br />

As can be seen from the map above, some generalizati<strong>on</strong>s can be made regarding<br />

the geographical ranges of the different types of c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong>. For<br />

example, in this sample, mora count-based allomorphy occurs primarily <strong>on</strong> Australia’s<br />

west coast, although <strong>on</strong>e example is found in central Australia. On the other hand,<br />

allomorphy based <strong>on</strong> features of the stem-final segment seems to be limited to eastern<br />

Australia. Semantically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy occurs in both the south central regi<strong>on</strong><br />

and in the northeast. Syllable count-based allomorphy occurs in the central and eastern<br />

195


egi<strong>on</strong>s. Finally, allomorphy determined by whether the stem is c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant- or vowel-final<br />

appears to be widely distributed, occurring in the eastern, central, and western regi<strong>on</strong>s.<br />

In the following secti<strong>on</strong>, I discuss some previous approaches to PN ergative<br />

allomorphy, then propose an account for the development of the phenomen<strong>on</strong> based <strong>on</strong><br />

the earlier studies and c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong> of the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphy patterns in modern<br />

PN languages.<br />

4.2.2 Previous discussi<strong>on</strong>s<br />

The historical development of Pama-Nyungan ergative allomorphy has been<br />

discussed in at least three previous studies. The first of these is Hale (1976b). Hale’s<br />

proposal for the development of ergative allomorphy can be summarized as follows.<br />

First, Hale narrows the discussi<strong>on</strong> to the alternant set in (60)a and the ‘extremely<br />

comm<strong>on</strong>’ ergative/locative allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong> pattern shown in (60)b (Hale 1976b:<br />

414; S = a stop homorganic to the preceding c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant).<br />

(60) a. ergative locative<br />

*-lu *-la<br />

*-ŋku *-ŋka<br />

*-mpu *-mpa<br />

*-njtju *-njtja<br />

b. (i) *-ŋku, *-ŋka attach to vowel-final disyllabic stems;<br />

(ii) *-lu, *-la attach to vowel-final polysyllabic stems;<br />

(iii) *-Su, *-Sa attach to c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final stems<br />

Hale assumes (1976b: 414) that the basic forms of the ergative and locative were *-lu and<br />

*-la, respectively. To collapse categories (ii) and (iii) in (1) above, Hale proposes an<br />

assimilati<strong>on</strong> rule changing l into a stop with place features determined by an immediately<br />

preceding c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant across a morpheme boundary (1976b: 415). Hale’s analysis centers<br />

196


around the observati<strong>on</strong> (1976b: 415) that there is a range of allowable stem-final<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants in Australian languages, such that some languages allow no final c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants,<br />

some allow apicals <strong>on</strong>ly, some allow cor<strong>on</strong>als, and some allow both cor<strong>on</strong>als and n<strong>on</strong>-<br />

cor<strong>on</strong>als. In a language that allowed stem-final cor<strong>on</strong>als and n<strong>on</strong>-cor<strong>on</strong>als and had the l-<br />

assimilati<strong>on</strong> rule described above, the ergative forms corresp<strong>on</strong>ding to a CVCVm and<br />

CVCVŋ stem would have been CVCVmpu and CVCVŋku, respectively. Now suppose<br />

that this language lost all of its n<strong>on</strong>-cor<strong>on</strong>al stem-final c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants at some later stage in<br />

its history. This would mean that both stems had the form CVCV, but their ergative<br />

forms would still have had the forms CVCVmpu and CVCVŋku (this leaves open the<br />

questi<strong>on</strong> of whether the same change applied to other suffixes in the language; the<br />

parallel patterning of locative allomorphy with ergative allomorphy in many PN<br />

languages suggests that the locative underwent the same changes as the ergative, though<br />

there are other possible sources for this similarity (e.g., the initial c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant of the<br />

ergative and locative could be a stem former rather than being part of the case suffixes)).<br />

Some reanalysis could have taken place such that the ergative stem was the same as the<br />

plain stem (CVCV) and the ergative suffix was reanalyzed as -mpu ~ -ŋku. This would<br />

yield a system with four ergative allomorphs, where cor<strong>on</strong>al-final stems take -Su, and V-<br />

final stems take lexically determined allomorphs: -lu ~ -mpu ~ -ŋku. Some semantic or<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> could then develop to account for the distributi<strong>on</strong> of these<br />

allomorphs. Languages that also exhibit *-njtju can be accounted for under this scenario<br />

if the rule deleting n<strong>on</strong>-cor<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants is expanded to delete all distributed<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants, which would then include tj.<br />

197


To account for languages that mark disyllabic stems with *-ŋku and stems with<br />

three or more syllables (‘polysyllabics’) with *-lu, Hale points out (1976b: 416) that<br />

many languages, including some Australian languages (Uradhi, Wik Me’nh, and Arandic<br />

Anmatjera) have a rule that Hale terms ‘velar-posthesis’, which inserts ŋ after a word-<br />

final vowel. There is no obvious ph<strong>on</strong>etic motivati<strong>on</strong> for such a rule, but it does recur in<br />

many different languages (Hale 1976b). In Arandic Anmatjera, this rule is limited to<br />

disyllabic words, and Hale proposes that this form of the rule was present in the mother<br />

language to the languages exhibiting the *-ŋku ~ *-lu allomorphy in disyllables vs.<br />

polysyllables. Hale proposes further that the stems undergoing ŋ-inserti<strong>on</strong> were<br />

reanalyzed as having underlying final ŋ by analogy with other ŋ-final stems since these<br />

two types of stems would have had the same shape in their citati<strong>on</strong> forms due to the<br />

applicati<strong>on</strong> of velar posthesis; this would have resulted in a disproporti<strong>on</strong>ately large<br />

number of ŋ-final disyllabic stems. Dix<strong>on</strong> (1980: 211) reports that this has happened<br />

‘over a wide area in the south-east,’ citing Muk-Thang of Gippsland, where ‘almost all<br />

disyllabic roots end in a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant, with the most comm<strong>on</strong> final segment being /ŋ/;<br />

am<strong>on</strong>gst m<strong>on</strong>osyllables and trisyllabics there are more final vowels’. Since vowel-final<br />

polysyllables would not have underg<strong>on</strong>e velar posthesis, they would still have had -lu as<br />

their ergative allomorph, whereas disyllabic stems would all take -Su due to the rule<br />

changing l to a stop homorganic to a previous c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant. If this language then underwent<br />

deleti<strong>on</strong> of final c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants (a relatively comm<strong>on</strong> process that may result from the loss of<br />

acoustic cues to the c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant when no vowel follows), the ergative suffix could have<br />

been reanalyzed as -ŋku for all of the stems that previously had final ŋ (either<br />

etymologically or via velar posthesis). Most of these stems would have been disyllabic,<br />

198


since all of the <strong>on</strong>es that got final ŋ through velar posthesis would be disyllabic, plus<br />

many of the stems with etymological final ŋ would already have been disyllabic as well.<br />

If a very high percentage of ŋ-final stems were disyllabic (in c<strong>on</strong>trast to stems ending in<br />

other segments, which would have had a lower percentage of disyllabic stems), this<br />

pattern could have been interpreted such that all disyllabic stems took -ŋku, while<br />

polysyllabic stems took -lu. In Table 3 below, I summarize Hale’s proposed sequence of<br />

changes leading to syllable counting allomorphy involving -ŋku vs. -lu.<br />

Table 3: Hale’s (1976b) proposed history of PN ergative/locative allomorphy<br />

Stage I: Ergative/locative is /-lu/; l → S / C + __ (where C is any c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant, + is a<br />

morpheme boundary, and S is a stop at the same place of articulati<strong>on</strong> as<br />

C); velar posthesis inserts ŋ after every V-final disyllabic stem.<br />

Stage II: CVCV stems are reanalyzed as CVCVŋ, yielding a disproporti<strong>on</strong>ately<br />

high number of disyllabic stems ending in ŋ; ergative forms of these stems<br />

change from CVCV-lu to CVCVN-ku (by l-assimilati<strong>on</strong>).<br />

Stage III: Final c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants are lost; former CVCVC stems are now CVCV, but their<br />

ergative forms are still CVCVCSu, reanalyzed as CVCV-CSu. Multiple<br />

primary ergative allomorphs now exist: -lu for stems that were always Vfinal<br />

(n<strong>on</strong>-disyllabic stems <strong>on</strong>ly) and multiple different -SCu forms (-ŋgu,<br />

-mpu, -njtju) for stems formerly ending in c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants (the largest class of<br />

these likely being ŋ-final since this class would include stems with<br />

etymological final ŋ as well as final ŋ from velar posthesis).<br />

Stage IV: Since all stems taking -lu are n<strong>on</strong>-disyllabic and most stems taking -ŋku<br />

are disyllabic, the ergative allomorphy is reanalyzed as follows: disyllabic<br />

stems take -ŋku; other stems take -lu.<br />

A sec<strong>on</strong>d source that discusses the development of ergative/locative/instrumental<br />

allomorphy is Dix<strong>on</strong> (1980). 22 Dix<strong>on</strong> rejects Pama-Nyungan as a genetic group, but<br />

rec<strong>on</strong>structs Proto-Australian ergative allomorphs that could also be interpreted as Pama-<br />

22 See also Dix<strong>on</strong> 2002, which includes further discussi<strong>on</strong> of some issues presented here<br />

but leaves out some data that were included in Dix<strong>on</strong> 1980. For that reas<strong>on</strong> I cite Dix<strong>on</strong><br />

1980 throughout the remainder of this secti<strong>on</strong>.<br />

199


Nyungan. In fact, as Sands (1996) points out, Dix<strong>on</strong>’s proposed Proto-Australian ergative<br />

marker is based <strong>on</strong> evidence from Pama-Nyungan. Dix<strong>on</strong> rec<strong>on</strong>structs the following<br />

allomorphs for Proto-Australian (S is a stop homorganic to the preceding stop; DH is a<br />

laminal stop).<br />

(61) -Su after nasals<br />

-DHu after y<br />

-du after l, rr<br />

-lu after vowels when root has 3+ syllables<br />

-ŋgu after vowels when root has 2 syllables<br />

Dix<strong>on</strong> accepts as plausible Hale’s (1976b) proposal that all of these allomorphs arose<br />

from *-lu via the series of changes described above in the discussi<strong>on</strong> of Hale’s analysis.<br />

Dix<strong>on</strong>’s proposal is therefore basically the same as Hale’s proposal, except that Dix<strong>on</strong><br />

claims that his rec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> holds for the ancestor of all of the Australian languages<br />

rather than just the Pama-Nyungan languages.<br />

Sands (1996) argues for a different rec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of the ergative in Pama-<br />

Nyungan. Sands claims that Pama-Nyungan had three ergative allomorphs as follows<br />

(1996: 8).<br />

(62) *-lu / V_ nominals which are not comm<strong>on</strong> nouns<br />

*-ŋgu / V_ 2 syllables<br />

*-DHu / elsewhere<br />

Sands claims further that an ergative suffix *-DHu can be rec<strong>on</strong>structed for Proto-<br />

Australian, though the evidence for this claim is weaker than that for the proposed Pama-<br />

Nyungan ergative rec<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>. Hale’s (1976b) scenario for the development of *-ŋgu<br />

from *-lu is not disputed, but Sands argues (1996: 11) that *-ŋgu must already have been<br />

restricted to occuring with disyllabic stems in Pama-Nyungan since the syllable count-<br />

based distributi<strong>on</strong> occurs across a wide geographical area in Sands’ survey. Although<br />

200


Sands includes more languages than the present survey, it should be pointed out that at<br />

least four of the ten western Australian languages that Sands cites (1996: 9) as having<br />

syllable count-based allomorphy (Martuthunira, Nhanda, Yindjibarndi, and Yingkarta,<br />

each discussed above) are more accurately described as having mora count-based<br />

allomorphy. Therefore, Sands’ proposal may need to be modified to state that PN had<br />

ergative allomorphy based <strong>on</strong> mora count rather than syllable count. The argument for the<br />

*-DHu allomorph is based both <strong>on</strong> the comm<strong>on</strong> occurrence of laminal-initial allomorphs<br />

across the Pama-Nyungan area and the fact that *-DHu is also plausible for some n<strong>on</strong>-<br />

Pama-Nyungan languages. Note that the latter argument applies <strong>on</strong>ly if <strong>on</strong>e accepts the<br />

claim that the Pama-Nyungan languages form a larger Australian group with the n<strong>on</strong>-<br />

Pama-Nyungan languages. This is a c<strong>on</strong>troversial claim that has not been substantiated to<br />

the satisfacti<strong>on</strong> of researchers in the field, with the notable excepti<strong>on</strong> of R.M.W. Dix<strong>on</strong>,<br />

who has argued for the existence of an Australian group and for the n<strong>on</strong>-existence of<br />

Pama-Nyungan. Despite the questi<strong>on</strong> of whether it is desirable to rec<strong>on</strong>struct a Pama-<br />

Nyungan ergative suffix by taking the n<strong>on</strong>-Pama-Nyungan languages into c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>,<br />

I n<strong>on</strong>etheless do not find evidence in the present survey to c<strong>on</strong>tradict *-DHu as opposed<br />

to an alveolar-initial suffix.<br />

4.2.3 A history of PN ergative allomorphy<br />

Each of the previous studies of the history of PN ergative allomorphy assumes<br />

that both *-lu and *-ŋgu were present in the comm<strong>on</strong> ancestral language of modern PN<br />

languages (though as discussed above, Dix<strong>on</strong> (1980) denies the existence of PN and<br />

instead rec<strong>on</strong>structs these allomorphs for Australian). Under Hale’s (1976b) and Dix<strong>on</strong>’s<br />

201


(1980) proposals, this allomorphy could have been derived by rule from a single<br />

underlying form, /-lu/. Under Sands’ (1996) account, <strong>on</strong> the other hand, the allomorphs<br />

were already in a suppletive relati<strong>on</strong>ship in Proto-PN. Sands’ justificati<strong>on</strong> for this<br />

assumpti<strong>on</strong> (1996: 7-8) is that there are several modern PN languages where -lu occurs<br />

with proper nouns (Sands 1996: 14-15): Yankunytjatjara, Badimaya, Yindjibarndi,<br />

Atynyamathanha, and Watjarri. However, a problem with this assumpti<strong>on</strong> is that<br />

according to Ethnologue all five of these languages are classified as South-West Pama-<br />

Nyungan languages (Gord<strong>on</strong> 2005). 23 Therefore, the use of -lu with proper nouns may be<br />

better analyzed as an innovati<strong>on</strong> in South-West Pama-Nyungan than as a feature of Proto-<br />

PN. I will assume, following Hale (1976b) and Dix<strong>on</strong> (1980) that the Proto-PN ergative<br />

suffix had a single underlying form.<br />

As menti<strong>on</strong>ed above, Sands (1996) makes a good case for rec<strong>on</strong>structing a<br />

laminal as the initial segment of the ergative suffix (*-DHu), though she does not analyze<br />

-lu as being a reflex of this suffix. I propose that the Proto-PN ergative suffix allomorphs<br />

were derived from <strong>on</strong>e underlying form and two (synchr<strong>on</strong>ic) ph<strong>on</strong>ological rules, as<br />

follows:<br />

23 More specifically, according to Ethnologue (Gord<strong>on</strong> 2005), Yankunytjatjara is Wati<br />

language, Atynyamathanha is a Yura language, Yindjibarndi is a Coastal Ngayarda<br />

language, Badimaya and Watjarri are Watjarri langauges; all of these are grouped<br />

together in the Ethnologue as South-West Pama-Nyungan. But it should be<br />

acknowledged that according to Claire Bowern (p.c.), this classificati<strong>on</strong> is disputed<br />

am<strong>on</strong>g some researchers, publicly if not in print.<br />

202


(63) Underlying form: /-DHu/<br />

Place Assimilati<strong>on</strong>: C + C V<br />

erg<br />

=<br />

Place Place<br />

[Laminal]<br />

Leniti<strong>on</strong>: V + C V<br />

erg<br />

= =<br />

Place<br />

[-c<strong>on</strong>t]<br />

[Laminal]<br />

Though the Leniti<strong>on</strong> rule may cause c<strong>on</strong>cern since it involves, in effect, two separate<br />

delinking processes (in additi<strong>on</strong> to the later default inserti<strong>on</strong> of [Alveolar] and [+c<strong>on</strong>t],<br />

which I assume), this is n<strong>on</strong>etheless not an unnatural rule. It may be thought of as a<br />

general process of reducti<strong>on</strong>, which happens to delete both the place and manner features<br />

of the c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant between two vowels.<br />

The proposed underlying form and ph<strong>on</strong>ological rules can account for Dix<strong>on</strong>’s<br />

(1980) allomorphs as follows:<br />

(64) Dix<strong>on</strong> (1980) allomorph Rule(s)<br />

-Su after nasals Place Assimilati<strong>on</strong><br />

-DHu after y Place Assimilati<strong>on</strong><br />

-du after l, rr Place Assimilati<strong>on</strong><br />

-lu after vowels when root has 3+ syllables Leniti<strong>on</strong>; see below<br />

-ŋgu after vowels when root has 2 syllables Place assimilati<strong>on</strong>; see below<br />

A few further comments are necessary to explain how this proposal accounts for the<br />

allomorphs identified by Dix<strong>on</strong> (1980). Although Dix<strong>on</strong> rec<strong>on</strong>structs the -lu allomorph as<br />

occurring after vowels when the root has 3+ syllables and -ŋgu after vowels when the<br />

root has two syllables, we can assume given Hale’s explanati<strong>on</strong> of the origin of -ŋgu that<br />

Proto-PN had <strong>on</strong>ly -lu after vowels, and that -ŋgu arose later in some languages where<br />

203


final ŋ was lost, according to Hale’s (1976b) scenario. 24 Given what was said above<br />

regarding the wide distributi<strong>on</strong> of -ŋgu vs. -lu for bimoraic vs. larger stems, I hypothesize<br />

that this was the basis for distributi<strong>on</strong> in the first language/group to develop -ŋgu, and<br />

that this underwent later changes in some languages to distributi<strong>on</strong>s based <strong>on</strong> syllable<br />

count, c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant- vs. vowel-final stem, semantic distincti<strong>on</strong>s, etc., as are found in<br />

modern PN languages. I assume, therefore, that Hale’s (1976b) proposed rule of velar<br />

posthesis actually applied to bimoraic stems, rather than to disyllabic stems.<br />

If this scenario is correct, then it need not be assumed that PN ergative<br />

allomorphy exists for the purpose of ph<strong>on</strong>ological optimizati<strong>on</strong>. Rather, as can be seen in<br />

the above discussi<strong>on</strong>, the modern patterns of PN ergative allomorphy arose via a complex<br />

series of ph<strong>on</strong>ological changes, each of which was independently motivated, but not<br />

necessarily for reas<strong>on</strong>s of optimizati<strong>on</strong> 25 (in fact, in the case of velar posthesis, it is<br />

difficult to imagine a ph<strong>on</strong>etic or ph<strong>on</strong>ological motivati<strong>on</strong>, 26 though Hale (1976b) and<br />

Dix<strong>on</strong> (1980) cite enough examples of the rule to justify the assumpti<strong>on</strong> that it is<br />

plausible and could have existed in Proto-PN). The purpose of this secti<strong>on</strong> has been to<br />

show that PN ergative allomorphy could have developed for other reas<strong>on</strong>s than<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological optimizati<strong>on</strong>. Having d<strong>on</strong>e this, I now move to an analysis of the general<br />

phenomen<strong>on</strong> of prosodically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy.<br />

24 This has the advantage of accounting for languages that never have -ŋgu postvocalically.<br />

Sands (1996: 13-14) lists 15 such languages.<br />

25 It could be argued that analogy is optimizing, since its overall effect can be to simplify<br />

the grammar. However, this would be a different kind of ‘optimizati<strong>on</strong>’ from the<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological optimizati<strong>on</strong> of words, which is the type of optimizati<strong>on</strong> that I am talking<br />

about here and the type that the P >> M model is meant to capture.<br />

26 Of course there must have been some motivati<strong>on</strong> for the process, but it was probably<br />

something external to the ph<strong>on</strong>ological system itself (e.g., analogy, borrowing, or perhaps<br />

some acoustic or articulatory factor not yet identified).<br />

204


4.3 Analysis of prosodically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy<br />

The apparent optimizing nature of Pama-Nyungan ergative allomorphy has been<br />

explained based <strong>on</strong> its historical origins in §4.2, and the majority of the remaining cases<br />

of syllable and mora count-based allomorphy are not ph<strong>on</strong>ologically optimizing. In this<br />

secti<strong>on</strong>, I c<strong>on</strong>trast two approaches to the phenomen<strong>on</strong> as they apply to prosodically<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy. The first is the Output Optimizati<strong>on</strong> approach, which<br />

was applied specifically to cases of ‘syllable-counting allomorphy’ (SCA) by Kager<br />

(1996). The sec<strong>on</strong>d approach, which I argue to be superior, is a subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

approach. As I will show, subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> is capable of handling both optimizing and<br />

n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing allomorphy, and it does a much better job of handling the n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing<br />

cases.<br />

4.3.1 The Output Optimizati<strong>on</strong> approach<br />

Kager (1996: 170) claims that ‘[s]yllable-counting allomorphy is an output-<br />

oriented phenomen<strong>on</strong>,’ resulting from the Emergence of the Unmarked (TETU;<br />

McCarthy and Prince 1994). In this approach, the morphology supplies multiple<br />

suppletive allomorphs of an affix in candidates in an OT tableau, and ph<strong>on</strong>ological foot<br />

structure and parsing c<strong>on</strong>straints select the appropriate output. This approach falls under<br />

McCarthy and Prince’s (1993a,b) ‘P >> M’ ranking schema, where ph<strong>on</strong>ological effects<br />

in morphology are modeled by ranking ph<strong>on</strong>ological (P) over morphological (M)<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straints. In ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy (PCSA), the relevant M<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straint is <strong>on</strong>e enforcing uniform marking of morphological categories. One predicti<strong>on</strong><br />

205


of this approach is that syllable-counting allomorphy should serve to optimize words with<br />

respect to ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints that are independently motivated elsewhere in<br />

Universal Grammar.<br />

Kager’s argument is based <strong>on</strong> Est<strong>on</strong>ian, where the Genitive plural, Partitive<br />

singular, and Partitive plural exhibit SCA, as seen below (examples below with page<br />

numbers in parentheses are from Mürk 1997, and the remaining examples are from Kager<br />

1996: 157, 168; this is reproduced from (4) above).<br />

(65) Genitive plural Partitive plural Partitive singular Gloss<br />

maa:-te (74) ma-it (74) maa:-t ‘land’<br />

aas:ta-tte (149) aas:ta-it (149) aas:ta-tt ‘year’<br />

häda-te (77) häda-sit (77) häda-Ø (77) ‘trouble’<br />

paraja-tte paraja-it paraja-tt ‘suitable’<br />

raamattu-tte raamaattu-it raamattu-tt ‘book’<br />

atmirali-te atmirali-sit atmirali-Ø ‘admiral’<br />

telef<strong>on</strong>i-te telef<strong>on</strong>i-sit telef<strong>on</strong>i-Ø ‘teleph<strong>on</strong>e’<br />

Kager claims that these apparent syllable counting effects in Est<strong>on</strong>ian result from<br />

foot parsing c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s rather than from true ‘counting’. Kager proposes (1996: 162-<br />

163) the following c<strong>on</strong>straints for Est<strong>on</strong>ian:<br />

(66) FT-BIN: Feet are binary under syllabic or moraic analysis.<br />

PARSE-2: One of two adjacent stress units (μ, σ) must be parsed by a foot.<br />

ALIGN-HD-L: Align (PrWd, L, Head(PrWd), L)<br />

ONSET: Syllables must have <strong>on</strong>sets.<br />

ALIGN-ST-R: Align (Stem, R, Foot, R) (Each right stem edge coincides with a<br />

right foot edge)<br />

PK-PROM: Peak(x) > Peak(y) if |x| > |y|.<br />

The correct genitive plural allomorphs for even-syllable (67)a and odd-syllable (67)b<br />

stems are selected via the following c<strong>on</strong>straint rankings (Kager 1996: 164-167).<br />

(67) Genitive plural<br />

a. /visa, {-te, -tte}/ FT-BIN PARSE-2 ALIGN-HD-L ONSET ALIGN-ST-R PK-PROM<br />

[(ví.sa)-te] L<br />

[(ví.sa-t).te] *! L<br />

[vi.(sá-t.te)] *! * H<br />

[(ví).(sà-t.te)] *! * L, H<br />

206


. /paraja, {-te, -tte}/ FT-BIN PARSE-2 ALIGN-HD-L ONSET ALIGN-ST-R PK-PROM<br />

[(pá.ra).(jà-t.te)] * L, H<br />

[(pá.ra).(jà-te)] * L, L!<br />

[pa.(rá.ja)-te] *! L<br />

[(pá.ra).ja-te)] *! * L<br />

[(pá.ra).(jà)-te] *! L, L<br />

[(pá.ra.ja)-te)] *! L<br />

Similarly, the partitive plural allomorphs for even-syllable (68)a and odd-syllable (68)b<br />

stems are selected as shown below (Kager 1996: 164-167).<br />

(68) Partitive plural<br />

a. /visa, {-sit, -it}/ FT-BIN PARSE-2 ALIGN-HD-L ONSET ALIGN-ST-R PK-PROM<br />

[(ví.sa)-sit] L<br />

[(ví.sa-i)t] *! L<br />

[(ví.sa).-it] *! L<br />

[vi.(sá-i)t] *! * H<br />

[(ví).(sà-i)t] *! * L, H<br />

b. /paraja, {-sit, -it}/ FT-BIN PARSE-2 ALIGN-HD-L ONSET ALIGN-ST-R PK-PROM<br />

[(pá.ra).(jà-i)t] * L, H<br />

[(pá.ra).(jà-si)t] * L, L!<br />

[(pá.ra).(jà-.i)t] *! * L, L<br />

[pa.(rá.ja)-sit] *! L<br />

[(pá.ra).ja-sit)] *! * L<br />

[(pá.ra).ja-it)] *! * L<br />

[(pá).(rà.ja)-sit] *! L, L<br />

[(pá.ra).(jà)-sit] *! L, L<br />

This type of analysis works for Est<strong>on</strong>ian, but we are left with the questi<strong>on</strong> of whether<br />

SCA is always reducible to general markedness and faithfulness, as Kager claims. In the<br />

following secti<strong>on</strong>, I address this questi<strong>on</strong> with reference to the other cases of syllable<br />

count-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy described in §4.1 and §4.2.<br />

4.3.2 Survey results revisited<br />

As described above, this survey uncovered many cases of SCA in which the<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs is not predictable from their shape and must be stipulated; this<br />

in itself is an important result since it c<strong>on</strong>tradicts Kager’s claim that SCA is optimizing.<br />

207


In some cases of SCA, the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs does relate to their shape. However,<br />

in some of these cases, the ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints that would be needed to model the<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong> are very specific c<strong>on</strong>straints that cannot be assumed to be part of UG, and<br />

therefore these cases still cannot be analyzed as TETU effects.<br />

For example, recall that in Kimatuumbi (Odden 1996), m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic verbs mark<br />

perfective with -i̹te, while polysyllabic stems take an -i̹- infix (Odden 1996: 51-53). The<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong> could be c<strong>on</strong>strued as resp<strong>on</strong>ding to a requirement that perfective forms have<br />

four syllables, though this is not surface-true due to some systematic excepti<strong>on</strong>s. But note<br />

that if this were captured using a ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint, it would be language-specific,<br />

not part of UG. Therefore, Kimatuumbi perfective allomorphy is not a TETU effect.<br />

4.3.3 Examples of n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing SCA<br />

As menti<strong>on</strong>ed above, this survey revealed several examples of n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing<br />

SCA. An example is found in Tzeltal (Walsh Dickey 1999), described above in §4.1,<br />

where the perfective is marked by -oh with m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic stems, and with -ɛh elsewhere.<br />

[o] and [ɛ] do not alternate elsewhere (Kaufman 1971: 28), so the allomorphy is probably<br />

truly suppletive. Stress in Tzeltal is word-final (Walsh Dickey 1999: 327), so the<br />

allomorphy is not stress-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed. A c<strong>on</strong>straint banning [ɛ] in the sec<strong>on</strong>d syllable has<br />

not been proposed for UG, so this is not a TETU effect. Such a c<strong>on</strong>straint in Tzeltal<br />

would be stipulative and used <strong>on</strong>ly for this phenomen<strong>on</strong>, so this appears to be a case<br />

where we would not want to describe the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs as ph<strong>on</strong>ologically<br />

optimizing in any way.<br />

208


Another such case is seen in Kaititj (Koch 1980), discussed above in §4.2. In this<br />

language, the -ŋ form of the ergative/instrumental/locative suffix occurs with disyllabic<br />

stems, while -l occurs with larger stems (examples are from Koch 1980: 264-266). Note<br />

that in these examples, /l/ → [ŋ] when the preceding c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant is apical (Koch 1980:<br />

274), and N is a prestopped apical nasal.<br />

(8) aˈki-ŋ ‘head-ERG’ aˈliki-l ‘dog-ERG’<br />

ilˈt y i-ŋ ‘hand-ERG’ aˈʈuyi-l ‘man-ERG’<br />

aNˈmi-ŋ ‘red ochre-ERG’ aˈɣirki-l ‘sun-ERG’<br />

aynˈpi-ŋ ‘pouch-ERG’ ˈɭuNpiri-ɭ ‘forehead-ERG’<br />

There does not seem to be anything ‘better’ about /ŋ/ rather than /l/ as a stressed syllable<br />

or sec<strong>on</strong>d syllable coda, so this seems <strong>on</strong>ce again to be a case of n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing SCA.<br />

A third example is found in Zuni (Newman 1965). As discussed above, in Zuni,<br />

singular nouns are marked with -ʔleʔ for m<strong>on</strong>osyllabic stems, and with -nne for<br />

polysyllabic stems. Again, there is nothing to suggest that the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs<br />

is ph<strong>on</strong>ologically optimizing.<br />

Finally, a fourth example of n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing SCA is seen in Dyirbal. As discussed<br />

in §4.2, in vowel-final stems in Dyirbal, disyllabic stems mark ergative with -ŋgu, while<br />

l<strong>on</strong>ger stems take -gu. McCarthy and Prince (1990) characterize this as a ‘compensatory<br />

relati<strong>on</strong>ship’ in that the ‘shorter’ suffix goes with the ‘l<strong>on</strong>ger’ stem and vice versa.<br />

McCarthy and Prince acknowledge that coda c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants are not generally c<strong>on</strong>sidered to<br />

be moraic in Dyirbal, but <strong>on</strong>e would have to assume that codas are moraic, at least in this<br />

c<strong>on</strong>text, to give substance to the claim that the allomorphy is motivated by compensati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

However, if the noti<strong>on</strong> of a closed syllable does have some status in the language, then if<br />

209


anything, we would expect the exact opposite distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs from what<br />

actually occurs in Dyirbal. The reas<strong>on</strong> is as follows:<br />

The stress pattern of Dyirbal is initial and alternating, and final syllables are<br />

unstressed (Dix<strong>on</strong> 1972: 274-276). This means that when we compare disyllabic stems<br />

with trisyllabic stems, the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs causes words with -ŋgu to have<br />

closed unstressed syllables, while words with the -gu suffix have open stressed syllables.<br />

As seen in (69)a with a two-syllable stem, the ŋ of -ŋgu causes the penultimate syllable,<br />

which is unstressed, to be closed. And as seen in (69)b, the use of -gu rather than -ŋgu<br />

with the three-syllable stem results in the stressed penultimate syllable being left open.<br />

(69) a. ˈya.raŋ.gu ‘man-ERG’ *ˈya.ra.gu<br />

b. ˈya.ma.ˈni.gu ‘rainbow-ERG’ *ˈya.ma.ˈniŋ.gu<br />

If ‘syllable-counting allomorphy’ results from TETU as claimed by Kager (1996), then<br />

we would expect the distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs in Dyirbal to be reversed, since the<br />

Stress-to-Weight Principle should enforce a corresp<strong>on</strong>dence between heavy syllables (to<br />

the extent that closed syllables can be called ‘heavy’ in this language) and stress.<br />

The observati<strong>on</strong> that coda c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants are not moraic in Dyirbal may in fact render<br />

the Stress-to-Weight argument moot, and a further complicati<strong>on</strong> is that in at least some<br />

Pama-Nyungan languages, NC sequences can be syllabified as <strong>on</strong>sets and may even be<br />

single segments (i.e., prenasalized stops). However, if the Stress-to-Weight argument is<br />

rejected <strong>on</strong> these grounds, <strong>on</strong>e must also reject McCarthy and Prince’s original comment<br />

<strong>on</strong> this example. 27 Without the noti<strong>on</strong> of ‘compensati<strong>on</strong>’, there is no clear way in which<br />

27 It should be noted that in later work, McCarthy and Prince (1993b: 117-120) aband<strong>on</strong><br />

reference to a ‘compensatory relati<strong>on</strong>ship’ between the root and affix in Dyirbal ergative<br />

210


the distributi<strong>on</strong> of ergative allomorphs is optimal in Dyirbal, and therefore this example is<br />

neutral at best. Even if the example is <strong>on</strong>ly neutral and not truly ‘perverse’, it is<br />

problematic for the P >> M approach because the relevant P c<strong>on</strong>straint in such an<br />

analysis would have to be language-specific, arbitrary, and not externally motivated. If an<br />

advantage of P >> M is supposed to be the reducti<strong>on</strong> of PCSA to ph<strong>on</strong>ological principles<br />

that are independently identified in the regular ph<strong>on</strong>ologies of the world’s languages,<br />

then proposing arbitrary, item-specific P c<strong>on</strong>straints for individual languages completely<br />

undermines the spirit of the model.<br />

4.3.4 Examples of SCA possibly resulting from TETU<br />

The survey did reveal some cases of SCA aside from Est<strong>on</strong>ian that may be analyzed<br />

as TETU effects. For example, as described above in §4.1, the repetitive in Shipibo<br />

(Elías-Ulloa 2004) is marked by -ribi with even-syllabled stems, and by -riba elsewhere.<br />

Elías-Ulloa (2004) claims that this allomorphy is driven by s<strong>on</strong>ority, so that /a/ is a good<br />

foot head, while /i/ is not (foot-initial syllables are assumed to be heads). The main stress<br />

is <strong>on</strong> the sec<strong>on</strong>d syllable if closed; otherwise, the first syllable. There is no sec<strong>on</strong>dary<br />

stress. Elías-Ulloa uses the c<strong>on</strong>straints *i/Head and *a/N<strong>on</strong>Head to select the correct<br />

allomorphs in a TETU analysis.<br />

allomorphy. Instead, they propose a P >> M account of this pattern in which the relevant<br />

P c<strong>on</strong>straint is AFX-TO-FT, which requires the -ŋgu suffix to attach to a base that c<strong>on</strong>sists<br />

of a foot. In this analysis, failure to satisfy AFX-TO-FT results in a null parse, in which<br />

case the -gu allomorph is used by ‘default’. Wolf and McCarthy (to appear: §6.1) discuss<br />

this aspect of the analysis further, proposing that there is a ‘stipulated priority<br />

relati<strong>on</strong>ship’ between the two suffix allomorphs such that the -ŋgu allomorph is ‘tried<br />

first’, and if this yields a null parse, then -gu is used since -gu is ‘not indexed to AFX-TO-<br />

FT’.<br />

211


Note, however, that we do not need to assume that the allomorphy is suppletive.<br />

We could say simply that the repetitive suffix is /-ribV/ with an unspecified vowel, and<br />

then *i/Head and *a/N<strong>on</strong>Head could determine the vowel quality. This would not then be<br />

an instance of the P >> M ranking schema, though it could still be c<strong>on</strong>sidered a TETU<br />

effect.<br />

Another case of SCA that can be analyzed as a TETU effect is found in Turkana<br />

(Dimmendaal 2000). Recall from §4.1 that the suffix used to form abstract nouns occurs<br />

as -ɪ̀sɪ́ with CVC roots and -ù with CiVjCiVjC roots. Since each noun has an á- feminine<br />

gender prefix, the resulting forms all have four syllables; this could be driven by foot<br />

structure/parsing c<strong>on</strong>straints and could therefore result from TETU.<br />

4.3.5 The Subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach<br />

The existence of n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing SCA dem<strong>on</strong>strates the need for a mechanism<br />

other than output optimizati<strong>on</strong> to handle SCA. A subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach captures the<br />

fact that there are cases of SCA where ph<strong>on</strong>ological well-formedness c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s have<br />

no bearing <strong>on</strong> the choice am<strong>on</strong>g allomorphs in a given envir<strong>on</strong>ment.<br />

An example of an SCA pattern that is particularly well-suited to the<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach is found in Nakanai (Austr<strong>on</strong>esian, New Britain; Johnst<strong>on</strong><br />

1980). In Nakanai, the -il- form of the nominalizing affix occurs when it can be in the<br />

first syllable and adjacent to main stress; -la occurs elsewhere (examples are from<br />

Johnst<strong>on</strong> 1980: 177-178).<br />

212


(70) au ‘steer’ vi-gile-muli ‘tell a story’<br />

il-au ‘steering’ vigilemulimuli-la ‘story’<br />

peho ‘die’ vi-kue ‘fight (v.)’<br />

p-il-eho ‘death’ vikue-la ‘fight (n.)’<br />

loso ‘dive’ go-ilo ‘go in’<br />

il-oso ‘diving’ goilo-la ‘entrance’<br />

Stress is <strong>on</strong> the penult (Johnst<strong>on</strong> 1980: 256). McCarthy (2003: 101-102) claimed that in<br />

Nakanai, -il- is attracted to the main stress of the word but is also a ‘formal prefix’, and<br />

the pattern is driven by dispreference for a stress shift with respect to the base. In<br />

McCarthy’s analysis, OO-PK-MAX penalizes the stress shift caused by -la, while the<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straints AFX-TO-HD(-il-) and PREFIX/σ(-il-) limit -il- to occurring with disyllabic and<br />

smaller stems. Each of these c<strong>on</strong>straints presumably outranks UNIFORMEXPONENCE,<br />

which requires each morphological category to be marked by a single affix across all<br />

forms (though McCarthy does not explicitly propose such a c<strong>on</strong>straint), making this a<br />

case of P >> M. Since OO-PK-MAX is not active elsewhere in the language (McCarthy<br />

2003: 102), this is a case of ‘the emergence of the faithful’, not TETU. Thus, even a case<br />

of suppletive allomorphy that is apparently ph<strong>on</strong>ologically optimizing still c<strong>on</strong>tradicts<br />

Kager’s (1996) claim that SCA results from TETU.<br />

A subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> account for the Nakanai allomorphy is characterized as<br />

follows. The -il- affix subcategorizes for the first vowel and main stress (under a cyclic<br />

account of stress). -il- can then attach <strong>on</strong>ly to disyllabic and smaller stems (see Yu 2003<br />

<strong>on</strong> using subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> for infixati<strong>on</strong>), and -la will attach to all other stems by virtue<br />

of its less restrictive subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> frame. The Nakanai example is thus exactly the<br />

type of case predicted and accounted for by subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

213


4.3.6 Using Subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> to model SCA<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong>, I show how subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> works using some examples seen<br />

above. First, to account for Tzeltal perfective allomorphy, we can propose the<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> frames shown below.<br />

(71) Perfective c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> A Perfective c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> B (‘elsewhere’)<br />

[[#σ#] verb stem oh perf suffix ] perf verb [[ ] verb stem εh perf suffix ] perf verb<br />

In this analysis, the -oh suffix left-subcategorizes for a verb stem with <strong>on</strong>ly a single<br />

syllable, while the -εh suffix left-subcategorizes for a verb stem with no ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

requirements. This is how -εh is selected as the ‘elsewhere’ allomorph.<br />

In Nakanai, we can characterize the nominalizing allomorphy seen above as<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> for a vowel and a stressed syllable. Below are proposed<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> frames for the two nominalizing allomorphs in Nakanai.<br />

(72) Nominal c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> A Nominal c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> B (‘elsewhere’)<br />

[il nominalizing prefix [V, σ́] verb stem ] noun [[ ] verb stem la nominalizing suffix ] noun<br />

Here, the il- allomorph right-subcategorizes for the leftmost vowel and stressed syllable<br />

of a verb stem. In the event that il- cannot be adjacent to both the leftmost vowel and the<br />

stressed syllable, then the elsewhere allomorph, -la, is selected. This allomorph left-<br />

subcategorizes for a verb stem with no ph<strong>on</strong>ological requirements.<br />

4.3.7 Est<strong>on</strong>ian revisited<br />

Given the existence of the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> mechanism discussed above, there<br />

are two possible reanalyses for the Est<strong>on</strong>ian data that were the impetus for Kager’s claim<br />

that SCA is output optimizati<strong>on</strong>. The first is the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> account outlined<br />

below. Here, I propose subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> frames to account for the allomorphy found in<br />

214


the genitive plural and partitive plural. Each of these is characterized as having the more<br />

specific allomorph subcategorize for a stem that ends in a complete foot.<br />

(73) a. Est<strong>on</strong>ian genitive plural c<strong>on</strong>st. A<br />

[[Ft#] stem te gen pl suffix ] gen pl word<br />

Est<strong>on</strong>ian genitive plural c<strong>on</strong>st. B (‘elsewhere’)<br />

[[ ] stem tte gen pl suffix ] gen pl word<br />

b. Est<strong>on</strong>ian partitive plural c<strong>on</strong>st. A<br />

[[Ft#] stem sit part pl suffix ] part pl word<br />

Est<strong>on</strong>ian partitive plural c<strong>on</strong>st. B (‘elsewhere’)<br />

[[ ] stem it part pl suffix ] part pl word<br />

A sec<strong>on</strong>d reanalysis is possible for the Est<strong>on</strong>ian genitive plural and partitive<br />

plural: a n<strong>on</strong>-suppletive account involving a single underlying form of the affix for each<br />

morphological category and ph<strong>on</strong>ological rules specific to each category: a rule of tt<br />

degeminati<strong>on</strong> for the genitive plural, and a rule of s inserti<strong>on</strong> for the partitive plural.<br />

These rules are schematized below.<br />

(74) a. Genitive plural tt degeminati<strong>on</strong> b. Partitive plural s inserti<strong>on</strong><br />

(σ σ) Ft ( σ σ) Ft<br />

μ<br />

stem<br />

=<br />

stem s i t<br />

t t e<br />

gen pl word<br />

Ø<br />

part pl word<br />

This analysis in terms of ph<strong>on</strong>ological rules is possible because the allomorphs in each<br />

category are ph<strong>on</strong>ologically similar to each other, allowing us to propose a single<br />

underlying form (/-tte/ for the genitive plural and /-it/ for the partitive plural).<br />

Interestingly, this is true of some other cases of optimizing SCA as well, so that am<strong>on</strong>g<br />

those cases of SCA found in this survey that appear to be optimizing, some may not<br />

actually involve suppletive allomorphy. For example, in the Shipibo repetitive<br />

215


allomorphy discussed above, it is possible to propose a single underlying form, /-ribV/,<br />

that corresp<strong>on</strong>ds to the two allomorphs. This is important because not <strong>on</strong>ly have we<br />

dem<strong>on</strong>strated that SCA is not always optimizing, but it may even be the case that the<br />

majority of cases of SCA are n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing <strong>on</strong>ce we factor out cases of optimizing SCA<br />

that do not actually involve suppletive allomorphy.<br />

4.3.8 Summary of analysis<br />

Given the existence of SCA that output optimizati<strong>on</strong> cannot handle, and the<br />

existence of subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>, which can handle these cases as well as those modeled by<br />

output optimizati<strong>on</strong>, we have 2 opti<strong>on</strong>s for our theory. Opti<strong>on</strong> A is to model the<br />

optimizing cases using output optimizati<strong>on</strong> and the n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing cases using<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>; this is similar to a proposal advanced by Booij (1998). Opti<strong>on</strong> B, the<br />

opti<strong>on</strong> advocated here, is to model all cases of PCSA (including SCA) using<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

Opti<strong>on</strong> B avoids the problem of having multiple theoretical mechanisms to model<br />

a single phenomen<strong>on</strong>. Opti<strong>on</strong> B also captures the fact that SCA appears to be a unitary<br />

phenomen<strong>on</strong>, rather than two distinct phenomena that can be easily differentiated, which<br />

is what Opti<strong>on</strong> A implies. As shown below, cases of SCA are distributed al<strong>on</strong>g a<br />

c<strong>on</strong>tinuum of optimizati<strong>on</strong> ranging from optimizing, TETU effects (as in Est<strong>on</strong>ian) to<br />

anti-optimizing or ‘perverse’ effects (as in Dyirbal).<br />

(75) A c<strong>on</strong>tinuum of optimizati<strong>on</strong> in SCA<br />

Optimizing; possible N<strong>on</strong>-arbitrary distributi<strong>on</strong>; not Arbitrary distributi<strong>on</strong>; ‘Perverse’<br />

TETU effects necessarily optimizing n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing<br />

e.g. Est<strong>on</strong>ian, Turkana Kimatuumbi, Nakanai Tzeltal, Kaititj Dyirbal<br />

216


Furthermore, Opti<strong>on</strong> A represents a poor way of doing science. If we use the P >> M<br />

model <strong>on</strong>ly to account for the type of examples that it handles best, then the model can<br />

have no predictive power and is completely untestable. Since we are dealing with an<br />

apparently unitary phenomen<strong>on</strong> in a single domain of grammar, there is no principled<br />

reas<strong>on</strong> to use two completely different models to account for different instances of the<br />

phenomen<strong>on</strong>. 1<br />

4.4 C<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong><br />

In this chapter we have seen a number of cases of suppletive allomorphy<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by elements of the prosodic hierarchy (mora, syllable, or foot). Examples<br />

from a wide variety of languages were presented in §4.1. One large class of cases<br />

revealed by the present survey involves the ergative/locative in the Pama-Nyungan<br />

languages of Australia. On their surface, the PN examples are problematic for my claim<br />

that PCSA is not inherently optimizing and should be modeled using subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

rather than Output Optimizati<strong>on</strong> because many of the patterns do appear to be optimizing.<br />

However, a look at the history of the PN ergative/locative allomorphy (§4.2) has revealed<br />

1<br />

This reflects a more general issue that has parallels in other areas of research, notably in<br />

the study of fixed segment reduplicati<strong>on</strong>. In a seminal article <strong>on</strong> the topic, Alderete et al<br />

(1999) propose two separate analyses, a ph<strong>on</strong>ological analysis and a morphological<br />

analysis, for what they view as two different types of fixed segment reduplicati<strong>on</strong>. In<br />

effect, the examples where the fixed segmentism seems to follow from ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

principles get a ph<strong>on</strong>ological analysis, while examples where the identity of the fixed<br />

segment is arbitrary get a morphological analysis. One could criticize this approach al<strong>on</strong>g<br />

the same lines as I have criticized the approach advocated by Booij (1998). However, an<br />

important difference between the use of a dual approach for fixed segment reduplicati<strong>on</strong><br />

vs. PCSA is that Alderete et al identify several independent properties of the<br />

morphological type of fixed segmentism that differ from the ph<strong>on</strong>ological type (1999:<br />

355-356). No such independent properties differentiate the optimizing vs. n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing<br />

types of PCSA, and for this reas<strong>on</strong>, a dual analysis of PCSA is unmotivated and<br />

unprincipled. See §6.4 for further discussi<strong>on</strong> of this point.<br />

217


a source for the apparent effect of optimizati<strong>on</strong> that does not involve morphological<br />

change for the sake of ph<strong>on</strong>ological optimizati<strong>on</strong>. This eliminates any problem that the<br />

PN examples might have posed for a subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach to PCSA. The<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach to prosodic PCSA is spelled out in §4.3 and c<strong>on</strong>trasted with<br />

Kager’s (1996) proposed use of Output Optimizati<strong>on</strong> to model the same phenomen<strong>on</strong>.<br />

Subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> is argued to be the superior account because it offers a unified analysis<br />

of PCSA and is able to handle n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing allomorphy. The approach to prosodic<br />

PCSA described in §4.3 is the same subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach used in chapters 2 and 3<br />

to model cases of PCSA c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by segments and by stress/t<strong>on</strong>e, respectively. In<br />

chapter 5, I make explicit some predicti<strong>on</strong>s for other types of ph<strong>on</strong>ology-morphology<br />

interacti<strong>on</strong>s that are made by this approach and c<strong>on</strong>trast them with the predicti<strong>on</strong>s of<br />

Output Optimizati<strong>on</strong>. I will argue that subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> offers a superior account of<br />

these other phenomena in additi<strong>on</strong> to PCSA.<br />

218


Chapter 5: Predicti<strong>on</strong>s of the P >> M model<br />

In the preceding three chapters we have seen examples of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy (PCSA) followed by dem<strong>on</strong>strati<strong>on</strong>s of how these<br />

cases can be modeled using the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach to morphology. In most of<br />

these cases, the so-called ‘P >> M’ approach espoused by McCarthy and Prince<br />

(1993a,b), discussed in chapter 1, can handle the examples equally well. In some cases of<br />

apparently n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing PCSA, the P >> M analysis is inferior to the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

approach because the P >> M analysis requires some highly stipulative and/or poorly<br />

motivated new c<strong>on</strong>straints to be proposed, as in the Tzeltal, Kaititj, Zuni, and Dyirbal<br />

examples discussed in chapter 4. However, some may argue that this disadvantage of the<br />

P >> M model is outweighed by its explanatory power, which exceeds that of the<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach in that it is able to make sense of the optimizing nature of<br />

many of the examples of PCSA observed in the survey; under the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

approach, this optimizing character is coincidental (in the synchr<strong>on</strong>ic realm). It was<br />

argued that this failure to capture the apparent optimizati<strong>on</strong> is not a fatal shortcoming of<br />

the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach because many examples of PCSA, as dem<strong>on</strong>strated in<br />

chapters 2-4, do not appear to involve optimizati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

In this chapter I discuss phenomena other than PCSA where ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s have some bearing <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong>. I will dem<strong>on</strong>strate that, based <strong>on</strong> what<br />

we know about those other phenomena, the P >> M model does not match very well with<br />

the range of phenomena found in the world’s languages. A c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong> of other<br />

phenomena at the ph<strong>on</strong>ology-morphology interface thereby lends further support to my<br />

claim based <strong>on</strong> PCSA that the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> model is the superior <strong>on</strong>e.<br />

219


<str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong> can in principle be manifested in several<br />

different ways involving the occurrence, shape, selecti<strong>on</strong>, ordering, and placement of<br />

affixes. In this chapter, I c<strong>on</strong>sider each of these possible effects, discussing the<br />

predicti<strong>on</strong>s made by P >> M for each type of effect and then comparing these predicti<strong>on</strong>s<br />

with the range of attested examples of each type am<strong>on</strong>g the world’s languages (in<br />

instances where relevant survey data are available).<br />

In terms of morpheme occurrence, ph<strong>on</strong>ology is expected to determine whether<br />

or not a particular morpheme will appear in surface forms. On the <strong>on</strong>e hand, there should<br />

be instances in which a morpheme is inserted for the purpose of ph<strong>on</strong>ological well-<br />

formedness; this corresp<strong>on</strong>ds to the phenomen<strong>on</strong> of the empty morph, discussed in §5.1.<br />

The other logical possibility is that ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s could prevent a<br />

morpheme from surfacing, resulting in a ph<strong>on</strong>ologically induced morphological gap<br />

(§5.2). Relating to this, ph<strong>on</strong>ology could also in principle determine whether a process<br />

such as reduplicati<strong>on</strong> is allowed to apply; this is covered in §5.3.<br />

The shape of the surface form of a particular morpheme can be influenced by<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ology whenever ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes end up applying to a morpheme in some<br />

words but not others depending <strong>on</strong> the ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>text. This is regular,<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed (n<strong>on</strong>-suppletive) allomorphy. I will not be discussing this<br />

type of allomorphy any further here; I c<strong>on</strong>sider this to be within the domain of pure<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ology since it does not have any effect <strong>on</strong> the actual process of affixati<strong>on</strong> per se.<br />

A related effect is the ph<strong>on</strong>ologically determined selecti<strong>on</strong> of multiple different<br />

underlying forms of an affix. This is the phenomen<strong>on</strong> of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed<br />

suppletive allomorphy, which has been the primary subject of this dissertati<strong>on</strong>. The<br />

220


eas<strong>on</strong> why PCSA is c<strong>on</strong>sidered as a ph<strong>on</strong>ological effect in morphology (while n<strong>on</strong>-<br />

suppletive allomorphy is not) is that PCSA involves the direct influence of ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

factors <strong>on</strong> the process of affixati<strong>on</strong> itself. PCSA will not be discussed further in this<br />

chapter since the predicti<strong>on</strong>s of P >> M and the cross-linguistic results have already been<br />

presented for this phenomen<strong>on</strong> in chapters 2-4.<br />

A final possible ph<strong>on</strong>ological effect <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong> involves the locati<strong>on</strong> of an affix<br />

in the word, in terms of its linear ordering with respect to other morphemes in the word,<br />

or (in the case of infixati<strong>on</strong>) its placement within the stem itself. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g>ly<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed affix order and infix placement are discussed in §5.4 and §5.5, respectively.<br />

As will be seen, those phenomena for which survey data are available tend to<br />

support the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach while providing arguments against the P >> M<br />

approach. This will be discussed further in the c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> in §5.6.<br />

5.1 Empty morphs<br />

The P >> M model predicts that empty morphs (defined by Bauer (1988: 242) as<br />

‘a recurrent form in a language that does not appear to be related to any element of<br />

meaning’) should occur based <strong>on</strong> ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s. In principle, any<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint should be able to force the inserti<strong>on</strong> of an empty morph. The<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint in questi<strong>on</strong> would have to outrank a morphological c<strong>on</strong>straint<br />

that I will call DEPMORPH, which bans inserti<strong>on</strong> of morphemes not present in the input<br />

(note that this is a different c<strong>on</strong>straint from the ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint DEP, which<br />

penalizes inserti<strong>on</strong> of ph<strong>on</strong>ological elements).<br />

221


Some specific types of ph<strong>on</strong>ological requirements that are predicted to be met via<br />

the use of empty morphs are: dissimilati<strong>on</strong> (similar ph<strong>on</strong>ological elements are separated<br />

from <strong>on</strong>e another by inserti<strong>on</strong> of an empty morph), word minimality (subminimal words<br />

are augmented by an empty morph that c<strong>on</strong>tributes enough moras or syllables to allow<br />

the word to satisfy minimality), licensing (an affix c<strong>on</strong>taining a particular marked<br />

segment or feature is <strong>on</strong>ly allowed to attach to the stem if an empty morph c<strong>on</strong>taining a<br />

segment or feature that licenses the marked segment/feature is added to the root),<br />

alignment (an empty morph that c<strong>on</strong>tains a segment that is eligible to link to a particular<br />

feature is added to the edge of a word so that the feature in questi<strong>on</strong> can spread to that<br />

edge, satisfying alignment), stress clash avoidance (an empty morph c<strong>on</strong>sisting of an<br />

unstressed syllable intervenes between two stressed morphemes to avoid a stress clash),<br />

anti-homoph<strong>on</strong>y (an empty morph occurs in some member of a paradigm to avoid<br />

c<strong>on</strong>fusi<strong>on</strong> with an otherwise homoph<strong>on</strong>ous member of the paradigm), and syllable<br />

structure c<strong>on</strong>straints (an empty morph c<strong>on</strong>sisting of a single C or V is inserted between<br />

V+V or C+C, respectively, to avoid a vowel hiatus or c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant cluster).<br />

To my knowledge, no cross-linguistic survey has been undertaken to determine<br />

which of these scenarios actually occurs in any of the world’s languages.<br />

Impressi<strong>on</strong>istically, some of these possibilities, such as the use of empty morphs to<br />

satisfy word minimality (attested in Ndebele (Sibanda 2004)) and for stress clash<br />

avoidance, seem plausible, while others, such as alignment, seem less likely to be<br />

attested. This is an empirical questi<strong>on</strong> for future study.<br />

222


5.2 <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g>ly induced morphological gaps<br />

Prince and Smolensky (1993) first pointed out the use of OT to account for<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ologically induced morphological gaps. In the traditi<strong>on</strong>al OT approach there is some<br />

winning candidate corresp<strong>on</strong>ding to every input, even if the winning candidate is not very<br />

‘good’ in that incurs many violati<strong>on</strong>s of even highly-ranked c<strong>on</strong>straints. In standard OT,<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ologically induced morphological gaps should therefore not be allowed. Prince and<br />

Smolensky (1993) found a way around this problem involving the so-called ‘null parse’<br />

and a c<strong>on</strong>straint called MPARSE. If “Ø” is c<strong>on</strong>sidered as a candidate output al<strong>on</strong>gside the<br />

faithful candidate and other candidates that are minimally different from the input, then a<br />

gap could result from the selecti<strong>on</strong> of “Ø” as the winning candidate. Prince and<br />

Smolensky assumed that the null parse satisfies all c<strong>on</strong>straints except MPARSE, and that<br />

no other candidate violates MPARSE. Thus, any candidate violating a c<strong>on</strong>straint ranked<br />

above MPARSE is ungrammatical, and if every n<strong>on</strong>-null candidate is ungrammatical, then<br />

the null parse is selected.<br />

Under this model, the P >> M ranking that creates gaps is the ranking of<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints ahead of the (presumably morphological) c<strong>on</strong>straint MPARSE. In<br />

principle, any ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint could give rise to gaps. As pointed out by Orgun<br />

and Sprouse (1999), Prince and Smolensky’s model predicts that any ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straint that causes a morphological gap will not be violated anywhere else in the<br />

language. Thus, for example, a language that has morphological gaps due to stress clash<br />

avoidance cannot have any words exhibiting stress clash.<br />

Orgun and Sprouse (1999) dem<strong>on</strong>strate that this predicti<strong>on</strong> is incorrect. The<br />

analysis of some languages (Turkish, Tagalog, and Tiene are discussed) requires<br />

223


violati<strong>on</strong> of certain c<strong>on</strong>straints to be allowed in some c<strong>on</strong>texts and to result in<br />

ungrammaticality in other c<strong>on</strong>texts. This gives rise to a ranking paradox in Prince and<br />

Smolensky’s model: in some languages a c<strong>on</strong>straint must be ranked above MPARSE for<br />

some purposes but below MPARSE for other purposes. Prince and Smolensky’s model<br />

undergenerates, since it cannot account for these three languages. To solve this problem,<br />

Orgun and Sprouse (1999) propose an alternative approach that involves adding a new<br />

layer to OT. Their proposal is that EVAL, the familiar OT candidate evaluati<strong>on</strong> module,<br />

will always select a n<strong>on</strong>-null winning candidate. This candidate must then be submitted to<br />

a higher level that Orgun and Sprouse term CONTROL. C<strong>on</strong>straints in CONTROL are<br />

absolutely inviolable, such that if the winning candidate from EVAL violates any<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straint in CONTROL, then it is ungrammatical and there will be no output.<br />

In principle, the revised OT model with CONTROL is compatible with the P >> M<br />

ranking schema. However, if gaps are created in CONTROL, then the P-M c<strong>on</strong>straint<br />

interacti<strong>on</strong> that actually creates gaps would be a ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint in CONTROL<br />

taking precedence over a morphological c<strong>on</strong>straint in EVAL (namely, MORPHEXPR,<br />

shown below) (Rose 2000a). 1<br />

(1) MORPHEXPR: An input morphological category is expressed in the output.<br />

Orgun and Sprouse’s model predicts that every ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint should be<br />

able to cause a morphological gap. However, unlike in Prince and Smolensky’s model, it<br />

1<br />

Since ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints in CONTROL can ‘override’ morphological c<strong>on</strong>straints in<br />

EVAL, the CONTROL-based model gives rise to a perhaps more restricted set of effects<br />

similar to those predicted by the EVAL ranking schema P >> M. Orgun and Sprouse<br />

(1999) do not put any limits <strong>on</strong> which c<strong>on</strong>straints or c<strong>on</strong>straint types can be part of<br />

CONTROL, but presumably if the CONTROL proposal were found to overgenerate in the<br />

same way as P >> M, then this problem could be addressed by putting some principled<br />

restricti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> which c<strong>on</strong>straints can be in CONTROL.<br />

224


is not the case that c<strong>on</strong>straints that cause gaps must be inviolable everywhere in the<br />

language. Given that some languages have gaps in some paradigms caused by c<strong>on</strong>straints<br />

that are violated elsewhere, Orgun and Sprouse’s model is superior to Prince and<br />

Smolensky’s in accounting for the kinds of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically induced morphological gaps<br />

that are found in the world’s languages.<br />

5.3 Reduplicati<strong>on</strong><br />

Under the Base-Reduplicant (BR) Corresp<strong>on</strong>dence model of reduplicati<strong>on</strong><br />

(McCarthy and Prince 1995), the reduplicant (or RED) is a morpheme that copies<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological material from the BASE. In this model, the producti<strong>on</strong> of RED is driven by<br />

the morphological c<strong>on</strong>straint MORPHEXPR (discussed above), and by the ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straint (or c<strong>on</strong>straint family) BR-CORRESPONDENCE, which enforces similarity<br />

between RED and the BASE. This model allows for effects of P >> M just like those<br />

described in §5.2 giving rise to morphological gaps, since certain ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straints if ranked ahead of MORPHEXPR could prevent the reduplicant from being<br />

realized. For example, a c<strong>on</strong>straint against stress clash could prevent the reduplicant from<br />

surfacing if it would have a stressed syllable that would surface next to a stressed syllable<br />

of the base. A c<strong>on</strong>straint banning sequences of (tier-) adjacent like c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants could<br />

prevent the reduplicant from being realized if its realizati<strong>on</strong> next to the base would have<br />

resulted in such a sequence. C<strong>on</strong>straints requiring foot binarity and exhaustive foot<br />

parsing could prevent a reduplicant with an odd syllable count from surfacing if the base<br />

has an even syllable count. In general, any possible ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint can in theory<br />

prevent the realizati<strong>on</strong> of a reduplicant. The P >> M model therefore predicts the<br />

225


existence of cases where the semantic c<strong>on</strong>tent of a reduplicative morpheme is expressed<br />

but the ph<strong>on</strong>ological form of the word is identical to the base and does not c<strong>on</strong>tain any<br />

reduplicated material.<br />

Under an alternative approach, Morphological Doubling Theory (MDT; Inkelas<br />

and Zoll 2005), the same effects of P >> M are predicted. In MDT, reduplicati<strong>on</strong> is a<br />

morphological rather than a ph<strong>on</strong>ological process. There is no ‘base’ to be c<strong>on</strong>trasted<br />

with a ‘reduplicant’, but instead two underlyingly identical instances of the stem, which<br />

are governed by separate sets of ranked ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints (coph<strong>on</strong>ologies). In this<br />

model, presumably the expressi<strong>on</strong> of each copy of the stem is driven by MORPHEXPR,<br />

which could be ranked differently between the two coph<strong>on</strong>ologies corresp<strong>on</strong>ding to the<br />

two copies of the stem. If in either coph<strong>on</strong>ology, some ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint outranked<br />

MORPHEXPR under the P >> M schema, then the P c<strong>on</strong>straint in questi<strong>on</strong> could prevent<br />

that copy of the stem from being realized. However, note that it is probably more difficult<br />

to generate such an effect under MDT than under BR Corresp<strong>on</strong>dence. This is because in<br />

order to account for why the root (rather than the affix) is always expressed when a<br />

particular affix is incompatible with it, there must be some very highly-ranked (or<br />

perhaps inviolable) c<strong>on</strong>straint requiring expressi<strong>on</strong> of the root (ROOTEXPR). In the BR<br />

Corresp<strong>on</strong>dence model, RED is an affix, so its expressi<strong>on</strong> is driven by the more general<br />

MORPHEXPR, which is not inviolable or as highly ranked as ROOTEXPR. This is what<br />

allows the possibility of a ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint blocking the expressi<strong>on</strong> of the<br />

reduplicant. But in MDT, the two copies of the stem have equal status, and neither is<br />

c<strong>on</strong>sidered an affix, so both are subject to ROOTEXPR (unless the stem for reduplicati<strong>on</strong><br />

includes some affixes, in which case those particular parts of each copy of the stem<br />

226


would not be subject to ROOTEXPR). This means that if ROOTEXPR is inviolable, then<br />

under MDT, the P >> M model cannot result in null expressi<strong>on</strong> of either copy of the<br />

stem. If ROOTEXPR is not inviolable but <strong>on</strong>ly very highly ranked, then a ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straint could still outrank it, resulting in null expressi<strong>on</strong>, but this is no more likely<br />

than the failure of any root (in a n<strong>on</strong>-reduplicative c<strong>on</strong>text) to be expressed.<br />

5.4 <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g>ly c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed affix order<br />

Though this has not to my knowledge been made explicit in the OT literature, the<br />

P >> M model makes broad predicti<strong>on</strong>s for ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed affix order and<br />

could in principle be used to model that phenomen<strong>on</strong> just as it has been used for other<br />

effects of ph<strong>on</strong>ology in morphology (such as suppletive allomorphy, as we have seen;<br />

other effects will be discussed in subsequent secti<strong>on</strong>s of this chapter). In §5.4.1, I discuss<br />

important predicti<strong>on</strong>s made by P >> M for affix order. Then, in §5.4.2, I discuss results of<br />

a cross-linguistic search for cases of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed affix order, showing that<br />

the predicti<strong>on</strong>s of P >> M for affix order do not hold up in the face of cross-linguistic<br />

data. Finally, in §5.4.3, I discuss an affix ordering phenomen<strong>on</strong> in Pulaar (West Atlantic,<br />

West Africa) which, <strong>on</strong> its surface, appears to exemplify a type of system predicted by<br />

the P >> M model to exist. I show, however, that up<strong>on</strong> close inspecti<strong>on</strong> Pulaar turns out<br />

not to be an example of this, and that its affix order can be reduced almost exclusively to<br />

semantic scope.<br />

5.4.1 Predicti<strong>on</strong>s for affix order<br />

The P >> M model makes important predicti<strong>on</strong>s for affix order. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g>ly<br />

227


driven affix order is easily generated by ranking ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints over<br />

morphological c<strong>on</strong>straints such as C<strong>on</strong>doravdi and Kiparsky’s (1998) SCOPE and<br />

Hyman’s (2003) MIRROR, c<strong>on</strong>straints that relate affix order to semantic scope and the<br />

order of syntactic operati<strong>on</strong>s. If P c<strong>on</strong>straints can outrank M c<strong>on</strong>straints, as allowed in OT<br />

and made explicit by McCarthy and Prince (1993a,b), then ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints can<br />

outrank these and other morphological c<strong>on</strong>straints governing affix order. Therefore, P >><br />

M predicts the existence of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically driven affix order. 2<br />

Can<strong>on</strong>ical OT does not respect morphological c<strong>on</strong>stituency. The input to a<br />

tableau, at least in the standard versi<strong>on</strong> of OT, includes the root and all affixes making up<br />

the word, unordered with respect to each other. 3 Therefore, P >> M predicts that affixes<br />

can be ordered ph<strong>on</strong>ologically. More specifically, it also predicts global, across-the-board<br />

reordering of all of the morphemes in a word for purposes of ph<strong>on</strong>ological optimizati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

This means that in some language, there could be a series of several affixes whose<br />

relative order (with respect to each other and to the root) is ph<strong>on</strong>ologically determined,<br />

perhaps al<strong>on</strong>g a ph<strong>on</strong>ological scale. Such a case has never, to my knowledge, been<br />

discussed as such in the literature, though a putative case from Fula/Pulaar (West<br />

2<br />

In fact, McCarthy and Prince (1993a: 85) explicitly claim that ‘…infixati<strong>on</strong> shows that<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints can determine even the linear order of morphemes and<br />

morpheme parts’ [emphasis mine]. Strictly speaking, this is false. The existence of<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ologically determined infix placement does not entail the existence of<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ologically determined affix order. Infix placement is not the same as affix order;<br />

infix placement involves the order of ph<strong>on</strong>ological segments making up affixes, not the<br />

order of the morphemes themselves. Looking at the placement of an infix in a stem does<br />

not tell us the linear order of the infix morpheme with respect to the stem morpheme,<br />

unless <strong>on</strong>e admits into the theory the rather strange c<strong>on</strong>cept of X being ordered inside Y.<br />

Therefore, it is still very much an open questi<strong>on</strong> whether ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints can (or<br />

should be allowed to) determine the ‘linear order of morphemes’.<br />

3<br />

Though Kiparsky (2000) introduces Stratal Optimality Theory, an approach that does<br />

respect morphological c<strong>on</strong>stituency.<br />

228


Atlantic, West Africa) will be discussed at length in §5.4.3. In the following secti<strong>on</strong>, I<br />

will discuss all of the possible examples of ph<strong>on</strong>ological affix order that were uncovered<br />

in the course of the search.<br />

5.4.2 Cross-linguistic findings<br />

Only 5 possible cases of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically driven affix order were identified in a<br />

search of over 400 grammars of languages representing a wide range of language<br />

families. The search also included a survey of the theoretical linguistics literature <strong>on</strong> affix<br />

ordering. The existence of templatic affix order is well established (see Zwicky 1985,<br />

Simps<strong>on</strong> and Withgott 1986, Speas 1990, Stump 1992, 1993, Inkelas 1993, Hyman and<br />

Inkelas 1997, and Good 2003), so the lack of cases of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed affix<br />

order is striking and may in itself be c<strong>on</strong>sidered a negative result for the P >> M<br />

predicti<strong>on</strong>. 4 I summarize the examples below.<br />

First, Jacobsen (1973) claims that suffixes in Washo (Hokan, California/Nevada)<br />

are reordered ‘to insure an even distributi<strong>on</strong> of stressed and unstressed syllables, and to<br />

draw most sequences of unstressed syllables to the end of the word’ (1973: 9). Affixes<br />

occur in a n<strong>on</strong>-scope order in some examples. Under P >> M, we can analyze this by<br />

ranking footing c<strong>on</strong>straints over SCOPE. However, this may also be analyzed via<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> without P >> M: stressed suffixes subcategorize for a foot to their left.<br />

4<br />

Of course it cannot be claimed that no other examples of ph<strong>on</strong>ological affix order exist<br />

in any language. However, the number of grammars examined in the course of this search<br />

(approximately 400 grammars) is close to the number examined in the survey of<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy described in chapters 2-4<br />

(approximately 600 grammars), so it is striking that <strong>on</strong>ly five putative examples were<br />

uncovered here, in c<strong>on</strong>trast to the 137 examples of PCSA found in the other survey. This<br />

should increase our level of c<strong>on</strong>fidence in the claim that ph<strong>on</strong>ological affix order is<br />

uncomm<strong>on</strong>.<br />

229


Descriptively, the verb in Awtuw (Ram, Papua New Guinea) has 13 affix slots<br />

(Feldman 1986: 53). The plural -m occurs in suffix positi<strong>on</strong> +3 or +6. -m cannot appear in<br />

+3 if -re Future or -rere Desiderative appears in +5, unless the -iy Imperfective or -kay<br />

Perfect is in +2. -m also cannot appear in +3 if -(k)ek C<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>al is in +4 and nothing<br />

follows it (Feldman 1986: 71). Where -m cannot occur in +3, it can appear in +6.<br />

Wherever -m can occur in +3, it can also occur, doubly marked, in both +3 and +6. This<br />

complicated +3 ~ +6 alternati<strong>on</strong> for plural marking may be ph<strong>on</strong>ologically motivated<br />

because the alternati<strong>on</strong> seems to optimize syllable structure in many c<strong>on</strong>texts. In each<br />

example where -m is disallowed in +3, the ungrammatical form would have had a more<br />

complex c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant sequence than the grammatical form. This suggests that the apparent<br />

morphological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> the positi<strong>on</strong> of -m are really ph<strong>on</strong>ological. Note, however,<br />

that two c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant sequences are allowed, even where a form with <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>on</strong>e c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant in<br />

the same positi<strong>on</strong> is available. Therefore, the alternati<strong>on</strong> is ph<strong>on</strong>ologically optimizing<br />

<strong>on</strong>ly for c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final roots. Because there is not a ph<strong>on</strong>ological explanati<strong>on</strong> for the<br />

pattern across all root types, this may be best analyzed as morphological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing.<br />

Hargus and Tuttle (1997) use P >> M to account for the placement of the s-<br />

Negative prefix in Witsuwit’en (Athabaskan, British Columbia). In some examples, s-<br />

occurs inside the Tense/Aspect prefix (Hargus and Tuttle 1997: 207). With ‘inner’<br />

subjects, the s- prefix occurs outside the Tense/Aspect prefix, which Hargus and Tuttle<br />

claim occurs in order to avoid a complex coda (1997: 207). Hargus and Tuttle’s analysis<br />

is that the normal order of the prefixes is Neg-T/A, but the order changes so that s- can be<br />

a coda, except where this would create a complex coda. Hargus and Tuttle (1997: 207)<br />

formulate this via P >> M using the c<strong>on</strong>straints in (2).<br />

230


(2) *COMPLEX<br />

ALIGN-CODA-SNEG: SNEG should be a coda.<br />

TENSE-STEM: Align the R edge of the Tense prefix to the L edge of the verb stem.<br />

NEG-STEM: Align the R edge of the Neg prefix to the L edge of the verb stem.<br />

The ranking *COMPLEX >> ALIGN-CODA-SNEG >> TENSE-STEM >> NEG-STEM selects the<br />

observed orderings. Note, however, that the data are c<strong>on</strong>sistent with a ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

metathesis analysis that does not involve P >> M. Since the prefixes in questi<strong>on</strong> each<br />

c<strong>on</strong>sist of a single segment, it may be the segments and not the morphemes themselves<br />

whose order is ph<strong>on</strong>ological. Perhaps the regular order is T/A-Neg-, and after the prefixes<br />

are in place, ph<strong>on</strong>ological metathesis occurs to repair complex codas. The metathesis<br />

does not have to result from the regular c<strong>on</strong>straints of the language; it could be specific to<br />

the s- prefix (as is the ALIGN-CODA-SNEG c<strong>on</strong>straint proposed by Hargus and Tuttle).<br />

According to Wiering and Wiering (1994), a series of c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal suffixes in<br />

Doyayo (Adamawa-Ubangi, Camero<strong>on</strong>) is ordered by scope, except that the -m<br />

pluralizing suffix is first in any combinati<strong>on</strong>. It also occurs before the final c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant of a<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant-final verb root. We can model the pattern by ranking a c<strong>on</strong>straint banning [m]<br />

as the sec<strong>on</strong>d in a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant cluster over a c<strong>on</strong>straint aligning -m to the right edge of a<br />

stem. However, we do not need P >> M: the placement of [m] could result from simple<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological metathesis. The generalizati<strong>on</strong> that [m] comes first in c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant clusters is<br />

surface-true, not specific to -m (Wiering and Wiering 1994: 70). Therefore, this can be<br />

handled via ph<strong>on</strong>ological metathesis. We need not assume that the placement of the affix<br />

itself is ph<strong>on</strong>ological.<br />

We have seen that the four examples presented above do not provide str<strong>on</strong>g<br />

evidence for the existence of ph<strong>on</strong>ological affix order, since each example was either<br />

weakly documented or c<strong>on</strong>sistent with a different analysis not involving ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

231


c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing of affix placement. Furthermore, even if these did c<strong>on</strong>stitute examples of<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological affix order, n<strong>on</strong>e involved the kind of global ph<strong>on</strong>ological reordering of<br />

multiple morphemes that is predicted by the P >> M approach. The correctness of that<br />

particular predicti<strong>on</strong> hinges <strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong>e final possible example, to be discussed in the<br />

following secti<strong>on</strong>. The example is from Fula/Pulaar, a language that appears <strong>on</strong> its<br />

surface to uphold the predicti<strong>on</strong> of global ph<strong>on</strong>ological reordering. In fact, I will argue<br />

that despite this surface appearance, affix order in Fula/Pulaar is driven by other, n<strong>on</strong>-<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s.<br />

5.4.3 Pulaar<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong>, I discuss affix order in Pulaar, a West Atlantic language spoken in<br />

a wide area of West Africa and comprising a large number of dialects. 5 I will use Pulaar<br />

as a case study here because, as will be discussed, it appears to exhibit global<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological affix reordering of the type predicted by P >> M. The discussi<strong>on</strong> in this<br />

secti<strong>on</strong> is presented in more detail in Paster (2006) and especially Paster (2005b).<br />

5.4.3.1 S<strong>on</strong>ority-based affix order?<br />

Fuuta Tooro Pulaar, which I describe beginning in §5.4.3.1.3, is spoken in the<br />

Fuuta Tooro regi<strong>on</strong> al<strong>on</strong>g the border between Senegal and Mauritania. The c<strong>on</strong>sultant for<br />

this study is a 42 year-old speaker who moved to the US from a town near Matam, which<br />

5 The name ‘Fula’ is sometimes used for all Pulaar dialects plus other dialects known by<br />

names such as Fulfulde, Fulani, and Fulbe. However, ‘Fula’ usually does not include<br />

Pulaar, so there is no single cover term for all of the dialects. Since the focus of the<br />

discussi<strong>on</strong> to follow is a Pulaar dialect, I use ‘Pulaar’ to refer to the entire language<br />

group.<br />

232


is in Senegal in the eastern part of the Fuuta Tooro regi<strong>on</strong>. Before turning to Fuuta Tooro,<br />

I discuss in §§5.4.3.1.1-2 the order of affixes in Gombe Fula (Arnott 1970), a dialect of<br />

northern Nigeria. Arnott (1970: 333, 366) reports that the order of affixes is largely fixed<br />

in Gombe Fula. In particular, according to Arnott, immediately after the verb stem are<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal suffixes ordered according to the formula ‘TDNR’: all of the /-t/ suffixes<br />

precede the /-d/ suffixes, which precede the /-n/ suffix, which precedes the /-r/ suffixes<br />

(1970: 366). This generalizati<strong>on</strong>, if true, is interesting (am<strong>on</strong>g other reas<strong>on</strong>s) because<br />

‘TDNR’ corresp<strong>on</strong>ds to increasing s<strong>on</strong>ority <strong>on</strong> the s<strong>on</strong>ority scale (see, e.g., Ladefoged<br />

1982), meaning that the fixed order of affixes may be ph<strong>on</strong>ological (Paster 2001). This<br />

can be modeled via P >> M and would c<strong>on</strong>stitute the first known example of the ordering<br />

of multiple affixes al<strong>on</strong>g a ph<strong>on</strong>ological scale, a phenomen<strong>on</strong> predicted by P >> M. As I<br />

show, however, there is a better, n<strong>on</strong>-ph<strong>on</strong>ological analysis of Gombe Fula affix order.<br />

This is an important negative result because it means that P >> M overgenerates in<br />

predicting a phenomen<strong>on</strong> that apparently does not exist.<br />

5.4.3.1.1 Gombe Fula affix order<br />

Arnott described eleven verb suffixes in Pulaar whose basic shape is a single<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant. These are shown below (Arnott 1970: 334, 340-364). 6<br />

6<br />

In Arnott’s orthography, < ’ > represents glottal stop, is a palatal implosive, <br />

is a palatal fricative, and and are voiceless and voiced palatal affricates. I have<br />

normalized Arnott’s transcripti<strong>on</strong>s to the official Senegalese orthography (Hartell<br />

1993:250) by using spaces where Arnott used hyphens between subject/object markers<br />

and verbs.<br />

233


(3) Shape Label Example<br />

-ɗ DENominative fur-ɗ-a ‘be grey’<br />

-t REVersive taar-t-a ‘untie’<br />

-t REPetitive soor-t-o ‘sell again’<br />

-t REFlexive ndaar-t-o ‘look at <strong>on</strong>eself’<br />

-t RETaliative jal-t-o ‘laugh at... in turn’<br />

-t INTensive yan-t-a ‘fall heavily’<br />

-d ASSociative nast-id-a ‘enter together’<br />

-d COMprehensive janng-id-a ‘read, learn all...’<br />

-n CAUsative woy-n-a ‘cause to cry’<br />

-r MODal ɓe mah-ir-i Îi ‘they built them with’<br />

-r LOCative ’o ’yiw-r-ii ‘he came from’<br />

Arnott lists both -C and -VC forms of these suffixes (V is usually [i]). The -VC forms<br />

occurs somewhat inc<strong>on</strong>sistently, so this may or may not be analyzable as epenthesis.<br />

The meanings of the suffixes as described by Arnott are summarized below. First,<br />

the Denominative -ɗ generally attaches to adjectives, c<strong>on</strong>verting them to verb stems. The<br />

Reversive -t suffix produces a verb that ‘undoes’ the result of the plain verb (e.g., the<br />

reversive corresp<strong>on</strong>ding to ‘close’ is ‘open’). The Repetitive -t denotes repetiti<strong>on</strong> of an<br />

acti<strong>on</strong>. The Reflexive -t reduces the number of arguments of the verb by <strong>on</strong>e, so that the<br />

subject performs the acti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> him/herself. The Retaliative -t indicates that an acti<strong>on</strong> is<br />

d<strong>on</strong>e to some<strong>on</strong>e else in retaliati<strong>on</strong>. The Intensive -t indicates ‘completeness, severity,<br />

intensity, etc.,’ (Arnott 1970: 343). The Associative -d denotes either ‘joint acti<strong>on</strong>’ or<br />

‘acti<strong>on</strong> in associati<strong>on</strong> with some pers<strong>on</strong> or thing’ (1970: 344). The effect <strong>on</strong> the<br />

arguments of the verb is to require either a plural subject or else any subject plus a sec<strong>on</strong>d<br />

actor introduced by a prepositi<strong>on</strong>. The Comprehensive -d indicates ‘totality or<br />

completeness’ of the subject or object (Arnott 1970: 345). The Causative -n suffix adds<br />

an object and c<strong>on</strong>tributes the meaning ‘cause to,’ ‘arrange for,’ or ‘make’ (Arnott 1970:<br />

234


346-347). The Modal -r introduces either an instrument or a manner in which an acti<strong>on</strong> is<br />

d<strong>on</strong>e. Finally, Locative -r introduces a locati<strong>on</strong> where an acti<strong>on</strong> is d<strong>on</strong>e.<br />

Arnott claims (1970: 366) that these suffixes have fixed order: ‘As far as [the<br />

c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal] extensi<strong>on</strong>s are c<strong>on</strong>cerned... [the] normal order can be summarized by the<br />

formula T-D-N-R’. 7 Forms with the ‘TDNR’ order are given below with page numbers<br />

from Arnott (1970).<br />

(4) ’o maɓɓ-it-id-ii jolɗe fuu<br />

3sg close-REV-COM-past doors all<br />

‘he opened all the doors’ (367)<br />

’o yam-ɗ-it-in-ir-ii mo lekki gokki kesi<br />

3sgi healthy-DEN-REV-CAU-MOD-past 3sgj medicine other new<br />

‘hei cured himj with some new medicine’ (368)<br />

war-t-ir-<br />

come-REV-MOD-<br />

‘bring back’ (367)<br />

’o maɓɓ-it-ir-ii yolnde hakkiil<br />

3sg close-REV-MOD-past door slowly<br />

‘he opened the door slowly’ (367)<br />

no njooɗ-od-or-too mi ’e maɓɓe<br />

how sit-ASS-MOD-rel.fut 1sg with 3pl<br />

‘how shall I sit/live with them?’ (367)<br />

Arnott also cites several examples of combinati<strong>on</strong>s of c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal suffixes that do<br />

not obey the ‘TDNR’ generalizati<strong>on</strong>. Some of these are shown below (Arnott 1970: 368).<br />

7 The Denominative -ɗ occurs immediately next to the root, but Arnott omits it from the<br />

‘TDNR’ formula.<br />

235


(5) mi wol-d-it-at-aa ’e maɓɓe<br />

1sg speak-COM-REP-fut-neg with 3pl<br />

‘I w<strong>on</strong>’t speak with them again’<br />

mi hul-n-it-oo mo<br />

1sg fear-CAU-RET-subjunctive 3sg<br />

‘I’ll frighten him in turn’<br />

’o nyaam-n-id-ii ɗi<br />

3sg eat-CAU-COM-past 3pl<br />

‘he fed them all’<br />

mi war-t-ir-id-an-te ɗi<br />

1sg come-REV-MOD-COM-DAT-future 3pl<br />

‘I’ll bring them all back to you’<br />

Arnott claims that excepti<strong>on</strong>s to the ‘TDNR’ generalizati<strong>on</strong> involve lexicalized<br />

combinati<strong>on</strong>s of the root and first extensi<strong>on</strong>: ‘Variati<strong>on</strong> from the usual order seems to be<br />

c<strong>on</strong>fined to cases where the basic radical and first extensi<strong>on</strong>… frequently occur together<br />

as an extended radical…’ (1970: 370). Lexicalized forms often have idiomatic meanings<br />

not predictable from the meaning of their parts, and yet these forms have compositi<strong>on</strong>al<br />

meanings. 8 I show in §5.4.3.1.5 that a scope-based analysis avoids having to posit<br />

lexicalized stems; first, I present below a ph<strong>on</strong>ological account based <strong>on</strong> Arnott’s<br />

generalizati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

8 This may not be immediately apparent in the example mi war-t-ir-id-an-te ɗi ‘I’ll bring<br />

them all back to you’ in (5), since Arnott glosses the -t extensi<strong>on</strong> here as a Reversive.<br />

However, since Reversive and Repetitive are homoph<strong>on</strong>ous, the [t] here could be an<br />

instance of the Repetitive suffix instead. In that case, we would have a compositi<strong>on</strong>al<br />

meaning: come + repetitive = come again, i.e., come back. The remaining problem would<br />

be to account for the causative meaning, make come back, i.e., bring back. Perhaps<br />

causative meaning is attributed to the verb due to the presence of the 3pl object ɗi, since<br />

war- ‘come’ usually does not have a direct object. A similar phenomen<strong>on</strong> occurs in some<br />

pairs of transitive vs. intransitive verbs in English, such as ‘I walked’ (which is<br />

intransitive and n<strong>on</strong>-causative) vs. ‘I walked the dog’ (which is transitive and can be<br />

interpreted as ‘I caused the dog to walk’). This also occurs in some varieties of American<br />

English in such c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>s as to learn some<strong>on</strong>e meaning ‘to teach some<strong>on</strong>e’.<br />

236


5.4.3.1.2 A P >> M account of Gombe Fula affix order<br />

Assuming that, despite the excepti<strong>on</strong>s shown above, ‘TDNR’ is the correct<br />

generalizati<strong>on</strong> for the order of c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal suffixes, we can analyze this ph<strong>on</strong>ologically<br />

using P >> M. As menti<strong>on</strong>ed above, the ‘TDNR’ generalizati<strong>on</strong> lends itself to a<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological analysis because the order corresp<strong>on</strong>ds to increasing s<strong>on</strong>ority, as<br />

schematized below.<br />

(6) t d n r<br />

voiceless stops voiced stops nasals liquids<br />

s<strong>on</strong>ority<br />

To model s<strong>on</strong>ority-based affix order, we need a ph<strong>on</strong>ological (P) c<strong>on</strong>straint<br />

enforcing increasing s<strong>on</strong>ority between c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants in separate morphemes, as shown<br />

below.<br />

(7) *FALLINGSONORITY C+C: When a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant C1 is followed by a c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant C2<br />

across a morpheme boundary, C2 may not be less s<strong>on</strong>orous than C1.<br />

The P c<strong>on</strong>straint outranks a morphological (M) c<strong>on</strong>straint, seen below, that requires affix<br />

order to corresp<strong>on</strong>d to semantic scope (C<strong>on</strong>doravdi and Kiparsky 1998).<br />

(8) SCOPE: Morphological c<strong>on</strong>stituency reflects scope.<br />

This c<strong>on</strong>straint refers to the proposal (see, e.g., Baker 1985, Bybee 1985, Rice 2000) that<br />

the order of affixes corresp<strong>on</strong>ds to their semantic scope (broadly defined; see Rice 2000)<br />

so that an affix occurs further from the root than another affix over which it has scope.<br />

We will make use of this c<strong>on</strong>cept in the analysis of Fuuta Tooro Pulaar in §5.4.3.1.4.<br />

To ensure that the P c<strong>on</strong>straint affects <strong>on</strong>ly the order of c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal suffixes, we<br />

also need to assume some undominated c<strong>on</strong>straints to prevent n<strong>on</strong>-c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal suffixes<br />

from being reordered and to prevent violati<strong>on</strong>s of *FALLINGSONORITY C+C from being<br />

237


epaired by c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant feature changes rather than reordering (I will not formulate these<br />

here). Under this analysis, the ranking P >> M (*FALLINGSONORITY C+C >> SCOPE)<br />

selects forms with the TDNR order, even when the order violates SCOPE, as shown<br />

below.<br />

(9) **’o irt-in-ir-ii kam supu ’o kuddu ‘he made me stir the soup with a spo<strong>on</strong>’<br />

/irt, -r, -n/ *FALLINGSONORITY C+C SCOPE<br />

irt-ir-in- *!<br />

irt-in-ir *<br />

Based <strong>on</strong> scope, we expect the order -r-n because Causative has scope over Modal: the<br />

instrument is used by the causee, so Causative applies to a stem that already refers to an<br />

instrument. The -n-r order is selected because the s<strong>on</strong>ority c<strong>on</strong>straint outranks SCOPE.<br />

Crucially, however, the form **’o irt-in-ir-ii kam supu ’o kuddu is not attested by<br />

Arnott (1970) (indicated by two asterisks above). I c<strong>on</strong>structed this example based <strong>on</strong> the<br />

TDNR generalizati<strong>on</strong> for the sake of the argument. In fact, not a single example cited by<br />

Arnott c<strong>on</strong>tradicts our scope-based expectati<strong>on</strong> for affix order. I argue in §5.4.3.1.5 that<br />

this is not accidental.<br />

This analysis allows for the ‘excepti<strong>on</strong>al’ n<strong>on</strong>-TDNR orderings if we assume,<br />

following Arnott, that these have lexicalized stems. In these forms, the suffix attaches<br />

straightforwardly to a stem ending in the c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant formerly bel<strong>on</strong>ging to another suffix.<br />

Thus, we can account for Arnott’s (1970) data using P >> M. But since Arnott’s<br />

data are also c<strong>on</strong>sistent with scope, perhaps P >> M is not needed. Arnott provided no<br />

examples allowing us to distinguish the two analyses. I present data below from the Fuuta<br />

Tooro dialect including many examples that distinguish the two analyses in favor of the<br />

scope-based analysis. I argue in §5.4.3.1.5 that we can extend this analysis to Gombe<br />

Fula.<br />

238


5.4.3.1.3 Fuuta Tooro Pulaar (Northeastern Senegal)<br />

The c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal suffixes of Fuuta Tooro are shown below. 9<br />

(10) Shape Label Example<br />

-ɗ DENominative mi dom-ɗ-ii ‘I became thirsty’<br />

-t SEParative/Reversive mi udd-it-ii baafal ŋgal ‘I opened the door’<br />

-t REPetitive ’o haal-t-ii ‘he spoke again’<br />

-d COMprehensive/Associative mi udd-id-ii baafe ɗe ‘I closed all the doors’<br />

-n CAUsative mi jaŋg-in-ii ‘I taught’<br />

-r MODal/Instrumental/Locative mi dog-r-ii paɗe ‘I ran with shoes’<br />

Note that there are fewer c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal suffixes here than listed by Arnott (1970). This is<br />

because some suffixes of Gombe Fula are not used productively in Fuuta Tooro and<br />

because in some cases Arnott distinguished suffixes where the data in Fuuta Tooro<br />

suggest a single suffix (e.g., Modal/Instrumental/Locative). See Paster (2005b) for<br />

details.<br />

Several pairwise combinati<strong>on</strong>s of c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal suffixes exhibit ordering<br />

alternati<strong>on</strong>s directly related to scope. For example, when Comprehensive has scope over<br />

Separative, the Comprehensive -d is ordered outside Separative -t, as in (11)a. The scope<br />

relati<strong>on</strong> is shown by the fact that the comprehensive acti<strong>on</strong> takes place simultaneously, a<br />

meaning c<strong>on</strong>tributed by the Comprehensive (Paster 2005b). In (11)b, the order is<br />

reversed. This corresp<strong>on</strong>ds to Separative having scope over Comprehensive, evidenced<br />

by the ‘sequential’ meaning, which results from the fact that Separative has no<br />

simultaneous acti<strong>on</strong> meaning. The original acti<strong>on</strong> takes place simultaneously, but the<br />

undoing does not.<br />

9<br />

Each suffix also has a -VC form as in Gombe Fula. For Fuuta Tooro, I use the official<br />

Senegalese Pulaar orthography, which omits predictable word-initial glottal stops, uses<br />

for the palatal nasal, and uses a ‘hooked y’ for the palatal implosive, which I replace<br />

with .<br />

239


(11) a. o sok-t-id-ii baafe ɗe fof<br />

3sg lock-SEP-COM-past doors det all<br />

‘he unlocked all the doors (at <strong>on</strong>ce)’<br />

b. o sok-d-it-ii baafe ɗe fof<br />

3sg lock-COM-SEP-past doors det all<br />

‘he unlocked all the doors (in sequence)’<br />

The Repetitive -t is ordered after the Comprehensive -d when Repetitive has<br />

scope over Comprehensive, as in (12)a. The fact that Repetitive has scope over<br />

Comprehensive is evidenced by the repetitive meaning in each case applying not <strong>on</strong>ly to<br />

the verb, but also to the participants referred to by the Comprehensive. When<br />

Comprehensive has scope over Repetitive, as in (12)b, the Repetitive -t is ordered first.<br />

The evidence for Comprehensive having scope over Repetitive is that in this example, the<br />

same participants are not necessarily involved in both the original and repeated acti<strong>on</strong>s.<br />

The Repetitive applies <strong>on</strong>ly to the verb, and then the Comprehensive applies to the output<br />

of Repetitive affixati<strong>on</strong>, which is a repeated acti<strong>on</strong>. This is c<strong>on</strong>sistent with the order of<br />

the affixes.<br />

(12) a. min cok-t-id-ii baafal ŋgal<br />

1pl lock-REP-COM-past door det<br />

‘we all locked the door again together’ (some<strong>on</strong>e else locked it before)<br />

b. mi yaa-d-it-ii ’e makko<br />

1sg go-COM-REP-past with 3sg<br />

‘I went with her again’ (I went with her before)<br />

As shown in (13), the Causative -n is ordered after the Separative -t. This is<br />

c<strong>on</strong>sistent with scope, since the Causative refers not to the original acti<strong>on</strong>, but to the<br />

‘undoing’. Thus, Causative applies to a verb that already has the separative meaning,<br />

which is c<strong>on</strong>sistent with the ordering of the Causative -n outside the Separative -t.<br />

240


(13) o haɓɓ-it-in-ii kam ɓoggol ŋgol<br />

3sg tie-SEP-CAU-past 1sg rope det<br />

‘he made me untie the rope’<br />

If order is scope-based, we predict that the opposite order should corresp<strong>on</strong>d to<br />

the opposite scope relati<strong>on</strong>, as was seen above where Separative-Comprehensive and<br />

Repetitive-Comprehensive were combined. In the case of Causative-Separative, however,<br />

it is impossible to find an order alternati<strong>on</strong> corresp<strong>on</strong>ding to a meaning change because it<br />

is apparently impossible for Separative to have scope over Causative. This is explained<br />

by the fact that Separative generally applies to a verb whose semantics involve putting<br />

things together. Thus, in order for Separative to apply to a Causative, the entire Causative<br />

verb would have to have a ‘putting together’ meaning. There are apparently no verbs<br />

corresp<strong>on</strong>ding to ‘make be together’ that use the Causative -n such that a Separative<br />

would be expected to attach to the Causativized stem (see Paster 2005b for details).<br />

When the Repetitive -t combines with the Causative -n, both orderings are<br />

acceptable, corresp<strong>on</strong>ding to scope. When Repetitive has scope over Causative, the<br />

Causative -n precedes the Repetitive -t, as in (14)a. The scope relati<strong>on</strong> is indicated by the<br />

fact that the same agent causes both the original and repeated acti<strong>on</strong>s. Thus, Repetitive<br />

applies to a Causativized verb, corresp<strong>on</strong>ding to the ordering of the Repetitive suffix<br />

outside the Causative. As predicted by scope, the opposite order of the Causative and<br />

Repetitive suffixes corresp<strong>on</strong>ds to the opposite scope relati<strong>on</strong> from (14)a. When<br />

Causative has scope over Repetitive (14)b, the Repetitive -t precedes the Causative -n.<br />

The scope relati<strong>on</strong> is evidenced by the fact that the original acti<strong>on</strong> is understood to have<br />

been d<strong>on</strong>e voluntarily rather than being caused by the same agent who causes the<br />

repeated acti<strong>on</strong>. Thus, Repetitive applies to the bare verb, and Causative applies to the<br />

241


Repetitive verb, meaning that causati<strong>on</strong> applies to the repeated acti<strong>on</strong> and not necessarily<br />

to the original acti<strong>on</strong>.<br />

(14) a. o sood-it-in-ii een deftere nde<br />

3sg buy-REP-CAU-past 1pl book det<br />

‘she made us buy the book again’<br />

b. o sood-in-it-ii een deftere nde<br />

3sg buy-CAU-REP-past 1pl book det<br />

‘she made us buy the book again’ (we bought it before voluntarily)<br />

The relative order of the Separative -t and Modal -r corresp<strong>on</strong>ds to their scope. In<br />

(15), Modal has scope over Separative, as indicated by the fact that the instrument is used<br />

to undo the acti<strong>on</strong> and not necessarily to do the original acti<strong>on</strong>. Thus, the scope of the two<br />

suffixes in this example corresp<strong>on</strong>ds to the ordering of Modal -r outside Separative -t.<br />

(15) a sok-t-ir-ii baafal ŋgal coktirgal<br />

2sg lock-SEP-MOD-past door det key<br />

‘you (sg.) unlocked the door with a key’<br />

It is apparently impossible to produce a single verb form where Separative has<br />

scope over Modal. When asked to produce such a form corresp<strong>on</strong>ding to, e.g., ‘we un-<br />

sewed the shirts with a needle,’ ([we un-[sewed the shirts with a needle]]) where the<br />

needle was used to do the sewing but not the unsewing, the speaker is unable to express<br />

this with a single verb. Therefore, we cannot test the predicti<strong>on</strong> of the scope principle that<br />

Separative should occur after Modal when Separative has scope over Modal.<br />

When Modal has scope over Repetitive (16), -r is ordered after -t, as predicted. It<br />

is clear that Modal has scope over Repetitive here since it is specified that a different<br />

instrument is used in the original vs. repeated acti<strong>on</strong>. Thus, Repetitive applies to the verb<br />

first, and then Modal applies to the Repetitive stem.<br />

242


(16) mi irt-it-ir-ii supu o kuddu goɗɗo<br />

1sg stir-REP-MOD-past soup det spo<strong>on</strong> different<br />

‘I stirred the soup again with a different spo<strong>on</strong>’<br />

When Repetitive has scope over Modal, the Modal -r suffix is ordered after the<br />

Repetitive -t suffix, as shown in (17).<br />

(17) mi udd-it-ir-ii baafal ŋgal sawru<br />

1sg close-REP-MOD-past door det stick<br />

‘I closed the door with a stick again’ (the same stick)<br />

This is the first example we have seen where the affix order does not corresp<strong>on</strong>d to<br />

scope. Based <strong>on</strong> scope, we expect Repetitive -t to be ordered after Modal -r here. We<br />

know that Repetitive has scope over Modal because it is understood that the same<br />

instrument is used for both the original and repeated acti<strong>on</strong>s. 10 This corresp<strong>on</strong>ds to the<br />

applicati<strong>on</strong> of Modal to the verb root, and then applicati<strong>on</strong> of Repetitive to the verb that<br />

already has an instrument so that the repeated acti<strong>on</strong> involves the use of the same<br />

instrument. Since this order has no apparent semantic explanati<strong>on</strong>, I assume the -t-r order<br />

is part of a morphological template. We will account for this in the analysis in §5.4.3.1.4.<br />

The order of the Causative -n with the Comprehensive -d is scope-based. When<br />

Comprehensive has scope over Causative, Causative -n precedes the Comprehensive -d,<br />

as in (18)a. When Causative has scope over Comprehensive, the Causative -n is ordered<br />

after the Comprehensive -d as predicted. However, the opposite ordering, -n-d, is also<br />

compatible with this reading, as in (18)b. This may be due to the difficulty of<br />

10<br />

It is possible that the ‘same instrument’ reading is arrived at c<strong>on</strong>textually, since this<br />

would likely be the default interpretati<strong>on</strong> of ‘I closed the door with a stick again’ in, e.g.,<br />

English. However, (17) c<strong>on</strong>trasts crucially with the type of example seen in (16), where<br />

the c<strong>on</strong>sultant states specifically that a different instrument is used in the original vs.<br />

repeated acti<strong>on</strong>. Unfortunately I do not have any Modal-Repetitive sentences that differ<br />

minimally in this respect (using exactly the same verb and instrument), but there are<br />

parallel cases involving the Modal and Comprehensive ((19)a and b) which do show a<br />

minimal difference in the same vs. different instrument reading.<br />

243


c<strong>on</strong>structing English stimuli where Causative has unambiguous scope over<br />

Comprehensive. When the speaker is given with English sentences like this, he may<br />

interpret them so that Comprehensive has over Causative, explaining why -n-d is<br />

accepted. The meaning difference is subtle, and this should be investigated in<br />

c<strong>on</strong>versati<strong>on</strong> or narratives.<br />

(18) a. ɓe njal-n-id-ii mo<br />

3pl laugh-CAU-COM-past 3sg<br />

‘we all made him laugh together’<br />

b. mi woy-d-in-ii ɓe ~ mi woy-n-id-ii ɓe<br />

1sg cry-COM-CAU-past 3pl<br />

‘I made them cry together’<br />

When the Comprehensive combines with the Modal so that Comprehensive has<br />

scope over Modal, Comprehensive -d is ordered after Modal -r, as in (19)a. The scope<br />

relati<strong>on</strong> is indicated by the fact that a different instrument is used to perform the acti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong><br />

each object. When Modal has scope over Comprehensive, as in (19)b, Modal -r is<br />

ordered after Comprehensive -d. The fact that Modal has scope over Comprehensive here<br />

is clear since the same instrument is used to perform the acti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> each object. This is<br />

c<strong>on</strong>sistent with the applicati<strong>on</strong> of Modal to a stem already having the comprehensive<br />

meaning so that the instrument applies to all of the objects referred to by the<br />

Comprehensive.<br />

(19) a. mi sok-r-id-ii baafe ɗe coktirgal goɗŋgal<br />

1sg lock-MOD-COM-past doors det key different<br />

‘I locked each of the doors with a different key’<br />

b. mi sok-d-ir-ii baafe ɗe coktirgal<br />

1sg lock-COM-MOD-past doors det key<br />

‘I locked all of the doors with a key’ (the same key)<br />

244


The final pairwise combinati<strong>on</strong> of suffixes shows variati<strong>on</strong>. When Causative has<br />

scope over Modal, we expect -n to come after -r. We do find this order corresp<strong>on</strong>ding to<br />

this scope reading, but the opposite order can also be used, as in (20)a; either order is<br />

allowed with no meaning difference. We find the same variati<strong>on</strong> when Modal has scope<br />

over Causative, as in (20)b. Here, we expect Modal -r to be ordered after Causative -n,<br />

but the opposite order can also be used. Our analysis will need to account for this.<br />

(20) a. o irt-ir-in-ii kam supu o kuddu ~<br />

3sg stir-MOD-CAU-past 1sg soup det spo<strong>on</strong><br />

o irt-in-ir-ii kam supu o kuddu<br />

3sg stir-CAU-MOD-past 1sg soup det spo<strong>on</strong><br />

‘he made me stir the soup with a spo<strong>on</strong>’ (I used a spo<strong>on</strong>)<br />

b. o irt-in-ir-ii kam supu o laɓi ~<br />

3sg stir-CAU-MOD-past 1sg soup det knife<br />

o irt-ir-in-ii kam supu o laɓi<br />

3sg stir-MOD-CAU-past 1sg soup det knife<br />

‘he made me stir the soup with a knife’ (he used a knife)<br />

This exhausts the pairwise combinati<strong>on</strong>s of the c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal suffixes. Based <strong>on</strong><br />

these examples, we have three generalizati<strong>on</strong>s about the order of c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal suffixes in<br />

Fuuta Tooro (21). In §5.4.3.1.4 I propose an analysis to account for these generalizati<strong>on</strong>s.<br />

(21) a. Repetitive -t precedes Modal -r regardless of their relative scope.<br />

b. Causative -n and Modal -r are freely ordered with each other regardless of<br />

scope.<br />

c. Otherwise, order is determined by scope.<br />

5.4.3.1.4 A scope-template account of Fuuta Tooro affix order<br />

Rice (2000) claims that scope determines the order of affixes whenever there is a<br />

scope relati<strong>on</strong> between them. Otherwise, order is arbitrary. Templates are ‘emergent’; in<br />

OT terms, SCOPE always outranks TEMPLATE. However, a language with scope-based<br />

245


order can have elements of fixed order that override scope, as seen above. This follows<br />

from TEMPLATE >> SCOPE; a ranking I use in the analysis of Fuuta Tooro affix order<br />

below.<br />

In this analysis, I break TEMPLATE into three separate c<strong>on</strong>straints, shown below.<br />

(22) TREP PRECEDES R: Repetitive -t precedes Modal -r.<br />

N PRECEDES R: Causative -n precedes Modal -r.<br />

R PRECEDES N: Modal -r precedes Causative -n.<br />

The observed affix order effects will be analyzed by ranking these templatic c<strong>on</strong>straints<br />

above SCOPE so that scope determines the order of affixes as l<strong>on</strong>g as the template is not<br />

violated; when scope and the template c<strong>on</strong>flict, the template ‘wins’.<br />

The ranking TREP PRECEDES R >> SCOPE successfully selects forms where the<br />

template and scope agree, as shown in the tableau in (23).<br />

(23) mi irt-it-ir-ii supu o kuddu goɗɗo ‘I stirred the soup again with a different spo<strong>on</strong>’<br />

/irt, -t, -r/ TREP PRECEDES R SCOPE<br />

irt-it-ir-<br />

irt-ir-it- *! *<br />

Since the repeated acti<strong>on</strong> is not d<strong>on</strong>e with the same instrument as the original acti<strong>on</strong>,<br />

Modal has scope over Repetitive, and therefore we expect Modal -r to be ordered after<br />

Repetitive -t. This is the order that is selected since SCOPE agrees with the template.<br />

This ranking also selects forms where TEMPLATE forces a violati<strong>on</strong> of SCOPE (24).<br />

(24) mi udd-it-ir-ii baafal ŋgal ‘I closed the door with a stick again’ (same stick)<br />

/udd, -t, -r/ TREP PRECEDES R SCOPE<br />

udd-it-ir- *<br />

udd-ir-it- *!<br />

The scope order is -r-t since Repetitive outscopes Modal (the same instrument is used in<br />

the original and repeated acti<strong>on</strong>s), but the -t-r order is selected by TREP PRECEDES R.<br />

246


The order of -n and -r is handled by variable ranking. In ranking #1, N PRECEDES<br />

R >> R PRECEDES N, SCOPE. This selects forms where -n precedes -r (25).<br />

(25) o irt-in-ir-ii kam supu o laɓi ‘he made me stir the soup with a knife’ (he used a knife)<br />

/irt, -n, -r/ N PRECEDES R R PRECEDES N SCOPE<br />

irt-in-ir- *<br />

irt-ir-in- *! *<br />

Here, the order predicted by scope is -n-r, since Modal has scope over Causative (the<br />

causer, not the causee, uses the instrument). Since this agrees with the high-ranked N<br />

PRECEDES R c<strong>on</strong>straint, the winning candidate also satisfies SCOPE.<br />

Our ranking also selects forms where SCOPE is violated (26).<br />

(26) o irt-in-ir-ii kam supu o kuddu ‘he made me stir the soup with a spo<strong>on</strong>’ (I used a spo<strong>on</strong>)<br />

/irt, -r, -n/ N PRECEDES R R PRECEDES N SCOPE<br />

irt-in-ir- * *<br />

irt-ir-in- *!<br />

The scope order is -r-n since Causative has scope over Modal (the causee uses the<br />

instrument), but since N PRECEDES R outranks SCOPE, the n<strong>on</strong>-scope -n-r order wins.<br />

In ranking #2, R PRECEDES N outranks N PRECEDES R and SCOPE. This selects<br />

forms with the Modal -r preceding the Causative -n regardless of scope. As seen in the<br />

tableau in (27), this ranking selects forms where the template and scope agree.<br />

(27) o irt-ir-in-ii kam supu ’o kuddu ‘he made me stir the soup with a spo<strong>on</strong>’ (I used a spo<strong>on</strong>)<br />

/irt, -r, -n/ R PRECEDES N N PRECEDES R SCOPE<br />

irt-in-ir- *! *<br />

irt-ir-in- *<br />

Here, the scope order is -r-n since Causative has scope over Modal (the causee uses the<br />

instrument). This agrees with R PRECEDES N, so the winner obeys SCOPE as well.<br />

This ranking also selects forms where scope and the template disagree, so that the<br />

winning candidate obeys the template at the expense of a scope violati<strong>on</strong> (28).<br />

247


(28) o irt-ir-in-ii kam supu ’o laɓi ‘he made me stir the soup with a knife’ (he used a knife)<br />

/irt, -n, -r/ R PRECEDES N N PRECEDES R SCOPE<br />

irt-in-ir- *!<br />

irt-ir-in- * *<br />

Here, the scope-based order is -n-r since the causer uses the instrument. However,<br />

because R PRECEDES N outranks SCOPE, the winning candidate has the -r-n order.<br />

The two c<strong>on</strong>straint rankings are summarized below.<br />

(29) Ranking #1: TREP PRECEDES R, N PRECEDES R >> R PRECEDES N, SCOPE<br />

Ranking #2: TREP PRECEDES R, R PRECEDES N >> N PRECEDES R, SCOPE<br />

By using template c<strong>on</strong>straints and SCOPE, all M c<strong>on</strong>straints, we have captured the order<br />

of c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal suffixes in Fuuta Tooro without P >> M. We will now revisit Gombe<br />

Fula, and I will show that a scope-based analysis is possible for that dialect as well.<br />

5.4.3.1.5 A scope-based reanalysis of Gombe Fula<br />

As menti<strong>on</strong>ed earlier, every example provided by Arnott (1970) is c<strong>on</strong>sistent with<br />

scope. Though most of Arnott’s examples obey the ‘TDNR’, they are also c<strong>on</strong>sistent with<br />

scope. For instance, -t-r in (30) is a ‘TDNR’ order. However, the order is also c<strong>on</strong>sistent<br />

with scope, since the adverb ‘slowly,’ introduced by Modal, applies to the Reversive<br />

acti<strong>on</strong>, not the original acti<strong>on</strong>. The Modal applies to a verb to which Reversive has<br />

already applied, corresp<strong>on</strong>ding to the ordering of the Modal -r outside the Reversive -t.<br />

(30) ’o maɓɓ-it-ir-ii yolnde hakkiilo<br />

3sg close-REV-MOD-past door slowly<br />

‘he opened the door slowly’ (Arnott 1970: 367)<br />

(31) is also c<strong>on</strong>sistent with both scope and the ‘TDNR’ generalizati<strong>on</strong>. Here, the order<br />

corresp<strong>on</strong>ds directly to the order of logical operati<strong>on</strong>s performed <strong>on</strong> the root. First, the<br />

Denominative -ɗ attaches to the adjective, c<strong>on</strong>verting it into a verb meaning ‘be healthy’.<br />

248


Then, the Repetitive -t applies to this stem, yielding a new stem meaning ‘be healthy<br />

again’ (=‘be cured’). Next, the Causative -n applies, resulting in a stem meaning ‘make<br />

be cured’ (=‘cure’). Finally, the Modal -r attaches to this stem, introducing an instrument,<br />

giving the meaning ‘cure with (some new medicine)’. The order of attachment of the<br />

affixes is reflected in the order of the suffixes: -t-n-r (Repetitive-Causative-Modal).<br />

(31) ’o yam-ɗ-it-in-ir-ii mo lekki gokki kesi<br />

3sgi healthy-DEN-[REP]-CAU-MOD-past 3sgj medicine other new<br />

‘hei cured himj with some new medicine’ (Arnott 1970: 368)<br />

Thus, the ordering generalizati<strong>on</strong> that Arnott (1970) accounts for using the ‘TDNR’<br />

generalizati<strong>on</strong> can also be accounted for by scope. The two examples shown above are<br />

the clearest examples, but no example c<strong>on</strong>tradicts the scope generalizati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

Not <strong>on</strong>ly does scope account for Arnott’s (1970) examples obeying the ‘TDNR’<br />

generalizati<strong>on</strong>, but it also accounts for the ‘excepti<strong>on</strong>s’, which Arnott explained as having<br />

lexicalized stems. Several of Arnott’s excepti<strong>on</strong>s can be explained straightforwardly<br />

based <strong>on</strong> scope. In (32), Repetitive has scope over Comitative.<br />

(32) mi wol-d-it-at-aa ’e maɓɓe<br />

1sg speak-COM-REP-future-negative with 3pl<br />

‘I w<strong>on</strong>’t speak with them again’ (Arnott 1970: 368)<br />

Ignoring the Negative, the form mi-wol-d-it-ii ’e maɓɓe ‘I spoke with them again’ would<br />

mean that the subject had spoken with ‘them’ before and did so again. This can be<br />

schematized as [[speak with] again]. Thus, the order of the affixes corresp<strong>on</strong>ds to scope.<br />

Similarly, in (33), the Comitative -d has scope over Causative -n, since the word<br />

‘fed’ is used in the English translati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

(33) ’o nyaam-n-id-ii ɗi<br />

3sg eat-CAU-COM-past 3pl<br />

‘he fed them all’ (Arnott 1970: 368)<br />

249


Once again, an apparent excepti<strong>on</strong> is explained straightforwardly based <strong>on</strong> scope.<br />

Finally, in (34), Retaliative has scope over the Causative since the term ‘frighten’<br />

in the English gloss means ‘cause to fear’. The interpretati<strong>on</strong> is [[cause to fear] in turn],<br />

which corresp<strong>on</strong>ds to the -n-t order, which disobeys the ‘TDNR’ generalizati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

(34) mi hul-n-it-oo mo<br />

1sg fear-CAU-RET-future 3sg<br />

‘I’ll frighten him in turn’ (Arnott 1970: 368)<br />

Since some of Arnott’s excepti<strong>on</strong>al forms are explained by scope, and n<strong>on</strong>e of his<br />

examples c<strong>on</strong>tradict scope, we can say that Arnott provided no evidence for a n<strong>on</strong>-scope<br />

principle in the order of c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal suffixes. The scope-based analysis allows an<br />

explanati<strong>on</strong> of the ‘excepti<strong>on</strong>al’ forms, which Arnott ignored. It also avoids the problem<br />

that the meaning of Arnott’s lexicalized stems is derived straightforwardly from their<br />

comp<strong>on</strong>ent parts rather than being idiomatic as ‘frozen’ forms often are.<br />

Thus, we have seen that neither Fuuta Tooro Pulaar nor Gombe Fula exhibits<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological affix order. In each dialect, the order of c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>antal suffixes is scope-based,<br />

with some excepti<strong>on</strong>s in Fuuta Tooro that are not ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed.<br />

Recall from §5.4.2 that <strong>on</strong>ly four other possible cases of ph<strong>on</strong>ological affix order<br />

were uncovered in this study, and no example was particularly compelling. Thus, with<br />

this alternative explanati<strong>on</strong> for the Fula/Pulaar example, we now appear to have no<br />

examples of ph<strong>on</strong>ological affix order requiring P >> M. This significantly weakens the<br />

case for P >> M, since a major predicti<strong>on</strong> of this model is not substantiated cross-<br />

linguistically.<br />

250


5.5 Infixati<strong>on</strong><br />

Yu (2003) critiques what he terms the Displacement Theory (DT) account of infix<br />

placement, exemplified by the Prosodic Optimizati<strong>on</strong> approach of McCarthy and Prince<br />

(1993b). The idea behind this approach is that, under the P >> M ranking schema,<br />

infixati<strong>on</strong> is accounted for by ranking prosodic well-formedness c<strong>on</strong>straints ahead of the<br />

morphological c<strong>on</strong>straints that state whether a given affix is a prefix or suffix (under this<br />

model, no affix is an underlying infix). In the original incarnati<strong>on</strong> of the Prosodic<br />

Optimizati<strong>on</strong> approach, alignment c<strong>on</strong>straints were gradiently violable, so that a violati<strong>on</strong><br />

was incurred for each segment by which a prefix or suffix strayed into the root from its<br />

underlying, peripheral positi<strong>on</strong>. Subsequently, McCarthy (2003) has revised the model so<br />

that c<strong>on</strong>straints can <strong>on</strong>ly be violated categorically.<br />

Yu (2003) argues that the Prosodic Optimizati<strong>on</strong> approach to infixati<strong>on</strong> makes<br />

several inaccurate predicti<strong>on</strong>s. The first is that affixes should surface as infixes <strong>on</strong>ly if the<br />

result is prosodically better-formed than if the affix had surfaced in its underlying,<br />

peripheral positi<strong>on</strong>. C<strong>on</strong>trary to this predicti<strong>on</strong>, Yu finds several cases in his survey of<br />

141 examples of infixati<strong>on</strong> in 101 languages where certain affixes are obligatorily<br />

infixed, never surfacing in what McCarthy and Prince would claim to be their underlying<br />

prefixed or suffixed positi<strong>on</strong>s. Alabama, Archi, and Tagalog (in the pluracti<strong>on</strong>al affix) are<br />

cited as having such infixes. An analysis where an affix that invariably surfaces as an<br />

infix is treated as a formal prefix or suffix is counterintuitive and unnecessarily abstract<br />

in comparis<strong>on</strong> to the alternative, that these are underlying infixes. This criticism holds not<br />

of the P >> M ranking schema in general, but of McCarthy and Prince’s use of it in a<br />

model specific to infixati<strong>on</strong>. N<strong>on</strong>etheless, since my overarching purpose is to c<strong>on</strong>trast the<br />

251


subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach as a coherent model with the P >> M schema as part of a<br />

coherent model, I am focusing <strong>on</strong> predicti<strong>on</strong>s of P >> M as it has been employed in the<br />

mainstream literature, not <strong>on</strong> predicti<strong>on</strong>s that would be made under some different use of<br />

P >> M. Therefore, I take this problem with the Prosodic Optimizati<strong>on</strong> account of<br />

infixati<strong>on</strong> to be a shortcoming of the P >> M schema as a whole.<br />

A sec<strong>on</strong>d inaccurate predicti<strong>on</strong> of Prosodic Optimizati<strong>on</strong> pointed out by Yu<br />

(2003) is that infixati<strong>on</strong> should always result from c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s of prosodic well-<br />

formedness. Yu points out that prosodic optimizati<strong>on</strong> is not sufficient to account even for<br />

languages where an affix occurs <strong>on</strong>ly sometimes as an infix. In some such languages, a P<br />

>> M account for infix placement works <strong>on</strong>ly if the P c<strong>on</strong>straint is an Edge Avoidance<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straint. Edge Avoidance may be c<strong>on</strong>strued as optimizing (certainly it can be made into<br />

an OT c<strong>on</strong>straint), but it cannot be said to increase ph<strong>on</strong>ological well-formedness. Thus,<br />

the Prosodic Optimizati<strong>on</strong> model at least has to be weakened enough to allow an Edge<br />

Avoidance c<strong>on</strong>straint to be the P c<strong>on</strong>straint in the relevant P >> M ranking. Here again,<br />

this incorrect predicti<strong>on</strong> is not made by P >> M in general, but by the implementati<strong>on</strong> of<br />

it in which the P c<strong>on</strong>straint has to be a well-formedness c<strong>on</strong>straint.<br />

In additi<strong>on</strong> to these two ways in which the Prosodic Optimizati<strong>on</strong> account<br />

undergenerates, Yu argues that this approach also overgenerates. Namely, it predicts what<br />

Yu calls ‘hyperinfixati<strong>on</strong>’, where an affix that underlyingly bel<strong>on</strong>gs at <strong>on</strong>e edge of a root<br />

migrates any number of segments towards the opposite edge, even going so far as to<br />

surface <strong>on</strong> the opposite periphery. For example, a formal prefix might surface just <strong>on</strong>e<br />

segment in from the right edge of the root or even as a suffix. But hyperinfixati<strong>on</strong> is not<br />

attested in any of the languages in Yu’s (2003) broad cross-linguistic survey of languages<br />

252


exhibiting infixati<strong>on</strong>. Yu points out that there are ways to avoid hyperinfixati<strong>on</strong> using the<br />

proper c<strong>on</strong>straints and rankings, but questi<strong>on</strong>s why we should need special mechanisms<br />

to rule out hyperinfixati<strong>on</strong> given that it apparently never occurs in any language.<br />

A possible example of hyperinfixati<strong>on</strong> not discussed by Yu (2003) is the<br />

phenomen<strong>on</strong> better known as mobile affixati<strong>on</strong>. ‘Mobile’ affixes, which occur sometimes<br />

as prefixes and sometimes as suffixes depending <strong>on</strong> the ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>text, have been<br />

documented in Huave (Noyer 1994) and Afar (Fulmer 1991). Under the Prosodic<br />

Optimizati<strong>on</strong> approach, mobile affixati<strong>on</strong> can receive the same treatment as infixati<strong>on</strong><br />

and could be c<strong>on</strong>strued as hyperinfixati<strong>on</strong>. However, if this is to be counted as extreme<br />

hyperinfixati<strong>on</strong>, then we are left with the puzzling questi<strong>on</strong> of why there are no ‘in-<br />

between’ cases. That is, if an underlying prefix can surface as a suffix or vice versa, then<br />

why do we not find any examples of an underlying prefix surfacing as an infix at the far<br />

right edge of the word? The lack of such examples suggests that Huave and Afar are<br />

better treated as cases of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy, where <strong>on</strong>e<br />

allomorph is a prefix and the other is a suffix. As cases of PCSA, Huave and Afar are<br />

unusual in that the separate allomorphs are identical in shape and differ <strong>on</strong>ly in their<br />

positi<strong>on</strong> with respect to the stem. However, they differ <strong>on</strong>ly minimally from Chimariko,<br />

which, as described by C<strong>on</strong>athan 2002, has a phenomen<strong>on</strong> similar to mobile affixati<strong>on</strong><br />

except that the prefix and suffix allomorphs are slightly ph<strong>on</strong>ologically different from<br />

each other, making it clear that this is a case of suppletive allomorphy rather than a single<br />

affix occurring in different positi<strong>on</strong>s. Thus, within what I c<strong>on</strong>sider to be PCSA, there are<br />

cases where two or more different ph<strong>on</strong>ologically selected allomorps occur in the same<br />

positi<strong>on</strong> (as in most of the examples described in chapters 2, 3, and 4), cases where two<br />

253


or more differently shaped allomorphs occur in different positi<strong>on</strong>s in the word (as in<br />

Chimariko), and cases where identical allomorphs occur in different positi<strong>on</strong>s in the word<br />

(Huave and Afar). Since mobile affixes in Huave and Afar never surface as infixes, they<br />

should not be counted as cases of hyperinfixati<strong>on</strong>, and therefore the Prosodic<br />

Optimizati<strong>on</strong> model still overgenerates in predicting this phenomen<strong>on</strong>.<br />

5.6 C<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong><br />

In this chapter, I have discussed some predicti<strong>on</strong>s of the P >> M ranking schema<br />

for several different phenomena: affix order, infixati<strong>on</strong>, morphological gaps, empty<br />

morphs, and reduplicati<strong>on</strong>. Those phenomena for which significant cross-linguistic data<br />

are available show that the P >> M model makes many predicti<strong>on</strong>s that are inaccurate,<br />

which offers further substantiati<strong>on</strong> for the point made in chapter 1 that the P >> M model<br />

makes incorrect predicti<strong>on</strong>s for ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy<br />

(PCSA). We have seen that in each of the logically possible effects of ph<strong>on</strong>ology <strong>on</strong><br />

affixati<strong>on</strong>, the P >> M predicts a wider range of effects than are actually attested, and yet<br />

there are also instances in which P >> M fails to predict or account for certain types of<br />

effects (for example, opaquely c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed PCSA (chapters 2-4), and infixes that always<br />

surface as infixes but never as peripheral affixes (§5.5)). Thus, the P >> M model both<br />

over- and undergenerates in the domain of several different phenomena at the ph<strong>on</strong>ology-<br />

morphology interface.<br />

254


Chapter 6: C<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong><br />

In this dissertati<strong>on</strong>, I have presented a survey of examples of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppletive allomorphy (PCSA). In chapters 2, 3, and 4, I discussed examples<br />

of PCSA c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by segments and features, t<strong>on</strong>e/stress, and prosodic elements,<br />

respectively. In each of these chapters, typological generalizati<strong>on</strong>s were drawn for each<br />

type of PCSA, and these generalizati<strong>on</strong>s were compared with predicti<strong>on</strong>s made by two<br />

competing models of ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong>, namely, the P >> M<br />

approach and the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach. It was argued that the survey results for<br />

PCSA are more c<strong>on</strong>sistent with subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> than with P >> M. In chapter 5, I laid<br />

out the predicti<strong>on</strong>s of P >> M for types of ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong> other<br />

than PCSA. It was shown that results for each of these other types of effects c<strong>on</strong>verge<br />

up<strong>on</strong> the same c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> drawn here, that the P >> M model both over- and<br />

underpredicts with respect to the range of ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong> found in<br />

the world’s languages. The subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach, <strong>on</strong> the other hand, is compatible<br />

with the cross-linguistic findings and is therefore a superior model of ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

In this chapter, I summarize the findings and arguments presented throughout the<br />

dissertati<strong>on</strong>. I begin in §6.1 with a summary of the predicti<strong>on</strong>s of the P >> M and<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approaches. Then, in §6.2, I summarize the survey results presented in<br />

chapters 2-4. In §6.3, I discuss the theoretical implicati<strong>on</strong>s of both the survey of PCSA<br />

and the findings for other types of ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong>. In §6.4, I<br />

c<strong>on</strong>sider and argue against a ‘hybrid model’ using both subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> and P >> M,.<br />

§6.5 provides arguments in favor of a particular way of eliminating the possibility of P<br />

255


M in an OT grammar. Finally, in §6.6, I c<strong>on</strong>clude with some suggested directi<strong>on</strong>s for<br />

future research <strong>on</strong> ph<strong>on</strong>ological effects in morphology.<br />

6.1 Summary of predicti<strong>on</strong>s<br />

In chapter 1, I laid out the general predicti<strong>on</strong>s of the P >> M and<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approaches. In this secti<strong>on</strong>, I reiterate those predicti<strong>on</strong>s before<br />

summarizing the cross-linguistic findings in §6.2.<br />

As discussed in chapter 1, the predicti<strong>on</strong>s of P >> M for PCSA can be<br />

summarized as in (1) below (repeated from chapter 1, §1.1.1.2).<br />

(1) a. PCSA is ‘optimizing’ and analyzable using preexisting P c<strong>on</strong>straints<br />

b. PCSA is sensitive to ph<strong>on</strong>ological elements in surface forms, not underlying<br />

forms<br />

c. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing between stem and affix can be bidirecti<strong>on</strong>al<br />

d. <str<strong>on</strong>g>C<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> allomorph selecti<strong>on</strong> can be located anywhere in the word<br />

Predicti<strong>on</strong> (1)a means that the P c<strong>on</strong>straints used to model PCSA in a P >> M account<br />

should be motivated elsewhere, either in the language being analyzed or as a widely<br />

attested c<strong>on</strong>straint in other languages. Predicti<strong>on</strong> (1)b indicates that PCSA should result<br />

in surface-true generalizati<strong>on</strong>s about allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong>, since allomorph selecti<strong>on</strong> is<br />

handled simultaneously with regular ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes. By predicti<strong>on</strong> (1)c, the<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s determining allomorph distributi<strong>on</strong> are expected to come from morphemes<br />

that are either closer to or farther from the root than the affix undergoing the allomorphy,<br />

since as discussed in chapter 1, standard P >> M analyses do not observe morphological<br />

bracketing. Finally, predicti<strong>on</strong> (1)d states that c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> PCSA are not limited to stem<br />

edges and can instead be located anywhere in the word. This means, for example, that<br />

prefix allomorphy could be c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by a stem-final segment, or suffix allomorphy<br />

256


could be triggered by a stem-initial segment, or allomorphy in a peripheral affix could be<br />

triggered by some element in the middle of the stem.<br />

The predicti<strong>on</strong>s of the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> model for PCSA, also discussed in<br />

chapter 1, are summarized below.<br />

(2) a. PCSA is not always ph<strong>on</strong>ologically optimizing<br />

b. PCSA is sensitive to ph<strong>on</strong>ological elements in underlying/input forms, not surface<br />

forms<br />

c. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> PCSA can come <strong>on</strong>ly from the ‘inside’<br />

d. Affix allomorphs occur adjacent to the ph<strong>on</strong>ological elements of stems that<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> their distributi<strong>on</strong><br />

Predicti<strong>on</strong> (2)a means that we should find some examples of PCSA in which the<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong> of allomorphs does not optimize words. This is in c<strong>on</strong>tradicti<strong>on</strong> to predicti<strong>on</strong><br />

(1)a, made by the P >> M approach, that PCSA can be accounted for by using established<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological well-formedness c<strong>on</strong>straints. Predicti<strong>on</strong> (2)b means that we should find<br />

instances in which PCSA is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed crucially by an input element that does not<br />

surface, rendering the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> allomorphy opaque. This can be c<strong>on</strong>trasted with<br />

predicti<strong>on</strong> (1)b, made by P >> M, that PCSA should be sensitive to surface elements. If<br />

predicti<strong>on</strong> (2)c is correct, we should find that PCSA in an affix can be c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed <strong>on</strong>ly<br />

by a property of the root or another affix closer to the root, and never to an affix farther<br />

from the root. On the other hand, as discussed above, the P >> M model predicts the<br />

existence of c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing from both the ‘inside’ and the ‘outside’ (predicti<strong>on</strong> (1)c).<br />

Finally, predicti<strong>on</strong> (2)d states that affixes should be c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by the part of the stem to<br />

which they are immediately adjacent. This means that we expect prefixes to be<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed <strong>on</strong>ly by elements at the left edge of the stem, and suffixes to be c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed<br />

<strong>on</strong>ly by elements at the right edge of the stem. In c<strong>on</strong>trast, as discussed above, P >> M<br />

257


predicts that we should find examples that do not obey this kind of locality restricti<strong>on</strong><br />

(predicti<strong>on</strong> (2)d).<br />

This c<strong>on</strong>cludes the general summary of predicti<strong>on</strong>s of the P >> M and<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approaches. As can be seen, the predicti<strong>on</strong>s outlined here c<strong>on</strong>stitute<br />

clear-cut differences between P >> M and subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>. The reader should keep<br />

these different predicti<strong>on</strong>s in mind when c<strong>on</strong>sidering the survey results from chapters 2-4,<br />

which will be discussed in the following secti<strong>on</strong>.<br />

6.2 Summary of survey results<br />

In chapters 2-4, I presented the results of a cross-linguistic survey of examples of<br />

PCSA. One hundred thirty-seven examples were found in 67 different languages, in a<br />

survey of sources <strong>on</strong> 600 languages. Here, I summarize the findings of the survey.<br />

The examples in chapter 2 involve c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing by segments or features. Several<br />

important generalizati<strong>on</strong>s were drawn regarding these examples. As was seen in chapter<br />

2 (§2.1.2), it appears that the C/V distincti<strong>on</strong> or the presence of any ph<strong>on</strong>ological feature<br />

of a segment can c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> PCSA. The c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing segment or feature is always at the<br />

same edge of the stem where PCSA occurs. Thus, PCSA in a prefix is triggered by stem-<br />

initial segments or features, while PCSA in a suffix is triggered by stem-final segments or<br />

features. It was also found that c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing always comes from an element closer to the<br />

root; for instance, if a suffix undergoes allomorphy, then this can be triggered by a suffix<br />

to its left or by the root itself, but it apparently cannot be triggered by a suffix to its right.<br />

In this chapter, all of the examples involve allomorphy in an affix or clitic c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by<br />

a stem. Another important finding is that there are several cases in which PCSA does not<br />

258


appear to be optimizing (§2.1.2.5), and where the relati<strong>on</strong>ship between the allomorphs<br />

and their distributi<strong>on</strong> instead seems arbitrary. Finally, examples were found where the<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> PCSA was made opaque by a ph<strong>on</strong>ological process (§2.1.2.6), such that the<br />

original c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> allomorphy was lost or changed in the surface form. As was<br />

discussed, this shows that PCSA is sensitive to input ph<strong>on</strong>ological elements rather than<br />

output elements.<br />

Chapter 3 presented cases of PCSA c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by t<strong>on</strong>e or stress. A general<br />

observati<strong>on</strong> about these cases is that very few examples were uncovered by the survey.<br />

N<strong>on</strong>etheless, the existence of some examples does dem<strong>on</strong>strate that t<strong>on</strong>e and stress can<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> PCSA. As with the examples in chapter 2, c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing by stress or t<strong>on</strong>e is<br />

always at the edge of the stem at which the allomorphy occurs. Another interesting<br />

finding in chapter 3 is that there seem to exist some instances of stem PCSA (§3.1.1.2),<br />

though they are few. These examples were rec<strong>on</strong>ciled with the generalizati<strong>on</strong> that<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing comes from the ‘inside’, so the generalizati<strong>on</strong> can still be maintained. An<br />

example from Spanish was discussed (§3.1.1.1) in which the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> allomorph<br />

distributi<strong>on</strong> are opaque <strong>on</strong> the surface, just as in the examples from chapter 2 menti<strong>on</strong>ed<br />

above. Finally, some examples of t<strong>on</strong>e or stress-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy were argued to<br />

be n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing (§3.1.1.4), since no well-motivated ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint could be<br />

identified as possibly being resp<strong>on</strong>sible for the allomorphy.<br />

In chapter 4, I discussed examples of PCSA c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by prosodic elements,<br />

namely, moras, syllables, and feet. Many examples were found, and the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s in<br />

these examples tended to be overall properties of words rather than individual elements at<br />

the edge of the stem. Still, the locality generalizati<strong>on</strong> discussed above is still maintained<br />

259


in these examples. Overall properties of the stem count as properties at the edge, since no<br />

material intervenes between the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing factor (e.g., all of the syllables of the stem)<br />

and the affix undergoing allomorphy. As in chapters 2 and 3, the examples in chapter 4<br />

involve c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing by elements closer to the root; no instances of stem allomorphy<br />

were found here. Some examples were discussed in which, as in chapters 2 and 3,<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> PCSA are made opaque due to regular ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes (see, for<br />

instance, the Ngiyambaa example in §4.2.1). There are also several examples of PCSA in<br />

chapter 4 in which the allomorphy appears to be n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing (§4.1.1.3). It is<br />

acknowledged that, relative to chapters 2 and 3, a higher percentage of the examples in<br />

chapter 4 appear to have some optimizing character. For this reas<strong>on</strong>, in chapter 4 I<br />

investigated in more detail a large set of related examples from the Pama-Nyungan<br />

languages of Australia involving allomorphy in the ergative suffix (§4.2). Several of<br />

these languages exhibit allomorphy that appears to optimize words, but many do not; in<br />

this discussi<strong>on</strong> I showed how a historical understanding of such examples can explain the<br />

apparent optimizati<strong>on</strong> effects while allowing for the n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing examples.<br />

I have summarized the cross-linguistic findings for PCSA that were presented in<br />

chapters 2-4. In the following secti<strong>on</strong>, I compare these findings with the predicti<strong>on</strong>s<br />

discussed in §6.1 and discuss the theoretical implicati<strong>on</strong>s of this comparis<strong>on</strong>.<br />

6.3 Summary of theoretical implicati<strong>on</strong>s<br />

In §6.1, I summarized the predicti<strong>on</strong>s for PCSA that are made by P >> M and<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>. Then, in §6.2, I summarized the results of the cross-linguistic survey<br />

of PCSA. In this secti<strong>on</strong>, I compare how well the predicti<strong>on</strong>s in §6.1 corresp<strong>on</strong>d to the<br />

260


cross-linguistic generalizati<strong>on</strong>s for PCSA in §6.2, dem<strong>on</strong>strating that the<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach fares better than the P >> M approach in this comparis<strong>on</strong>. I<br />

c<strong>on</strong>clude this secti<strong>on</strong> by summarizing the theoretical implicati<strong>on</strong>s of the comparis<strong>on</strong>, and<br />

also the implicati<strong>on</strong>s of the findings discussed in chapter 5 for other types of<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

First, regarding the predicti<strong>on</strong>s for PCSA, it appears that the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

model is a better predictor of the attested examples, based <strong>on</strong> the present survey. This can<br />

be assessed in terms of the four major predicti<strong>on</strong>s made by each model. The first of these<br />

deals with ph<strong>on</strong>ological optimizati<strong>on</strong>. The P >> M approach, since it uses regular<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straints, predicts that every case of PCSA should be ph<strong>on</strong>ologically<br />

optimizing with respect to an established ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint (predicti<strong>on</strong> (1)a in<br />

§6.1); the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach predicts the existence of n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing examples<br />

(predicti<strong>on</strong> (2)a). As discussed above, many examples found in this survey appear to be<br />

n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing. While it is difficult to prove that a particular example is n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing,<br />

the large number of cases of PCSA for which no ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>straint is readily<br />

available (see examples in §2.1.2.5, §3.1.1.4, and §4.1.1.3) to handle the allomorphy<br />

suggests that the predicti<strong>on</strong> of the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> model is correct.<br />

The sec<strong>on</strong>d predicti<strong>on</strong> of each model refers to input/underlying forms vs. surface<br />

forms. P >> M predicts that PCSA should refer to surface ph<strong>on</strong>ological properties of<br />

words (predicti<strong>on</strong> (1)b), while subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> predicts that there should be instances<br />

where PCSA is clearly sensitive to input or underlying forms, rather than surface forms<br />

(predicti<strong>on</strong> (2)b). As discussed above, several examples are found in which the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s<br />

<strong>on</strong> PCSA are rendered opaque by the operati<strong>on</strong> of regular ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes (see<br />

261


especially §2.1.2.6). This upholds the predicti<strong>on</strong> of the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> model and is<br />

problematic for P >> M, since in these examples, PCSA is crucially sensitive to input<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological elements, and not to surface elements.<br />

A third predicti<strong>on</strong> of each model c<strong>on</strong>cerns c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing from the ‘inside’ vs. the<br />

‘outside’. In a standard P >> M analysis, morphological c<strong>on</strong>stituency is not reflected in<br />

the input form, and therefore each morpheme in the word is equally likely to trigger<br />

allomorphy in other morphemes. This means that in P >> M, an affix can c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong><br />

PCSA in another affix closer to the root, or even in the root itself (predicti<strong>on</strong> (1)c). The P<br />

>> M model thus predicts the existence of c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing from both the ‘inside’ and the<br />

‘outside’. The subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach, <strong>on</strong> the other hand, is more restrictive in this<br />

regard. As discussed above, subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> as implemented within a model of<br />

morphology such as Lexical Morphology (which is standard for subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

analyses) predicts the existence <strong>on</strong>ly of c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing from the ‘inside’, never from the<br />

‘outside’ (predicti<strong>on</strong> (2)c). Based <strong>on</strong> the survey results throughout chapters 2-4, it appears<br />

that this more restrictive predicti<strong>on</strong> of subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> is upheld cross-linguistically.<br />

There are no clear-cut cases of c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing from the ‘outside’.<br />

Finally, both models make predicti<strong>on</strong>s for the locati<strong>on</strong> of the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong><br />

affixati<strong>on</strong> vis à vis the locati<strong>on</strong> of the affix undergoing allomorphy. The P >> M approach<br />

predicts that the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> may be located anywhere in the word, regardless of the<br />

locati<strong>on</strong> of the affix (predicti<strong>on</strong> (1)d). The subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach, <strong>on</strong> the other hand,<br />

predicts that c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> PCSA are limited to elements immediately adjacent to the<br />

262


affix in questi<strong>on</strong> (predicti<strong>on</strong> (2)d). 1 The survey data appear to uphold the predicti<strong>on</strong>s of<br />

the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> model, not the P >> M model. Based <strong>on</strong> this survey, c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong><br />

PCSA are always at the same edge of the stem where the affix allomorphs occur; this is<br />

most apparent in chapter 2 (§2.1.2). There are no examples of the type predicted by P >><br />

M in which, for example, prefix allomorphy is c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by the stem-final segment.<br />

Therefore, <strong>on</strong>ce again, the survey results point to subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> as the superior model.<br />

We have seen that the results for PCSA overwhelmingly support the<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach. In additi<strong>on</strong>, results for other types of ph<strong>on</strong>ology-morphology<br />

interacti<strong>on</strong>s appear to favor this approach as well, c<strong>on</strong>verging with the results reported<br />

here. In chapter 5, I covered some other types of ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong>,<br />

laying out the predicti<strong>on</strong>s made by P >> M for each area and discussing, where available,<br />

the cross-linguistic results for each. The following five logically possible types of<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong> (aside from PCSA) were discussed: empty morphs<br />

(§5.1), ph<strong>on</strong>ologically induced morphological gaps (§5.2), reduplicati<strong>on</strong> (§5.3),<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed affix order (§5.4), and infixati<strong>on</strong> (§5.5). For infixati<strong>on</strong>, there<br />

does exist a large cross-linguistic survey of the phenomen<strong>on</strong> al<strong>on</strong>g with a critique of the<br />

P >> M approach (Yu 2003). The results in that area c<strong>on</strong>verge with the results presented<br />

here, since P >> M predicts the existence of some unattested effects in affixati<strong>on</strong>, and it<br />

also fails to predict some effects that are attested. Thus, Yu (2003) argues against the use<br />

1<br />

As with the third predicti<strong>on</strong> (regarding the directi<strong>on</strong> of c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ing), this predicti<strong>on</strong> is<br />

made not by the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> mechanism itself, but by a standard implementati<strong>on</strong> of<br />

the model. In this case, the implementati<strong>on</strong> would need to incorporate the Generalized<br />

Determinant Focus Adjacency C<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> (GDFAC; Inkelas 1990), discussed in chapters<br />

1 and 2. As pointed out in chapter 1, the GDFAC is uniquely compatible with the<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach, not the P >> M approach, so from this perspective the<br />

adjacency predicti<strong>on</strong> is, at least indirectly, a predicti<strong>on</strong> of the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> model<br />

itself.<br />

263


of P >> M for modeling infixati<strong>on</strong>, as I have d<strong>on</strong>e here for PCSA. Large surveys for the<br />

purpose of assessing the claims of P >> M have not been c<strong>on</strong>ducted in the other areas<br />

discussed in chapter 5, but I have pointed out claims made by P >> M in each area, and<br />

have pointed out some unusual and likely false predicti<strong>on</strong>s that are made in some cases.<br />

Therefore, the available data <strong>on</strong> types of ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong> other than<br />

PCSA and infixati<strong>on</strong> lend tentative support to subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>, though more work is<br />

needed.<br />

In this secti<strong>on</strong> I have pointed out how subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> makes more accurate<br />

predicti<strong>on</strong>s than P >> M for PCSA, and how this is true for other types of ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong> for which data are available. The overall result is that the P >> M<br />

model is not upheld and should be aband<strong>on</strong>ed in favor of the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach.<br />

Thus, cross-linguistic research has given us insight into the best way to model<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological effects in morphology.<br />

6.4 Two types of PCSA?<br />

Although the cross-linguistic results str<strong>on</strong>gly favor the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

approach, <strong>on</strong>e may still find problematic the model’s inability to capture apparent<br />

optimizati<strong>on</strong> effects of PCSA. Some of the apparently optimizing examples discussed in<br />

the literature are not clear-cut cases of such (e.g. the Dyirbal example claimed by<br />

McCarthy and Prince (1990) to involve complementarity when in fact no tenable P >> M<br />

analysis has been able to make use of this insight), and in chapter 5 I discussed at length<br />

how an understanding of the historical origins of PCSA patterns minimizes the need for<br />

synchr<strong>on</strong>ic explanati<strong>on</strong>s of apparent optimizati<strong>on</strong>. However, <strong>on</strong>e may w<strong>on</strong>der whether a<br />

264


hybrid model could be applied, in which the cases that seem to be optimizing are<br />

modeled via P >> M, while subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> frames are used for the other, n<strong>on</strong>-<br />

optimizing cases. As discussed for syllable-counting allomorphy in §4.3.8, a proposal<br />

similar to this was made by Booij (1998), and this also corresp<strong>on</strong>ds with Mascaró’s<br />

(1996) distincti<strong>on</strong> between ‘internal’ and ‘external’ allomorphy.<br />

There are a number of serious problems with this strategy. First, even the<br />

‘optimizing’ examples still appear to fulfill predicti<strong>on</strong>s (b-d) of the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

approach more closely than those of the P >> M approach: they are never dem<strong>on</strong>strably<br />

output-based, they are c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed from the ‘inside’ and not the ‘outside’, and they never<br />

violate the adjacency requirements of the GDFAC. Thus, even those examples for which<br />

we would give a P >> M analysis under the dual approach still fail to fulfill three other<br />

predicti<strong>on</strong>s of the P >> M approach that distinguish it from the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> model.<br />

A sec<strong>on</strong>d problem has to do with how we might establish the split between<br />

optimizing and n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing cases to determine which model to use for a given<br />

example. Optimizati<strong>on</strong> vs. n<strong>on</strong>-optimizati<strong>on</strong> is not a black-and-white distincti<strong>on</strong>, but<br />

rather a c<strong>on</strong>tinuum, as was discussed for syllable-counting allomorphy in §4.3.8.<br />

The c<strong>on</strong>tinuum is problematic because it is not clear where optimizati<strong>on</strong> ends and n<strong>on</strong>-<br />

optimizati<strong>on</strong> begins. In order to analyze the optimizing examples in <strong>on</strong>e way and the n<strong>on</strong>-<br />

optimizing examples in a different way, we need a clear dividing line between the two<br />

types.<br />

A related problem is that there is no independent basis for two different types of<br />

PCSA. The split would therefore have to be made based <strong>on</strong> which examples lend<br />

themselves to analysis in P >> M and which do not. This is circular because the claim<br />

265


that there are two types of allomorphy that should be analyzed differently would rest<br />

up<strong>on</strong> the fact that we analyzed the two types differently. A useful comparis<strong>on</strong> can be<br />

made between this situati<strong>on</strong> and the situati<strong>on</strong> faced by Alderete et al (1999) in their study<br />

of fixed segment reduplicati<strong>on</strong> (FSR). As was discussed in §4.3.8, Alderete et al<br />

proposed that there are two types of FSR, a ph<strong>on</strong>ological type and a morphological type;<br />

the former follows ph<strong>on</strong>ological principles and is analyzed ph<strong>on</strong>ologically, while the<br />

latter does not follow ph<strong>on</strong>ological principles (e.g., the identity of the fixed segment in<br />

morphological FSR is an arbitrary segment, not a ph<strong>on</strong>ologically unmarked ‘default’<br />

segment) and is analyzed morphologically. Unlike in our present study of PCSA,<br />

Alderete et al (1999: 355-356) identified several independent differences between their<br />

proposed ph<strong>on</strong>ological and morphological types of FSR. We have no such independent<br />

criteria to distinguish two types of PCSA, and the burden of proof is <strong>on</strong> those who would<br />

argue that PCSA can be split into multiple separate phenomena in a principled way. The<br />

survey presented in this dissertati<strong>on</strong> represents an attempt to find independent criteria <strong>on</strong><br />

which such a distincti<strong>on</strong> might be made, but n<strong>on</strong>e were found.<br />

(footnote 2):<br />

B<strong>on</strong>et et al (in press) advocate a dual approach based <strong>on</strong> the following argument<br />

‘The idea that all allomorphy should be explained by the same mechanism<br />

seems to be assumed by some authors, either implicitly or explicitly (for<br />

instance, Paster, 2005[a]: secti<strong>on</strong> 5, states that subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> “avoids<br />

the problem of having multiple theoretical mechanisms to model a single<br />

phenomen<strong>on</strong>”). But ‘allomorphy’ is a (vague) descriptive c<strong>on</strong>cept that has<br />

no privileged theoretical status.’<br />

Two points must be made regarding this line of reas<strong>on</strong>ing. First, it must be clarified that<br />

while some authors may indeed claim that ‘all allomorphy should be explained by the<br />

same mechanism,’ Paster 2005a argues <strong>on</strong>ly that syllable-counting allomorphy, a specific<br />

266


subtype of PCSA (itself a subtype of ‘allomorphy’) should have a unified analysis; the<br />

argument is extended in this dissertati<strong>on</strong> to all of PCSA but not to ‘allomorphy’ in<br />

general. In fact, several specific independent criteria for distinguishing PCSA from n<strong>on</strong>-<br />

suppletive ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy are established in §2.1.1. Thus, the<br />

claim that ‘allomorphy’ has no theoretical status is immaterial to the arguments made in<br />

Paster 2005a and in this dissertati<strong>on</strong>. Sec<strong>on</strong>d, the asserti<strong>on</strong> that allomorphy (or more<br />

specifically, PCSA, if this is what was actually intended in the quote above) is merely a<br />

‘(vague) descriptive c<strong>on</strong>cept’ is easily turned back <strong>on</strong> B<strong>on</strong>et et al, who rely crucially <strong>on</strong><br />

Mascaró’s (1996) distincti<strong>on</strong> between internal and external allomorphy (renamed by<br />

B<strong>on</strong>et et al as ‘arbitrary ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy’ and ‘regular (natural)<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed allomorphy’, respectively); the arbitrary ‘type’ of allomorphy<br />

apparently c<strong>on</strong>sists of cases in which ‘[i]t is difficult to see any natural ph<strong>on</strong>ological<br />

c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> between the shape of the allomorphs’ (B<strong>on</strong>et et al in press: §1). Although<br />

naturalness is <strong>on</strong>e factor that I have used to determine what c<strong>on</strong>stitutes PCSA vs. n<strong>on</strong>-<br />

suppletive allomorphy (see §2.1.1), this is not the <strong>on</strong>ly criteri<strong>on</strong> used, whereas<br />

naturalness (defined in terms of difficulty for the analyst) does seem to be the sole<br />

difference between B<strong>on</strong>et et al’s two types of PCSA. Classifying a particular case as<br />

optimizing or n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing allomorphy based solely <strong>on</strong> the ease of analysis in P >> M<br />

vs. subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> is circular and not insightful.<br />

A final problem with the dual approach has to do with how to formalize it. Even if<br />

we decide that there are two types of PCSA that should be analyzed differently, how can<br />

we ensure that the grammar will ‘do’ the optimizing type using P >> M and the n<strong>on</strong>-<br />

optimizing type using subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>? A possible way to encode the distincti<strong>on</strong> in the<br />

267


grammar would be to put limits <strong>on</strong> subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> frames so that affixes cannot<br />

subcategorize for the elements that comm<strong>on</strong>ly c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> the optimizing type of PCSA. I<br />

observed earlier that PCSA c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by prosodic units such as feet, syllables, and<br />

moras, as well as the C/V distincti<strong>on</strong>, account for most of the optimizing examples, while<br />

PCSA c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by specific segments and/or features are more comm<strong>on</strong>ly n<strong>on</strong>-<br />

optimizing. Suppose, then, that subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> frames were limited so that an affix<br />

could <strong>on</strong>ly subcategorize for small units like segments and features, and not for larger<br />

prosodic units or C/V. Then suppose that the grammar were set up so that it would ‘try’ a<br />

subcategorizati<strong>on</strong>-based generalizati<strong>on</strong> first, and failing this, would then default to the P<br />

>> M generalizati<strong>on</strong>. This would achieve the effect of having the grammar (rather than<br />

the analyst) distinguish the two types of PCSA, but there is a major problem with this<br />

move. The problem is that it directly c<strong>on</strong>tradicts the set of things that have previously<br />

been established as elements that affixes can subcategorize for. In his study of infixati<strong>on</strong>,<br />

Yu (2003, in press) found that the set of ph<strong>on</strong>ological elements that can be<br />

morphologically subcategorized for is exactly: {foot, syllable, mora, C, V}. Thus,<br />

preventing affixes from subcategorizing for these elements would have unintended<br />

negative c<strong>on</strong>sequences for other types of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed morphology.<br />

The bottom line is that while the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> model can handle both the<br />

examples that seem to optimize and those that do not, the P >> M model can handle <strong>on</strong>ly<br />

the optimizing examples well. And with no independent evidence to distinguish two<br />

separate types of PCSA, the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> model is the <strong>on</strong>e that should be used.<br />

Assuming that <strong>on</strong>e accepts these arguments for the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> model, <strong>on</strong>e<br />

may reas<strong>on</strong>ably ask whether this means that the apparent optimizati<strong>on</strong> found in so many<br />

268


examples in the survey is merely a coincidence. The answer is no, not necessarily. As I<br />

menti<strong>on</strong>ed in §2.2, <strong>on</strong>e way in which PCSA can arise is from a ph<strong>on</strong>ological process that<br />

is lost and becomes morphologized. If the original ph<strong>on</strong>ological process was optimizing<br />

(and it is widely held that ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes often do have this characteristic), then<br />

the resulting PCSA can retain the appearance of optimizati<strong>on</strong> without this having to be<br />

encoded in the synchr<strong>on</strong>ic grammar. Therefore, although the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> approach<br />

does not directly capture the optimizing effects that are apparent in some examples in the<br />

survey, this does not mean that we cannot explain them.<br />

6.5 M >> P vs. separate comp<strong>on</strong>ents<br />

If P >> M is rejected as a way of modeling ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong>,<br />

how might we rule out this ranking schema? There are at least two possibilities. One,<br />

proposed by Yu (2003: 108) is to propose a universal ranking M >> P. 2 Alternatively, P<br />

and M may be distinguished as separate comp<strong>on</strong>ents of grammar that are not evaluated in<br />

parallel and therefore have no ranking relati<strong>on</strong>ship. Both of these opti<strong>on</strong>s are sufficient to<br />

rule out P >> M, but they make different predicti<strong>on</strong>s, which I will discuss here.<br />

The M >> P proposal makes at least two important claims. The first is that PCSA<br />

is surface-based, since if M and P have a ranking relati<strong>on</strong>ship, they will be evaluated in<br />

parallel just as in P >> M. The sec<strong>on</strong>d is that P c<strong>on</strong>straints will drive morphology<br />

whenever M c<strong>on</strong>straints underdetermine outputs.<br />

The ‘separate comp<strong>on</strong>ents’ proposal, <strong>on</strong> the other hand, makes opposing claims.<br />

In this approach, assuming that the output of morphology is the input to ph<strong>on</strong>ology,<br />

2<br />

Note, however, that Yu in press, which is based <strong>on</strong> Yu 2003, does not pursue this<br />

opti<strong>on</strong>.<br />

269


PCSA should be an input-based phenomen<strong>on</strong>. A sec<strong>on</strong>d claim is that P c<strong>on</strong>straints cannot<br />

drive morphological processes; instead their effects should be seen <strong>on</strong> the outputs of<br />

morphology <strong>on</strong>ly.<br />

There is some evidence suggesting that the ‘separate comp<strong>on</strong>ents’ approach is the<br />

correct <strong>on</strong>e. First, as we have seen above, PCSA is crucially an input-based phenomen<strong>on</strong>,<br />

not output-based. This is dem<strong>on</strong>strated in the Turkish example discussed in §2.1.2.6.<br />

Thus, a predicti<strong>on</strong> of the M >> P proposal is c<strong>on</strong>tradicted by PCSA. The sec<strong>on</strong>d type of<br />

evidence against M >> P comes from affix ordering. Assuming that affix order is handled<br />

by M c<strong>on</strong>straints (an assumpti<strong>on</strong> that is explicitly made in some treatments of putative<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed affix order, e.g. Hargus and Tuttle 1997), then under M >> P,<br />

we expect that anytime the M c<strong>on</strong>straints do not fully determine affix order, P c<strong>on</strong>straints<br />

should be able to step in and select a winner. However, as I discuss in Paster 2006, no<br />

good cases of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically driven affix order are attested. Furthermore, there are at<br />

least two attested examples of free affix order (in Chintang (Bickel et al in press) and in<br />

Filomeno Mata Tot<strong>on</strong>ac (McFarland 2007)). Under M >> P, we would expect that if the<br />

morphology left the affix order free, then the lower-ranked P c<strong>on</strong>straints should come<br />

into play, as in TETU, and select a winner. Free affix order should not exist because the P<br />

c<strong>on</strong>straints should always pick a c<strong>on</strong>sistent winner. Thus, the existence of free affix<br />

order, in combinati<strong>on</strong> with the other observati<strong>on</strong>s discussed here, favors the ‘separate<br />

comp<strong>on</strong>ents’ approach.<br />

I have elaborated <strong>on</strong> some aspects of the argument in favor of subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

and against P >> M, arguing in §6.4 that a hybrid model in terms of ‘two types of PCSA’<br />

is untenable and in this secti<strong>on</strong> that P and M should be understood as separate<br />

270


comp<strong>on</strong>ents of grammar rather than having any ranking relati<strong>on</strong> in OT, even <strong>on</strong>e that<br />

inherently rules out P >> M. In the following secti<strong>on</strong>, I suggest a few ways in which the<br />

present line of research may be advanced.<br />

6.6 Future directi<strong>on</strong>s<br />

This dissertati<strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>tributes to our understanding of the ph<strong>on</strong>ology-morphology<br />

interface by providing a broad empirical basis for the study of PCSA, an important<br />

instance of a ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong>. The generalizati<strong>on</strong>s about PCSA that<br />

have been presented here are based <strong>on</strong> a large database of examples; previous studies<br />

have not had a very large set of examples <strong>on</strong> which to base generalizati<strong>on</strong>s. Because of<br />

this, the generalizati<strong>on</strong>s presented here and the theoretical c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s that follow from<br />

them are perhaps more significant than those that have been made before. Thus, the<br />

dissertati<strong>on</strong> makes a theoretical c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong> as well as an empirical <strong>on</strong>e.<br />

The work presented here gives insight into just <strong>on</strong>e part of an overall picture of<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ological effects in morphology, and the ph<strong>on</strong>ology-morphology interface more<br />

generally. As discussed in chapter 1, the study of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed morphology<br />

began in earnest relatively recently, and much work in this area remains to be d<strong>on</strong>e.<br />

Regarding the study of PCSA itself, some facts have been left unexplained here.<br />

One of these, pointed out in chapter 3, is that the survey revealed <strong>on</strong>ly a very small<br />

number of examples of PCSA c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed by t<strong>on</strong>e or stress. Perhaps this is a gap in the<br />

survey, or perhaps it reflects some deeper, yet unknown, property of language. This issue<br />

might fruitfully be probed through careful research <strong>on</strong> a particular family of languages<br />

with well documented stress or t<strong>on</strong>e properties (e.g., the Bantu languages of Africa) in<br />

271


order to find out whether regular ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes involving stress and t<strong>on</strong>e can<br />

evolve into patterns of stress- or t<strong>on</strong>e-c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed PCSA, and if not, why not. A sec<strong>on</strong>d<br />

issue is the appearance of optimizati<strong>on</strong> in many examples discussed in the presentati<strong>on</strong> of<br />

survey results, perhaps more than expected by chance under the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong><br />

approach. It can still be maintained that the existence of apparent n<strong>on</strong>-optimizing<br />

examples is sufficient to argue against P >> M, since that model predicts that such<br />

examples should not exist. However, in the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> model, we do not have a<br />

ready explanati<strong>on</strong> for the apparent fact that many examples of PCSA (perhaps the<br />

majority) can be plausibly argued to be optimizing in some way. The detailed look at<br />

examples of ergative allomorphy in the Pama-Nyungan languages in chapter 4 was<br />

intended to suggest a general historical approach to optimizing PCSA that complements<br />

the subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> model. This approach could be tested <strong>on</strong> other examples to see<br />

whether other apparently optimizing examples can be accounted for successfully in the<br />

historical realm. Perhaps the apparent optimizing nature of ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes is<br />

sufficient to explain optimizati<strong>on</strong> in PCSA, since it seems likely that many cases of<br />

PCSA evolved from regular ph<strong>on</strong>ological processes that were lost. However, analogy<br />

seems to play a major role as well, and it remains an open questi<strong>on</strong> whether analogy can<br />

involve some type of optimizati<strong>on</strong>, even if PCSA itself is not optimizing synchr<strong>on</strong>ically.<br />

In additi<strong>on</strong>, instances of ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong> other than PCSA<br />

were discussed in chapter 5, and some have not yet been well studied from a cross-<br />

linguistic perspective. In particular, empty morphs and ph<strong>on</strong>ologically induced<br />

morphological gaps are not well understood. Future research will show whether the<br />

c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s regarding the best way to model PCSA hold up for those phenomena as well.<br />

272


Also, I have focused here <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>on</strong> ph<strong>on</strong>ological c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> affixati<strong>on</strong>, but other<br />

morphological processes, such as compounding, should be c<strong>on</strong>sidered as well. Further<br />

testing based <strong>on</strong> larger and better cross-linguistic studies will reveal the extent to which<br />

the claims made in this dissertati<strong>on</strong> can be accepted as general principles of morphology.<br />

273


References<br />

Ab<strong>on</strong>dolo, Daniel M. 1988. Hungarian Inflecti<strong>on</strong>al Morphology. Budapest: Akadémiai<br />

Kiadó.<br />

Alderete, John. 2001. Dominance effects as transderivati<strong>on</strong>al anti-faithfulness. Ph<strong>on</strong>ology<br />

18.2: 201-253.<br />

Alderete, John, Jill Beckman, Laura Benua, Amalia Gnanadesikan, John McCarthy, and<br />

Suzanne Urbanczyk. 1999. Reduplicati<strong>on</strong> with fixed segmentism. Linguistic Inquiry<br />

30.3: 327-364.<br />

Anders<strong>on</strong>, Stephen R. 1981. Why ph<strong>on</strong>ology isn’t ‘natural’. Linguistic Inquiry 12: 493-<br />

539.<br />

And<strong>on</strong>ian, Hagop. 1999. Beginner’s Armenian. New York: Hippocrene Books.<br />

Aranovich, Raúl, Shar<strong>on</strong> Inkelas, Orhan Orgun, and R<strong>on</strong>ald Sprouse. 2005. Opacity in<br />

ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppleti<strong>on</strong>. Paper presented at the Thirteenth Manchester<br />

Ph<strong>on</strong>ology Meeting.<br />

Arnott, D.W. 1970. The Nominal and Verbal Systems of Fula. Oxford: Clarend<strong>on</strong> Press.<br />

Austin, Peter. 1981. A Grammar of Diyari, South Australia. Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press.<br />

Bach, Emm<strong>on</strong> and Robert T. Harms. 1972. How do languages get crazy rules?. Pp. 1-21<br />

in Robert P. Stockwell and R<strong>on</strong>ald K.S. Macaulay, eds. Linguistic Change in<br />

Generative Theory. Bloomingt<strong>on</strong>: Indiana University Press.<br />

Baker, Mark. 1985. The mirror principle and morphosyntactic explanati<strong>on</strong>. Linguistic<br />

Inquiry 16: 373-415.<br />

Bastin, Yv<strong>on</strong>ne. 1983. La finale -IDE et l’imbricati<strong>on</strong> en bantou. Tervuren: Annales du<br />

Musée Royale de l’Afrique Centrale. Série IN-8, Sciences Humaines. N. 114.<br />

Bauer, Laurie. 1988. Introducing Linguistic Morphology. Edinburgh: Edinburgh<br />

University Press.<br />

Beckman, Jill. 1998. Positi<strong>on</strong>al Faithfulness. PhD. dissertati<strong>on</strong>, University of<br />

Massachusetts, Amherst.<br />

274


Bickel, Balthasar, Goma Banjade, Martin Gaenszle, Elena Lieven, Netra Paudyal,<br />

Ichchha Purna Rai, Manoj Rai, Novel Kishor Rai, and Sabine Stoll. In press. Free<br />

prefix ordering in Chintang. Language 83.<br />

Biggs, Bruce. 1961. The structure of New Zealand Maaori. Anthropological Linguistics<br />

3: 1-54.<br />

Blevins, Juliette. 2001. Nhanda: An Aboriginal Language of Western Australia.<br />

H<strong>on</strong>olulu: University of Hawai’i Press.<br />

Blevins, Juliette. 2004. Evoluti<strong>on</strong>ary Ph<strong>on</strong>ology. Cambridge: Cambridge University<br />

Press.<br />

B<strong>on</strong>et, Eulàlia. 2004. Morph inserti<strong>on</strong> and allomorphy in Optimality Theory.<br />

Internati<strong>on</strong>al Journal of English Studies 4.2: 73-104.<br />

B<strong>on</strong>et, Eulàlia, Maria-Rosa Lloret, and Joan Mascaró. In press. Allomorph selecti<strong>on</strong> and<br />

lexical preferences: Two case studies. Lingua.<br />

Booij, Geert. 1997. N<strong>on</strong>-derivati<strong>on</strong>al ph<strong>on</strong>ology meets lexical ph<strong>on</strong>ology. Pp. 261-288 in<br />

Iggy Roca, ed. Derivati<strong>on</strong>s and C<strong>on</strong>straints in Ph<strong>on</strong>ology. Oxford: Clarend<strong>on</strong> Press.<br />

Booij, Geert. 1998. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g> output c<strong>on</strong>straints in morphology. Pp. 143-163 in<br />

Wolfgang Kehrein and Richard Wiese, eds. Ph<strong>on</strong>ology and Morphology of the<br />

Germanic Languages. Tübingen: Niemeyer.<br />

Booij, Geert. 2005. The Grammar of Words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

Booij, Geert and Rochelle Lieber. 1993. On the simultaneity of morphological and<br />

prosodic structure. Pp. 23-44 in Shar<strong>on</strong> Hargus and Ellen M. Kaisse, eds.<br />

Ph<strong>on</strong>etics and Ph<strong>on</strong>ology 4: Studies in Lexical Ph<strong>on</strong>ology. San Diego: Academic<br />

Press, Inc.<br />

Breen, J.G. 1976a. Bidjara. P. 339 in R.M.W. Dix<strong>on</strong>, ed. Grammatical Categories in<br />

Australian Languages. Canberra: Australian Institute of Aboriginal Studies.<br />

Breen, J.G. 1976b. Wangkumara. Pp. 336-339 in R.M.W. Dix<strong>on</strong>, ed. Grammatical<br />

Categories in Australian Languages. Canberra: Australian Institute of Aboriginal<br />

Studies.<br />

Breen, J.G. 1976c. Warluwara and Bularnu. Pp. 331-335 in R.M.W. Dix<strong>on</strong>, ed.<br />

Grammatical Categories in Australian Languages. Canberra: Australian Institute of<br />

Aboriginal Studies.<br />

275


Broadwell, George Aar<strong>on</strong>. 2005. The morphology of Zapotec pr<strong>on</strong>ominal clitics. Pp. 15-<br />

35 in Rosemary Beam de Azc<strong>on</strong>a and Mary Paster, eds. Proceedings of the<br />

C<strong>on</strong>ference <strong>on</strong> Otomanguean and other Oaxacan Languages. Berkeley: Survey of<br />

California and Other Indian Languages.<br />

Buckley, Eugene. 1994. Theoretical Aspects of Kashaya Ph<strong>on</strong>ology and Morphology.<br />

Stanford: CSLI.<br />

Buechel, Eugene. 1939. A Grammar of Lakota. St. Louis, Missouri: John S. Swift<br />

Company, Inc.<br />

Bybee, Joan. 1985. Morphology: A Study of the Relati<strong>on</strong> Between Meaning and Form.<br />

Amsterdam: Benjamins.<br />

Bye, Patrik. 2005. Allomorphy – Selecti<strong>on</strong>, not optimizati<strong>on</strong>. Paper presented at the<br />

University of Chicago linguistics department colloquium.<br />

Bye, Patrik. To appear. Allomorphy – Selecti<strong>on</strong>, not optimizati<strong>on</strong>. Sylvia Blaho, Patrik<br />

Bye, and Martin Krämer, eds. Freedom of Analysis? Berlin: Mout<strong>on</strong> de Gruyter.<br />

Cadely, John-Robert. 2002. Le statut des voyelles nasals en Créole haïtien. Lingua 112:<br />

435-464.<br />

Carstairs, Andrew. 1988. Some implicati<strong>on</strong>s of ph<strong>on</strong>ologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppleti<strong>on</strong>.<br />

Yearbook of Morphology 1988: 67-94.<br />

Carstairs, Andrew. 1990. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g>ly c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed suppleti<strong>on</strong>. Pp. 17-23 in Wolfgang<br />

U. Dressler, Hans C. Luschützky, Oskar E. Pfeiffer, and John R. Rennis<strong>on</strong>, eds.<br />

C<strong>on</strong>temporary Morphology. New York: Mout<strong>on</strong> de Gruyter.<br />

Carstairs-McCarthy, Andrew. 1998. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g> c<strong>on</strong>straints <strong>on</strong> morphological rules. Pp.<br />

144-148 in Andrew Spencer and Arnold Zwicky, eds. The Handbook of Morphology.<br />

Oxford: Blackwell.<br />

Cohen, Kevin Bret<strong>on</strong>nel. 2000. Aspects of the Grammar of Kukú. München: Lincom<br />

Europa.<br />

C<strong>on</strong>athan, Lisa J. 2002. Split intransitivity and possessi<strong>on</strong> in Chimariko. Pp. 18-31 in<br />

Lisa C<strong>on</strong>athan and Teresa McFarland, eds. Survey report #12: Proceedings of the<br />

50th Anniversary C<strong>on</strong>ference of the Survey of California and Other Indian<br />

Languages. Berkeley: Survey of California and Other Indian Languages.<br />

C<strong>on</strong>doravdi, Cleo and Paul Kiparsky. 1998. Optimal order and scope. Paper presented at<br />

Lexic<strong>on</strong> in Focus, Heinrich-Heine Universität Düsseldorf.<br />

276


Crosswhite, Katherine. 1999. Intra-paradigmatic homoph<strong>on</strong>y avoidance in two dialects of<br />

Slavic. Pp. 48-67 in Matthew K. Gord<strong>on</strong>, ed. UCLA Working Papers in Linguistics 1:<br />

Papers in Ph<strong>on</strong>ology 2. Los Angeles: UCLA Department of Linguistics.<br />

Davis, Stuart. 1998. Syllable c<strong>on</strong>tact in Optimality Theory. Korean Journal of Linguistics<br />

23: 181-211.<br />

de Maria, Jose. 1918. Gramatica y vocabulario jibaros. Quito: Impr. de la Universidad<br />

Central.<br />

Dench, Alan. 1995. Martuthunira: A Language of the Pilbara Regi<strong>on</strong> of Western<br />

Australia. Canberra: Pacific Linguistics, Series C-125.<br />

Dench, Alan. 1998. Yingkarta. München: LINCOM Europa.<br />

DiFabio, Elvira G. 1990. The Morphology of the Verbal Infix isc in Italian and Romance.<br />

PhD dissertati<strong>on</strong>, Harvard University.<br />

Dimmendaal, Gerrit J. 1983. The Turkana Language. Dordrecht: Foris.<br />

Dimmendaal, Gerrit J. 2000. Morphology. Pp. 161-193 in Bernd Heine and Derek Nurse,<br />

eds. African Languages: An Introducti<strong>on</strong>.<br />

Dix<strong>on</strong>, Roland B. 1910. The Chimariko Indians and language. University of California<br />

Publicati<strong>on</strong>s in American Archaeology and Ethnology 5.5. Berkeley: University of<br />

California Press.<br />

Dix<strong>on</strong>, R.M.W. 1972. The Dyirbal Language of North Queensland. Cambridge:<br />

Cambridge University Press.<br />

Dix<strong>on</strong>, R.M.W. 1977. A Grammar of Yidiɲ. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Dix<strong>on</strong>, R.M.W. 1980. The Languages of Australia. Cambridge: Cambridge University<br />

Press.<br />

Dix<strong>on</strong>, R.M.W. 2002. Australian Languages: Their Nature and Development.<br />

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Dolbey, Andrew. 1997. Output optimizati<strong>on</strong> and cyclic allomorph selecti<strong>on</strong>. Proceedings<br />

of the Fifteenth West Coast C<strong>on</strong>ference <strong>on</strong> Formal Linguistics: 97-112. Stanford:<br />

CSLI.<br />

D<strong>on</strong>alds<strong>on</strong>, Tamsin. 1980. Ngiyambaa: The Language of the Wangaaybuwan.<br />

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

277


Dresher, Elan B. and Xi Zhang. In press. C<strong>on</strong>trast in Manchu vowel systems. In Carsten<br />

Naher, ed. Proceedings of the First Internati<strong>on</strong>al C<strong>on</strong>ference <strong>on</strong> Manchu-Tungus<br />

Studies. Volume 2: Trends in Tungusic and Siberian Linguistics. Wiesbaden,<br />

Germany: Harrassowitz.<br />

Elías-Ulloa, José. 2004. Variable syllable weight and quantity-insensitive allomorphy in<br />

Shipibo. Paper presented at the 35th meeting of the North Eastern Linguistic Society,<br />

University of C<strong>on</strong>necticut.<br />

Fast Mowitz, Gerhard, Ruby Warkentin de Fast, and Daniel Fast Warkentin. 1996.<br />

Dicci<strong>on</strong>ario Achuar-Shiwiar – Castellano. Serie lingüistica Peruana 36.<br />

Yarinacocha, Pucallpa, Peru: Instituto Lingüístico de Verano.<br />

Feldman, Harry. 1986. A Grammar of Awtuw. Pacific Linguistics Series B, number 94.<br />

Canberra: Australian Nati<strong>on</strong>al University.<br />

Fulmer, Sandra. 1991. Dual-positi<strong>on</strong> affixes in Afar: An argument for ph<strong>on</strong>ologicallydriven<br />

morphology. Pp. 189-203 in Aar<strong>on</strong> Halpern, ed. Proceedings of the Ninth West<br />

Coast C<strong>on</strong>ference <strong>on</strong> Formal Linguistics. Stanford: CSLI.<br />

Good, Jeff. 2003. Str<strong>on</strong>g Linearity: Three Case Studies Towards a Theory of<br />

Morphosyntactic Templatic C<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>s. PhD. dissertati<strong>on</strong>, UC Berkeley.<br />

Gord<strong>on</strong>, Raym<strong>on</strong>d G., Jr., ed. 2005. Ethnologue: Languages of the World. Fifteenth<br />

editi<strong>on</strong>. Dallas, Tex.: SIL Internati<strong>on</strong>al. Online versi<strong>on</strong>: http://www.ethnologue.com.<br />

Gouskova, Maria. 2004. Relati<strong>on</strong>al hierarchies in Optimality Theory: The case of syllable<br />

c<strong>on</strong>tact. Ph<strong>on</strong>ology 21.2: 201-250.<br />

Haig, Geoffrey. To appear. C<strong>on</strong>straints <strong>on</strong> morpheme repetiti<strong>on</strong> in Turkish?. In<br />

Proceedings of the Eleventh Internati<strong>on</strong>al C<strong>on</strong>ference <strong>on</strong> Turkish Linguistics.<br />

Hale, Kenneth. 1976a. Dja:bugay. Pp. 321-326 in R.M.W. Dix<strong>on</strong>, ed. Grammatical<br />

Categories in Australian Languages. Canberra: Australian Institute of Aboriginal<br />

Studies.<br />

Hale, Kenneth. 1976b. On ergative and locative suffixal alternati<strong>on</strong>s in Australian<br />

languages. Pp. 414-417 in R.M.W. Dix<strong>on</strong>, ed. Grammatical Categories in Australian<br />

Languages. Canberra: Australian Institute of Aboriginal Studies.<br />

Hale, K. and A. Lacayo Blanco. 1989. Dicci<strong>on</strong>ario elemental del Ulwa (Sumu<br />

Meridi<strong>on</strong>al). Cambridge: Center for Cognitive Science, MIT.<br />

278


Hall, Beatrice L. and Eluzai Moga Yokwe. 1981. Bari vowel harm<strong>on</strong>y: The evoluti<strong>on</strong> of a<br />

cross-height vowel harm<strong>on</strong>y system. Pp. 55-63 in Eluzai Moga Yokwe and Wanda<br />

Pace, eds. Occasi<strong>on</strong>al Papers in the Study of Sudanese Languages 1. Juba, Sudan:<br />

University of Juba Printing Unit.<br />

Hall, Robert A. 1948. Descriptive Italian Grammar. Ithaca, New York: Cornell<br />

University Press and Linguistic Society of America.<br />

Hall, Robert A. 1953. Haitian Creole: Grammar, Texts, Vocabulary. Memoirs of the<br />

American Anthropological Associati<strong>on</strong> 74. Menasha, Wisc<strong>on</strong>sin: American<br />

Anthropological Associati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

Hanss<strong>on</strong>, Gunnar Ólafur. 2001. Theoretical and Typological Issues in C<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant<br />

Harm<strong>on</strong>y. PhD. dissertati<strong>on</strong>, UC Berkeley.<br />

Hargus, Shar<strong>on</strong> and Siri G. Tuttle. 1997. Augmentati<strong>on</strong> as affixati<strong>on</strong> in Athabaskan<br />

languages. Ph<strong>on</strong>ology 14: 177-220.<br />

Harlow, Ray. 1996. Māori. München: LINCOM Europa.<br />

Harrell, Richard S. 1962. A Short Reference Grammar of Moroccan Arabic. Washingt<strong>on</strong>,<br />

DC: Georgetown University Press.<br />

Harris, James W. 1979. Some observati<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> ‘Substantive principles in natural<br />

generative ph<strong>on</strong>ology’. Pp. 281-293 in Daniel A. Dinnsen, ed. Current Approaches to<br />

<str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g> Theory. Bloomingt<strong>on</strong>, Indiana: Indiana University Press.<br />

Harris<strong>on</strong>, S.P. 1973. Reduplicati<strong>on</strong> in Micr<strong>on</strong>esian languages. Oceanic Linguistics 7:<br />

407-454.<br />

Hartell, Rh<strong>on</strong>da L., ed. 1993. Alphabets of Africa. Dakar: UNESCO/SIL.<br />

Hayward, Richard J. 1998. Qafar (East Cushitic). Pp. 624-647 in Andrew Spencer and<br />

Arnold M. Zwicky, eds. The Handbook of Morphology. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers<br />

Ltd.<br />

Hendricks, Sean Q. 1999. Reduplicati<strong>on</strong> Without Template C<strong>on</strong>straints: A Study in Bare-<br />

C<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ant Reduplicati<strong>on</strong>. PhD. dissertati<strong>on</strong>, University of Ariz<strong>on</strong>a.<br />

Hyman, Larry M. 1995. Minimality and the prosodic morphology of Cibemba<br />

imbricati<strong>on</strong>. Journal of African Languages and Linguistics 16: 3-39.<br />

Hyman, Larry M. 2003. Suffix ordering in Bantu: A morphocentric approach. Yearbook<br />

of Morphology 2002: 245-281.<br />

279


Hyman, Larry M. and Shar<strong>on</strong> Inkelas. 1997. Emergent templates: The unusual case of<br />

Tiene. Pp. 92-116 in Viola Miglio and Bruce Morén, eds. Selected Ph<strong>on</strong>ology<br />

Papers from H-OT-97. University of Maryland Working Papers in Linguistics.<br />

College Park: University of Maryland Department of Linguistics.<br />

Inkelas, Shar<strong>on</strong>. 1990. Prosodic C<strong>on</strong>stituency in the Lexic<strong>on</strong>. New York: Garland.<br />

Inkelas, Shar<strong>on</strong>. 1993. Nimboran positi<strong>on</strong> class morphology. Natural Language and<br />

Linguistic Theory 11: 559-624.<br />

Inkelas, Shar<strong>on</strong>. 1998. The theoretical status of morphologically c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>ed ph<strong>on</strong>ology:<br />

A case study of dominance effects. Yearbook of Morphology 1997: 121-155.<br />

Inkelas, Shar<strong>on</strong> and Cheryl Zoll. 2005. Reduplicati<strong>on</strong>: Doubling in Morphology.<br />

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Inkelas, Shar<strong>on</strong>, Orhan Orgun, and Cheryl Zoll. 1997. The implicati<strong>on</strong>s of lexical<br />

excepti<strong>on</strong>s for the nature of grammar. Pp. 393-418 in Iggy Roca, ed. Derivati<strong>on</strong>s<br />

and C<strong>on</strong>straints in Ph<strong>on</strong>ology. Oxford: Clarend<strong>on</strong> Press.<br />

Jacobsen, William H. 1973. A rhythmic principle in Washo morphotactics. Paper<br />

presented at the Symposium <strong>on</strong> California Indian Linguistics, Southwestern<br />

Anthropological Associati<strong>on</strong>, San Francisco, California.<br />

Jespersen, Otto. 1904. Lehrbuch der Ph<strong>on</strong>etik. Leipzig and Berlin: Teubner.<br />

Jintia, Yánkuam, P. Luis Bolla Sartori, and Péas Kantásh Ishtiku. 2000. Achuar<br />

ujákratmau: Dicci<strong>on</strong>ario Achuar. Achuar matsátmau 3. Lima: Centro Amazónico de<br />

Antropología y Aplicación Práctica.<br />

Johnst<strong>on</strong>, Raym<strong>on</strong>d Leslie. 1980. Nakanai of New Britain: The Grammar of an Oceanic<br />

Language. Canberra: Australian Nati<strong>on</strong>al University.<br />

Kager, Rene. 1996. On affix allomorphy and syllable counting. Pp. 155-171 in Ursula<br />

Kleinhenz, ed. Interfaces in Ph<strong>on</strong>ology. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.<br />

Karlss<strong>on</strong>, Fred. 1999. Finnish: An Essential Grammar. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong> and New York:<br />

Routledge.<br />

Kaufman, Terrence. 1971. Tzeltal Ph<strong>on</strong>ology and Morphology. University of California<br />

Publicati<strong>on</strong>s in Linguistics 61. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California<br />

Press.<br />

Kenesei, István, Robert Vago, and Anna Fenyvesi. 1997. Hungarian. New York:<br />

Routledge.<br />

280


Kennedy, Robert. 2002. Stress and allomorphy in Woleaian reduplicati<strong>on</strong>. In Proceedings<br />

of the Texas Linguistics Society C<strong>on</strong>ference. Austin, Texas: University of Texas.<br />

Kikuchi, Seiichiro. 2000. Spanish definite article allomorphy: A corresp<strong>on</strong>dence<br />

approach. Paper presented at the Sixth Meeting of the <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g> Society of<br />

Japan, Chiba University.<br />

Kikuchi, Seiichiro. 2001. Spanish definite article allomorphy: A corresp<strong>on</strong>dence<br />

approach. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g> Studies 4: 49-56. Tokyo: Kaitakusha.<br />

Kiparsky, Paul. 1982a. Lexical Morphology and Ph<strong>on</strong>ology. Pp. 3-91 in I.-S. Yange, ed.<br />

Linguistics in the Morning Calm. Seoul: Hanshin.<br />

Kiparsky, Paul. 1982b. Word-formati<strong>on</strong> and the lexic<strong>on</strong>. Pp. 1-29 in Frances Ingemann,<br />

ed. 1982 Mid-America Linguistics C<strong>on</strong>ference Papers. Lawrence, Kansas:<br />

Department of Linguistics, University of Kansas.<br />

Kiparsky, Paul. 1996. Allomorphy or morphoph<strong>on</strong>ology?. Pp. 13-31 in Rajendra Singh,<br />

ed. Trubetzkoy’s Orphan: Proceedings of the M<strong>on</strong>treal Roundtable<br />

‘Morphoph<strong>on</strong>ology: C<strong>on</strong>temporary Resp<strong>on</strong>ses’. Amsterdam: Benjamins.<br />

Kiparsky, Paul. 2000. Opacity and cyclicity. The Linguistic Review 17: 351-366.<br />

Kite, Suzanne and Stephen Wurm. 2004. The Duuŋidjawu Language of Southeast<br />

Queensland. Canberra: Pacific Linguistics.<br />

Klein, Thomas B. 2003. Syllable structure and lexical markedness in creole<br />

morphoph<strong>on</strong>ology: Determiner allomorphy in Haitian and elsewhere. Pp. 209-228<br />

in Ingo Plag, ed. The Ph<strong>on</strong>ology and Morphology of Creole Languages.<br />

Tübingen: Max Niemeyer.<br />

Koch, Harold J. 1980. Kaititj nominal inflecti<strong>on</strong>: Some comparative notes. Pp. 259-274<br />

in B. Rigsby and P. Sutt<strong>on</strong>, eds. Papers in Australian Linguistics 13: C<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong>s to<br />

Australian Linguistics. Australian Nati<strong>on</strong>al University: Pacific Linguistics Series A,<br />

Number 59.<br />

Kornfilt, Jaklin. 1997. Turkish. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong> and New York: Routledge.<br />

Kosch, Ingeborg M. 1998. Thoughts <strong>on</strong> suppleti<strong>on</strong> in Northern Sotho. South African<br />

Journal of African Languages 18.2: 33-40.<br />

Kramer, Ruth. 2005. Root and pattern morphology in Coptic. Ms., University of<br />

California, Santa Cruz.<br />

281


Kramer, Ruth. To appear. Root and pattern morphology in Coptic: Evidence for the root.<br />

In Chris Davis, Amy Rose Deal, and Youri Zabbal, eds. Proceedings of the 36th<br />

Annual Meeting of the North Eastern Linguistic Society. Amherst, MA:<br />

University of Massachusetts Graduate Linguistics Student Associati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

Krämer, Martin. 1998. A corresp<strong>on</strong>dence approach to vowel harm<strong>on</strong>y and disharm<strong>on</strong>y.<br />

Collaborative Research Centre 282 Working Paper Number 107, Heinrich-Heine-<br />

Universität Düsseldorf.<br />

Ladefoged, Peter. 1982. A Course in Ph<strong>on</strong>etics. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.<br />

Lapointe, Steven G. 1999. Stem selecti<strong>on</strong> and OT. Yearbook of Morphology 1999: 263-<br />

297.<br />

Lauriault, James. 1948. Alternating-mora timing in Shipibo. Internati<strong>on</strong>al Journal of<br />

American Linguistics 14: 22-24.<br />

Lazard, Gilbert and Louise Peltzer. 2000. Structure de la langue tahitienne. Paris:<br />

Peeters.<br />

le Bleis, Yves and Daniel Barreteau. 1987. Les extensi<strong>on</strong>s verbales en Mafa. Pp. 99-114<br />

in Herrmann Jungraithmayr and Henry Tourneux, eds. Etudes tchadiques: Classes et<br />

extensi<strong>on</strong>s verbales.<br />

Lee, Hansol H.B. 1989. Korean Grammar. New York: Oxford University Press.<br />

Leben, William. 1973. Suprasegmental Ph<strong>on</strong>ology. PhD. dissertati<strong>on</strong>, MIT.<br />

Lewis. Geoffrey L. 1967. Turkish Grammar. Oxford: Clarend<strong>on</strong> Press.<br />

Li, Bing. 1996. Tungusic Vowel Harm<strong>on</strong>y. The Hague: Holland Academic Graphics.<br />

Lieber, Rochelle. 1980. On the Organizati<strong>on</strong> of the Lexic<strong>on</strong>. PhD. dissertati<strong>on</strong>, MIT.<br />

Lindstrom, Lam<strong>on</strong>t and John Lynch. 1994. Kwamera. München: Lincom Europa.<br />

Lipkind, William. 1945. Winnebago Grammar. New York: King’s Crown Press.<br />

Mareš, František Václav. 1965. The Origin of the Slavic <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g> System and Its<br />

Development up to the End of Slavic Language Unity. Ann Arbor: Michigan Slavic<br />

Materials.<br />

Martin, Samuel E. 1954. Korean Morphoph<strong>on</strong>emics. William Dwight Whitney Linguistic<br />

Series. Baltimore: Linguistic Society of America.<br />

282


Martin, Samuel E. and Young-Sook C. Lee. 1964. Beginning Korean. New Haven,<br />

C<strong>on</strong>necticut: Yale University Press.<br />

Martinet, A. 1952. Langues à syllabes ouvertes: Le cas du slave commun. Zietschrift für<br />

Ph<strong>on</strong>etic und allgemeine Sprachwissenschaft 6: 145-163.<br />

Mascaró, Joan. 1996. External allomorphy and lexical representati<strong>on</strong>. Ms., Universitat<br />

Autònoma de Barcel<strong>on</strong>a.<br />

McCarthy, John J. 1986. OCP effects: Geminati<strong>on</strong> and antigeminati<strong>on</strong>. Linguistic Inquiry<br />

17: 207-263.<br />

McCarthy, John J. 2003. OT c<strong>on</strong>straints are categorical. Ph<strong>on</strong>ology 20: 75-138.<br />

McCarthy, John J. and Alan S. Prince. 1990. Foot and word in prosodic morphology: The<br />

Arabic broken plural. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 8.2: 209-283.<br />

McCarthy, John J. and Alan Prince. 1993a. Generalized Alignment. Yearbook of<br />

Morphology 1993: 79-153.<br />

McCarthy, John J. and Alan Prince. 1993b. Prosodic Morphology I: C<strong>on</strong>straint<br />

interacti<strong>on</strong> and satisfacti<strong>on</strong>. Ms., University of Massachusetts, Amherst and Rutgers<br />

University.<br />

McCarthy, John J. and Alan Prince. 1994. The Emergence of the Unmarked. Ms.,<br />

University of Massachusetts, Amherst, and Rutgers University.<br />

McCarthy, John J. and Alan Prince. 1995. Faithfulness and reduplicative identity. Pp.<br />

249-384 in Jill Beckman, Laura Dickey and Suzanne Urbanczyk, eds. University of<br />

Massachusetts Occasi<strong>on</strong>al Papers in Linguistics 18: Papers in Optimality Theory.<br />

Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts Graduate Linguistics Student<br />

Associati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

McCawley, James D. 1979. On the role of notati<strong>on</strong> in generative ph<strong>on</strong>ology. Pp. 204-<br />

216 in Adverbs, Vowels, and Other Objects of W<strong>on</strong>der. Chicago: University of<br />

Chicago Press.<br />

McFarland, Teresa. 2007. Free affix order in Filomeno Mata Tot<strong>on</strong>ac. Paper presented at<br />

the 2007 LSA Annual Meeting, Anaheim, California.<br />

McGregor, William. 1990. A Functi<strong>on</strong>al Grammar of Go<strong>on</strong>iyandi. Amsterdam: John<br />

Benjamins Publishing Company.<br />

Melnar, Lynette R. 2004. Caddo Verb Morphology. Lincoln, Nebraska: University of<br />

Nebraska Press.<br />

283


Mester, R. Armin. 1994. The quantitative trochee in Latin. Natural Language and<br />

Linguistic Theory 12: 1-61.<br />

Mohanan, K.P. 1986. The Theory of Lexical Ph<strong>on</strong>ology. Dordrecht: Reidel.<br />

Mürk, Harri William. 1997. A Handbook of Est<strong>on</strong>ian: Nouns, Adjectives, and Verbs.<br />

Bloomingt<strong>on</strong>, Indiana: Indiana University Research Institute for Inner Asian Studies.<br />

Nash, David. 1986. Topics in Warlpiri Grammar. New York: Garland Publishing, Inc.<br />

Németh, Gyula. 1962. Turkish Grammar. English translati<strong>on</strong> of the German original by<br />

T. Halasi-Kun. The Hague: Mout<strong>on</strong>.<br />

Newman, Stanley S. 1965. Zuni Grammar. University of New Mexico Publicati<strong>on</strong>s in<br />

Anthropology 14. Albuquerque: University of New Mexico Press.<br />

Nikiema, Emmanuel. 1999. De la variati<strong>on</strong> du déterminant /la/ dans les créoles haïtien et<br />

st-lucien. Lingua 107: 69-93.<br />

Noyer, Rolf. 1994. Mobile affixes in Huave: Optimality and morphological<br />

wellformedness. Pp. 67-82 in Eric Duncan, D<strong>on</strong>ka Farkas, and Philip Spaelti, eds.<br />

Proceedings of the Twelfth West Coast C<strong>on</strong>ference <strong>on</strong> Formal Linguistics. Stanford:<br />

CSLI.<br />

Oates, Lynette F. 1988. The Muruwari Language. Pacific Linguistics C-108. Canberra:<br />

Australian Nati<strong>on</strong>al University.<br />

Odden, David. 1993. Interacti<strong>on</strong> between modules in Lexical Ph<strong>on</strong>ology. Pp. 111-144 in<br />

Shar<strong>on</strong> Hargus and Ellen Kaisse, eds. Ph<strong>on</strong>etics and Ph<strong>on</strong>ology 4: Studies in Lexical<br />

Ph<strong>on</strong>ology. San Diego: Academic Press, Inc.<br />

Odden, David. 1996. The Ph<strong>on</strong>ology and Morphology of Kimatuumbi. Oxford: Clarend<strong>on</strong><br />

Press.<br />

Orgun, Cemil Orhan. 1996. Sign-Based Morphology and Ph<strong>on</strong>ology with Special<br />

Attenti<strong>on</strong> to Optimality Theory. PhD. dissertati<strong>on</strong>, UC Berkeley.<br />

Orgun, Cemil Orhan and R<strong>on</strong>ald Sprouse. 1999. From MParse to C<strong>on</strong>trol: Deriving<br />

ungrammaticality. Ph<strong>on</strong>ology 16: 191-224.<br />

Osburne, A. 1975. A Transformati<strong>on</strong>al Analysis of T<strong>on</strong>e in the Verb System of Zahao<br />

(Laizo) Chin. PhD. dissertati<strong>on</strong>, Cornell University.<br />

Oswalt, Robert L. 1960. A Kashaya Grammar (Southern Pomo). PhD. dissertati<strong>on</strong>, UC<br />

Berkeley.<br />

284


Parker, E.M. and R. J. Hayward. 1985. An Afar-English-French Dicti<strong>on</strong>ary (with<br />

Grammatical Notes in English). L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: School of Oriental and African Studies,<br />

University of L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>.<br />

Paster, Mary. 2001. What determines suffix ordering in Fula? Paper presented at the 32nd<br />

Annual C<strong>on</strong>ference <strong>on</strong> African Linguistics, UC Berkeley.<br />

Paster, Mary. 2004. Vowel height harm<strong>on</strong>y and blocking in Buchan Scots. Ph<strong>on</strong>ology<br />

21.3: 359-407.<br />

Paster, Mary. 2005a. Subcategorizati<strong>on</strong> vs. output optimizati<strong>on</strong> in syllable-counting<br />

allomorphy. Pp. 326-222 in John Alderete, Chung-Hye Han, and Alexei Kochetov,<br />

eds. Proceedings of the Twenty-Fourth West Coast C<strong>on</strong>ference <strong>on</strong> Formal<br />

Linguistics. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Proceedings Project.<br />

Paster, Mary. 2005b. Pulaar verbal extensi<strong>on</strong>s and ph<strong>on</strong>ologically driven affix order.<br />

Yearbook of Morphology 2005: 155-199.<br />

Paster, Mary. 2006. A survey of ph<strong>on</strong>ological affix order with special attenti<strong>on</strong> to Pulaar.<br />

Leah Bateman and Cherl<strong>on</strong> Ussery, eds. Proceedings of the 35th Annual Meeting of<br />

the North Eastern Linguistic Society: Volume 2: 491-506. Amherst, MA: University<br />

of Massachusetts Graduate Linguistics Student Associati<strong>on</strong>.<br />

Paster, Mary and Rosemary Beam de Azc<strong>on</strong>a. 2005. A ph<strong>on</strong>ological sketch of the<br />

Yucunany dialect of Mixtepec Mixtec. Pp. 61-76 in Proceedings of the Seventh<br />

Annual Workshop <strong>on</strong> American Indigenous Languages.<br />

Pater, Joe. 1999. Austr<strong>on</strong>esian nasal substituti<strong>on</strong> and other *NC̥ effects. Pp. 310-343 in<br />

Rene Kager, Harry van der Hulst, and Wim Z<strong>on</strong>neveld, eds. The Prosody-<br />

Morphology Interface. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Patz, Elizabeth. 1991. Djabugay. Pp. 245-347 in Robert M.W. Dix<strong>on</strong> and Barry J. Blake,<br />

eds. The Handbook of Australian Languages 4. Melbourne: Oxford University Press.<br />

Patz, Elizabeth. 2002. A Grammar of the Kuku Yalanji Language of North Queensland.<br />

Canberra: Pacific Linguistics.<br />

Payne, David L. 1981. The Ph<strong>on</strong>ology and Morphology of Axininca Campa. Dallas,<br />

Texas and Arlingt<strong>on</strong>, Texas: Summer Institute of Linguistics and University of Texas<br />

at Arlingt<strong>on</strong>.<br />

Pike, Eunice V. and Thomas Ibach. 1978. The ph<strong>on</strong>ology of the Mixtepec dialect of<br />

Mixtec. Pp. 271-285 in Mohammed Jazayery, Edgar C. Polomé, and Werner Winter,<br />

eds. Linguistic and Literary Studies in H<strong>on</strong>or of Archibald A. Hill, Volume 2:<br />

Descriptive Linguistics. The Hague: Mout<strong>on</strong>.<br />

Poser, William. 1985. There is no domain size parameter. GLOW Newsletter 14: 6-67.<br />

285


Prince, Alan. 1983. Relating to the grid. Linguistic Inquiry 14: 19-100.<br />

Prince, Alan and Paul Smolensky. 1993. Optimality Theory: C<strong>on</strong>straint Interacti<strong>on</strong> in<br />

Generative Grammar. Technical Report 2. New Brunswick, New Jersey: Rutgers<br />

Center for Cognitive Science, Rutgers University.<br />

Pulleyblank, Douglas. 1996. Neutral vowels in Optimality Theory: A comparis<strong>on</strong> of<br />

Yoruba and Wolof. Canadian Journal of Linguistics/Revue canadienne de<br />

linguistique 41.4: 295-347.<br />

Pulleyblank, Douglas. 2002. Harm<strong>on</strong>y drivers: No disagreement allowed. Pp. 249-267 in<br />

Julie Lars<strong>on</strong> and Mary Paster, eds. Proceedings of the Twenty-Eighth Annual<br />

Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society. Berkeley: Berkeley Linguistics Society.<br />

Radhakrishnan, R. 1981. The Nancowry Word: Ph<strong>on</strong>ology, Affixal Morphology, and<br />

Roots of a Nicobarese Language. Edm<strong>on</strong>t<strong>on</strong>, Alberta: Linguistic Research, Inc.<br />

Rice, Keren. 2000. Morpheme Order and Semantic Scope: Word Formati<strong>on</strong> in the<br />

Athapaskan Verb. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Riggs, S.R., ed. 1852. Grammar and Dicti<strong>on</strong>ary of the Dakota Language. New York:<br />

G.P. Putnam.<br />

Rose, Shar<strong>on</strong>. 2000a. Multiple corresp<strong>on</strong>dence in reduplicati<strong>on</strong>. Pp. 315-326 in M. Juge<br />

and J. Moxley, eds. Proceedings of the Twenty-Third Annual Meeting of the Berkeley<br />

Linguistics Society. Berkeley: Berkeley Linguistics Society.<br />

Rose, Shar<strong>on</strong>. 2000b. Epenthesis positi<strong>on</strong>ing and syllable c<strong>on</strong>tact in Chaha. Ph<strong>on</strong>ology<br />

17.3: 397-425.<br />

Rounds, Carol. 2001. Hungarian: An Essential Grammar. New York: Routledge.<br />

Sands, Kristina. 1996. The Ergative in Proto-Australian. München: LINCOM Europa.<br />

Schuh, Russell G. 1998. A Grammar of Miya. University of California Publicati<strong>on</strong>s in<br />

Linguistics 130. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.<br />

Schwarze, Christoph. 1999. Inflecti<strong>on</strong>al classes in Lexical Functi<strong>on</strong>al Morphology: Latin<br />

-sk- and its evoluti<strong>on</strong>. In Miriam Butt and Tracy Holloway King, eds. The<br />

Proceedings of the LFG ’99 C<strong>on</strong>ference. Stanford: CSLI.<br />

Selkirk, Elisabeth. 1982. The Syntax of Words. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.<br />

Selkirk, Elisabeth. 1984. Ph<strong>on</strong>ology and Syntax. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.<br />

286


Sezer, Engin. 1981. The k/Ø alternati<strong>on</strong> in Turkish. Pp. 354-382 in G.N. Clements, ed.<br />

Harvard Studies in Ph<strong>on</strong>ology. Bloomingt<strong>on</strong>: Indiana University Linguistics<br />

Club.<br />

Sharp, Janet Catherine. 2004. Nyangumarta: A Language of the Pilbara Regi<strong>on</strong> of<br />

Western Australia. Canberra: Pacific Linguistics.<br />

Shaw, Patricia A. 1980. Theoretical Issues in Dakota Ph<strong>on</strong>ology and Morphology. New<br />

York: Garland.<br />

Sibanda, Galen. 2004. Verbal Ph<strong>on</strong>ology and Morphology of Ndebele. PhD. dissertati<strong>on</strong>,<br />

UC Berkeley.<br />

Simps<strong>on</strong>, Jane and Margaret Withgott. 1986. Pr<strong>on</strong>ominal clitic clusters and templates.<br />

Syntax and Semantics 19: The Syntax of Pr<strong>on</strong>ominal Clitics: 149-174.<br />

Slocum, Marianna C. 1948. Tzeltal (Mayan) noun and verb morphology. Internati<strong>on</strong>al<br />

Journal of American Linguistics 14: 77-86.<br />

Sohn, H.M. 1975. Woleaian Reference Grammar. H<strong>on</strong>olulu: University Press of Hawaii.<br />

Sohn, H.M. and A.F. Tawerilmang. 1976. Woleaian-English Dicti<strong>on</strong>ary. H<strong>on</strong>olulu:<br />

University Press of Hawaii.<br />

Spagnolo, L. M. 1933. Bari Grammar. Ver<strong>on</strong>a, Italy: The Nigrizia Printing Press School.<br />

Speas, Margaret. 1990. Phrase Structure in Natural Language. Dordrecht: Kluwer.<br />

Steriade, D<strong>on</strong>ca. 1988. Reduplicati<strong>on</strong> and syllable transfer in Sanskrit. Ph<strong>on</strong>ology 5: 73-<br />

155.<br />

Stump, Gregory. 1992. On the theoretical status of positi<strong>on</strong> class restricti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong><br />

inflecti<strong>on</strong>al affixes. Yearbook of Morphology 1991: 211-241.<br />

Stump, Gregory. 1993. Positi<strong>on</strong> classes and morphological theory. Yearbook of<br />

Morphology 1992: 129-180.<br />

Terrill, Angela. 1998. Biri. München: LINCOM Europa.<br />

Thomps<strong>on</strong>, D.A. 1976. Kuuku Yaʔu. Pp. 329-331 in R.M.W. Dix<strong>on</strong>, ed. Grammatical<br />

Categories in Australian Languages. Canberra: Australian Institute of Aboriginal<br />

Studies.<br />

Timberlake, Alan. 2004. A Reference Grammar of Russian. Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press.<br />

287


Tranel, Bernard. 1996a. French liais<strong>on</strong> and elisi<strong>on</strong> revisited: A unified account within<br />

Optimality Theory. Pp. 433-455 in Claudia Parodi, Carlos Quicoli, Mario Saltarelli,<br />

and María-Luisa Zubizarreta, eds. Aspects of Romance Linguistics. Washingt<strong>on</strong>, DC:<br />

Georgetown University Press.<br />

Tranel, Bernard. 1996b. Excepti<strong>on</strong>ality in Optimality Theory and final c<strong>on</strong>s<strong>on</strong>ants in<br />

French. Pp. 275-291 in Karen Zag<strong>on</strong>a, ed. Grammatical Theory and Romance<br />

Languages. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins.<br />

Try<strong>on</strong>, Darrell T. 1970. C<strong>on</strong>versati<strong>on</strong>al Tahitian: An Introducti<strong>on</strong> to the Language of<br />

French Polynesia. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.<br />

Underhill, Robert. 1976. Turkish Grammar. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.<br />

Valentine, J. Randolph. 2001. Nishnaabemwin Reference Grammar. Tor<strong>on</strong>to: University<br />

of Tor<strong>on</strong>to Press.<br />

van Marle, J. 1985. On the Paradigmatic Dimensi<strong>on</strong> of Morphological Creativity.<br />

Dordrecht: Foris.<br />

van Marle, J. 1986. The Domain Hypothesis: The study of rival morphological processes.<br />

Linguistics 24: 601-627.<br />

van Wijk, Judith. 2002. The Dutch plural landscape. Linguistics in the Netherlands 2002:<br />

211-221.<br />

Vaux, Bert. 1998. The Ph<strong>on</strong>ology of Armenian. Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

Vaux, Bert. 2003. Syllabificati<strong>on</strong> in Armenian, Universal Grammar, and the Lexic<strong>on</strong>.<br />

Linguistic Inquiry 34.1: 91-125.<br />

Wade, Terence. 2002. Russian Grammar and Verbs. Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

Walsh Dickey, Laura. 1999. Syllable count and Tzeltal segmental allomorphy. Pp. 323-<br />

334 in John R. Rennis<strong>on</strong> and Klaus Kühnhammer, eds. Ph<strong>on</strong>ologica 1996:<br />

Syllables!?. The Hague: Thesus.<br />

Wats<strong>on</strong>, Janet C.E. 2002. The Ph<strong>on</strong>ology and Morphology of Arabic. Oxford: Oxford<br />

University Press.<br />

Werner, Roland. 1993. Tidn-Aal: A Study of Midob. Berlin: Dietrich Reimer Verlag.<br />

Wiering, Elisabeth, and Marinus Wiering. 1994. The Doyayo Language: Selected Studies.<br />

Arlingt<strong>on</strong>, Texas: SIL and University of Texas at Arlingt<strong>on</strong>.<br />

288


Wolf, Matthew and John J. McCarthy. To appear. Less than zero: Corresp<strong>on</strong>dence and<br />

the null output. In Curt Rice, ed. Modeling Ungrammaticality in Optimality Theory.<br />

L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Equinox.<br />

Wordick, F.J.F. 1982. The Yindjibarndi Language. Canberra, Australia: Pacific<br />

Linguistics.<br />

Yip, Moira. 2004. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Ph<strong>on</strong>ological</str<strong>on</strong>g> markedness and allomorph selecti<strong>on</strong> in Zahao. Language<br />

and Linguistics 5.4: 969-1001.<br />

Yu, Alan C.L. 2003. The Morphology and Ph<strong>on</strong>ology of Infixati<strong>on</strong>. PhD. dissertati<strong>on</strong>, UC<br />

Berkeley.<br />

Yu, Alan. In press. A Natural History of Infixati<strong>on</strong>. Oxford University Press.<br />

Zoll, Cheryl. 1996. Parsing Below the Segment in a C<strong>on</strong>straint Based Framework. PhD.<br />

dissertati<strong>on</strong>, UC Berkeley.<br />

Zoll, Cheryl. 2002. Clash-driven t<strong>on</strong>e mapping. MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 42:<br />

377-404. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Working Papers in Linguistics.<br />

Zwicky, Arnold. 1985. How to describe inflecti<strong>on</strong>. Pp. 372-386 in Mary Niepokuj, Mary<br />

VanClay, Vassiliki Nikiforidou, and Deborah Feder, eds. Proceedings of the Eleventh<br />

Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society. Berkeley: Berkeley Linguistics<br />

Society.<br />

Zwicky, Arnold M. 1986. The general case: Basic form versus default form. Pp. 305- 314<br />

in Vassiliki Nikifordou, Mary VanClay, Mary Niepokuj, and Deborah Feder, eds.<br />

Proceedings of the Twelfth Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society.<br />

Berkeley: Berkeley Linguistics Society.<br />

289


Appendix: Surveyed languages<br />

Note: references to languages in the text included what was deemed the most useful or relevant<br />

level of specificity in classificati<strong>on</strong>. Here, I list the phylum to which each language bel<strong>on</strong>gs, in<br />

order to facilitate an assessment of the range of languages surveyed. Linguistic affiliati<strong>on</strong>s are<br />

from Ethnologue (Gord<strong>on</strong> 2005).<br />

Abbreviati<strong>on</strong>s: AA = Afro-Asiatic; IE = Indo-European; MP = Malayo-Polynesian; NC = Niger-<br />

C<strong>on</strong>go; NS = Nilo-Saharan; PN = Pama-Nyungan.<br />

Language name Phylum Locati<strong>on</strong> Reference<br />

Armenian IE: Armenian Armenia And<strong>on</strong>ian 1999<br />

Axininca Campa Arawakan: Maipuran Peru Payne 1981<br />

Bari NS: Eastern Sudanic Sudan Spagnolo 1933<br />

Biak Austr<strong>on</strong>esian: MP New Guinea Booij 2005<br />

Bidjara Australian: PN Australia Breen 1976a<br />

Biri Australian: PN Australia Terrill 1998<br />

Caddo Caddoan: Southern Oklahoma Melnar 2004<br />

Chimariko Hokan: Northern Northwestern California C<strong>on</strong>athan 2002<br />

Coptic AA: Egyptian Egypt Kramer 2005<br />

Dakota Siouan: Siouan Northern United States Shaw 1980<br />

Proper<br />

Diyari Australian: PN Australia Austin 1981<br />

Dja:bugay Australian: PN Australia Patz 1991<br />

Dutch IE: Germanic Netherlands Booij 1997<br />

Duuŋidjawu Australian: PN Australia Kite and Wurm 2004<br />

Dyirbal Australian: PN Australia Dix<strong>on</strong> 1972<br />

English IE: Germanic United Kingdom Zwicky 1986<br />

Est<strong>on</strong>ian Uralic: Finnic Est<strong>on</strong>ia Mürk 1997<br />

Finnish Uralic: Finnic Finland Karlss<strong>on</strong> 1999<br />

Go<strong>on</strong>iyandi Australian: Bunaban Australia McGregor 1990<br />

Haitian Creole creole Haiti Hall 1953<br />

Hungarian Uralic: Finno-Ugric Hungary Rounds 2001<br />

Italian IE: Italic Italy Hall 1948<br />

Jivaro Jivaroan Ecuador de Maria 1918<br />

Kaititj Australian: PN Australia Koch 1980<br />

Kashaya Hokan: Northern Northern California Oswalt 1960<br />

Kimatuumbi NC: Atlantic-C<strong>on</strong>go Tanzania Odden 1996<br />

Korean isolate Korea Lee 1989<br />

Kuku Yalanji Australian: PN Australia Patz 2002<br />

Kuuku Yaʔu Australian: PN Australia Thomps<strong>on</strong> 1976<br />

Kwamera Austr<strong>on</strong>esian: MP Vanuatu Lindstrom and Lynch 1994<br />

Latin IE: Italic Vatican State Mester 1994<br />

Mafa AA: Chadic Camero<strong>on</strong> Le Bleis and Barreteau 1987<br />

Manchu Altaic: Tungus China Li 1996<br />

Maori Austr<strong>on</strong>esian: MP New Zealand Biggs 1961<br />

Martuthunira Australian: PN Australia Dench 1995<br />

290


Midob NS: Eastern Sudanic Sudan Werner 1993<br />

Mixtepec Mixtec Oto-Manguean: Mexico Paster and Beam de Azc<strong>on</strong>a 2005<br />

Mixtecan<br />

Miya AA: Chadic Nigeria Schuh 1998<br />

Moroccan Arabic AA: Semitic Morocco Harrell 1962<br />

Muruwari Australian: PN Australia Oates 1988<br />

Nancowry Austro-Asiatic: Nicobar Islands Radhakrishnan 1981<br />

M<strong>on</strong>-Khmer<br />

Ngiyambaa Australian: PN Australia D<strong>on</strong>alds<strong>on</strong> 1980<br />

Nhanda Australian: PN Australia Blevins 2001<br />

Nishnaabemwin Algic: Alg<strong>on</strong>quian Ontario Valentine 2001<br />

Northern Sotho NC: Atlantic-C<strong>on</strong>go South Africa Kosch 1998<br />

Nyangumarta Australian: PN Australia Sharp 2004: 117<br />

Qafar AA: Cushitic Ethiopia Parker and Hayward 1985<br />

Russian IE: Slavic Russia Timberlake 2004<br />

Saami Uralic: Sami Norway Dolbey 1997<br />

Sa’ani Arabic AA: Semitic Egypt Wats<strong>on</strong> 2002<br />

Shipibo Panoan: Peru Elías-Ulloa 2004<br />

North-Central<br />

Spanish IE: Italic Spain Kikuchi 2001<br />

Tahitian Austr<strong>on</strong>esian: MP French Polynesia Try<strong>on</strong> 1970<br />

Turkana NS: Eastern Sudanic Kenya Dimmendaal 1983<br />

Turkish Altaic: Turkic Turkey Lewis 1967<br />

Tzeltal Mayan: Mexico Slocum 1948<br />

Cholan-Tzeltalan<br />

Wangkumara Australian: PN Australia Breen 1976b<br />

Warlpiri Australian: PN Australia Nash 1986<br />

Warluwara Australian: PN Australia Breen 1976c<br />

Warrgamay Australian: PN Australia Dix<strong>on</strong> 1980<br />

Winnebago Siouan: Siouan Wisc<strong>on</strong>sin Lipkind 1945<br />

Proper<br />

Woleaian Austr<strong>on</strong>esian: MP Micr<strong>on</strong>esia Sohn 1975<br />

Yidiɲ Australian: PN Australia Dix<strong>on</strong> 1977<br />

Yindjibarndi Australian: PN Australia Wordick 1982<br />

Yingkarta Australian: PN Australia Dench 1998<br />

Zahao Sino-Tibetan: Burma Osburne 1975<br />

Tibeto-Burman<br />

Zuni isolate New Mexico Newman 1965<br />

291

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!